SET-THEORETIC CONSTRUCTIONS OF TWO-POINT SETS



Similar documents
Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part IV: Vector Spaces

x < y iff x < y, or x and y are incomparable and x χ(x,y) < y χ(x,y).

COFINAL MAXIMAL CHAINS IN THE TURING DEGREES

Continued Fractions and the Euclidean Algorithm

DEGREES OF ORDERS ON TORSION-FREE ABELIAN GROUPS

WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT?

MATH10212 Linear Algebra. Systems of Linear Equations. Definition. An n-dimensional vector is a row or a column of n numbers (or letters): a 1.

Lecture 4 DISCRETE SUBGROUPS OF THE ISOMETRY GROUP OF THE PLANE AND TILINGS

INTRODUCTORY SET THEORY

Basic Concepts of Point Set Topology Notes for OU course Math 4853 Spring 2011

IRREDUCIBLE OPERATOR SEMIGROUPS SUCH THAT AB AND BA ARE PROPORTIONAL. 1. Introduction

This asserts two sets are equal iff they have the same elements, that is, a set is determined by its elements.

Integer roots of quadratic and cubic polynomials with integer coefficients

The Banach-Tarski Paradox

1 Sets and Set Notation.

Ideal Class Group and Units

GROUPS ACTING ON A SET

The Ideal Class Group

3. Mathematical Induction

SOLUTIONS TO ASSIGNMENT 1 MATH 576

An example of a computable

Copyrighted Material. Chapter 1 DEGREE OF A CURVE

MODELS OF SET THEORY

Chapter 4, Arithmetic in F [x] Polynomial arithmetic and the division algorithm.

How To Know If A Domain Is Unique In An Octempo (Euclidean) Or Not (Ecl)

CHAPTER 7 GENERAL PROOF SYSTEMS

F. ABTAHI and M. ZARRIN. (Communicated by J. Goldstein)

DEGREES OF CATEGORICITY AND THE HYPERARITHMETIC HIERARCHY

There is no degree invariant half-jump

EMBEDDING COUNTABLE PARTIAL ORDERINGS IN THE DEGREES

Degrees that are not degrees of categoricity

11 Ideals Revisiting Z

This chapter is all about cardinality of sets. At first this looks like a

How To Understand The Theory Of Hyperreals

Surface bundles over S 1, the Thurston norm, and the Whitehead link

SMALL SKEW FIELDS CÉDRIC MILLIET

FACTORING IN QUADRATIC FIELDS. 1. Introduction. This is called a quadratic field and it has degree 2 over Q. Similarly, set

CHAPTER II THE LIMIT OF A SEQUENCE OF NUMBERS DEFINITION OF THE NUMBER e.

INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY

God created the integers and the rest is the work of man. (Leopold Kronecker, in an after-dinner speech at a conference, Berlin, 1886)

FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: QUOTIENT SPACES

Turing Degrees and Definability of the Jump. Theodore A. Slaman. University of California, Berkeley. CJuly, 2005

ABSTRACT. For example, circle orders are the containment orders of circles (actually disks) in the plane (see [8,9]).

Notes from February 11

How many numbers there are?

Cycles in a Graph Whose Lengths Differ by One or Two

ON SEQUENTIAL CONTINUITY OF COMPOSITION MAPPING. 0. Introduction

1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set.

PUTNAM TRAINING POLYNOMIALS. Exercises 1. Find a polynomial with integral coefficients whose zeros include

4.5 Linear Dependence and Linear Independence

1 VECTOR SPACES AND SUBSPACES

minimal polyonomial Example

CURVES WHOSE SECANT DEGREE IS ONE IN POSITIVE CHARACTERISTIC. 1. Introduction

On Integer Additive Set-Indexers of Graphs

4. Expanding dynamical systems

Properties of BMO functions whose reciprocals are also BMO

Factoring Cubic Polynomials

ON GALOIS REALIZATIONS OF THE 2-COVERABLE SYMMETRIC AND ALTERNATING GROUPS

CHAPTER SIX IRREDUCIBILITY AND FACTORIZATION 1. BASIC DIVISIBILITY THEORY

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 3. Spaces with special properties

Separation Properties for Locally Convex Cones

Primality - Factorization

ON FIBER DIAMETERS OF CONTINUOUS MAPS

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products

Some Polynomial Theorems. John Kennedy Mathematics Department Santa Monica College 1900 Pico Blvd. Santa Monica, CA

Global Properties of the Turing Degrees and the Turing Jump

How To Find Out How To Calculate A Premeasure On A Set Of Two-Dimensional Algebra

THE DIMENSION OF A VECTOR SPACE

MA651 Topology. Lecture 6. Separation Axioms.

1 = (a 0 + b 0 α) (a m 1 + b m 1 α) 2. for certain elements a 0,..., a m 1, b 0,..., b m 1 of F. Multiplying out, we obtain

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces

Prime Numbers and Irreducible Polynomials

FACTORING CERTAIN INFINITE ABELIAN GROUPS BY DISTORTED CYCLIC SUBSETS

Tilings of the sphere with right triangles III: the asymptotically obtuse families

Alex, I will take congruent numbers for one million dollars please

If A is divided by B the result is 2/3. If B is divided by C the result is 4/7. What is the result if A is divided by C?

Lecture Notes on Polynomials

ZORN S LEMMA AND SOME APPLICATIONS

ELLIPTIC CURVES AND LENSTRA S FACTORIZATION ALGORITHM

Best Monotone Degree Bounds for Various Graph Parameters

TOPOLOGY: THE JOURNEY INTO SEPARATION AXIOMS

4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS

ON THE COEFFICIENTS OF THE LINKING POLYNOMIAL

Labeling outerplanar graphs with maximum degree three

6 EXTENDING ALGEBRA. 6.0 Introduction. 6.1 The cubic equation. Objectives

Georg Cantor and Set Theory

FACTORING POLYNOMIALS IN THE RING OF FORMAL POWER SERIES OVER Z

DISINTEGRATION OF MEASURES

Math 55: Discrete Mathematics

CHAPTER 3. Methods of Proofs. 1. Logical Arguments and Formal Proofs

GENTLY KILLING S SPACES TODD EISWORTH, PETER NYIKOS, AND SAHARON SHELAH

P NP for the Reals with various Analytic Functions

CONTRIBUTIONS TO ZERO SUM PROBLEMS

SECTION 10-2 Mathematical Induction

OSTROWSKI FOR NUMBER FIELDS

THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF ALGEBRA VIA PROPER MAPS

Numerical Analysis Lecture Notes

SOME PROPERTIES OF FIBER PRODUCT PRESERVING BUNDLE FUNCTORS

MOP 2007 Black Group Integer Polynomials Yufei Zhao. Integer Polynomials. June 29, 2007 Yufei Zhao

LEARNING OBJECTIVES FOR THIS CHAPTER

Transcription:

SET-THEORETIC CONSTRUCTIONS OF TWO-POINT SETS BEN CHAD AND ROBIN KNIGHT AND ROLF SUABEDISSEN Abstract. A two-point set is a subset of the plane which meets every line in exactly two points. By working in models of set theory other than ZFC we demonstrate two new constructions of two-point sets. Our first construction shows that in ZFC + CH there exist two-point sets which are contained within the union of a countable collection of concentric circles. Our second construction shows that in certain models of ZF we can show the existence of two-point sets without explicitly invoking the Axiom of Choice. Mathematics subject classification 000: 03E35 54G99. Key words: two-point set continuum hypothesis axiom of choice. 1. Introduction Given a cardinal κ a subset of the plane is said to be a κ-point set if and only if it meets every line in exactly κ many points and is said to be a partial κ-point set if and only if it meets every line in at most κ many points. We are particularly interested in the case that κ = and we refer to such sets as two-point sets. The existence of two-point sets was first shown by Maurkiewic [8]. (A French translation is given in [9].) A two-point set is classically constructed via transfinite recursion making use of an arbitrary well-ordering of the collection of all lines in the plane. We will demonstrate two constructions of two-point sets which result by varying the use of this well-ordering. The first construction shows that working in ZFC+CH we can construct a two-point set which is contained in the union of a countable collection of concentric circles of unbounded radius. In general classical constructions of two-point sets can be thought of as starting with a c-point set and then refining it to a two-point set and so this construction is of interest because we obtain a two-point set by refining an ℵ 0 -point set. We achieve this development by being careful about the well-ordering of the collection of all lines that we choose to help us in our construction. The second construction shows that in ZF if we assume that the real line satisfies a certain number of properties we can construct a two-point set without explicitly invoking the Axiom of Choice. It is a question of Erdős as discussed by Mauldin [7] to determine if a two-point set can be a 1

BEN CHAD AND ROBIN KNIGHT AND ROLF SUABEDISSEN Borel set. It is known from work of Larman [6] and Baston and Bostock [1] that a two-point set cannot be an F σ set but we know little else about this problem. Since a Borel set can always be described by a countable Borel code and the known methods of constructing two-point sets use a transfinite recursion of length c it would appear that these existing techniques cannot possibly yield a two-point set which is guaranteed to be Borel. Accordingly new methods of constructing two-point sets are necessary which do not rely so explicitly on the Axiom of Choice. In our construction the assumptions that we will make about the real line are implied by and appear to be strictly weaker than the assumption that it is well-orderable. If it indeed turns out to be the case that our assumptions are equivalent in ZF to the real line being well-orderable our construction is still of interest since we construct a two-point set by dealing with collections of lines simultaneously rather than by dealing with lines sequentially. The proof of the following result is essentially that given by Maurkiewic and we include it for comparison. Theorem 1.1. There exists a two-point set. Proof. Note that we can always extend a given a partial two-point set with cardinality less than c to a partial two-point set which meets a given line in exactly two points. To construct a two-point set we enumerate the set of all lines in order type c and construct an increasing c-sequence of partial twopoint sets using the enumeration to ensure that the union of the members of the sequence is a two-point set. Throughout the remainder of this paper we use the variables α β δ and γ to range over ordinals and the variables κ and λ to range over (wellorderable) cardinals.. The existence of two-point sets contained in ℵ 0 -point sets Given a property P the proofs of the existence of P two-point sets previously found in mathematical literature classically proceed in the manner of Theorem 1.1 and consist of a recursion of length c which at each step requires a choice to be made from c many possibilities. It follows that theorems of the form There exists a two-point set with P which are proved in this way can be stated as theorems of the form There exist c two-point sets with P. Hence if there exists some property P (expressible in the language of set theory) such that the collection of P two-point sets has cardinality less than c then we cannot demonstrate that this is the case by constructing a P two-point set with our classical techniques. Isometry groups of two-point sets have been studied by Chad and Suabedissen. In [3] it was shown that any subgroup of S 1 of cardinality less than c is the isometry group of some two-point set and that there exist proper

SET-THEORETIC CONSTRUCTIONS OF TWO-POINT SETS 3 subgroups of S 1 of cardinality c which are the isometry group of some twopoint set. In [] it was shown that there exist proper subgroups of S 1 which are not the isometry group of any two-point set. Given G S 1 with coset representatives enumerated by g α : α < κ a two-point set X with isometry group G is of the form α<κ (r αg α G s α g α G) for some real-valued sequences r α : α < κ and s α : α < κ. (To see this note that X is a union of G orbits and the line spanned by the origin and g α meets X in exactly two points.) Hence if G is chosen to have countable index then there are at most c many two-point sets with isometry group G. Further if X is indeed a two-point set with such an isometry group then X is contained in a union of countably many circles. While it was tempting for the authors to conjecture that it is impossible for a two-point set to be contained in a union of countably many circles we will now demonstrate that this may possibly be the case. We now introduce some terminology. Let Y be an ℵ 0 -point set and let a b c Y be distinct. Then we say that x Y \ {a b c} is a focus point with respect to a b and c if and only if there is a line L and u v w L Y such that a x and u are collinear; as are b x and v; as are c x and w. Any line L witnessing that x is a focus point is called a screen. We note that if Y has at most countably many focus points then Y has at most countably many screens. For A R we let L(A) denote the set of all lines spanned by distinct points from A. Note that L(A) A + ℵ 0. Further for B R we let L(A B) denote the set of all lines spanned by a point from A and a (different) point from B. It is easily seen that if B A then L(A) = L(B) L(B A \ B) L(A \ B). Again let Y be an ℵ 0 -point set and let A R be infinite. We say that A is fat with respect to Y if and only if for all L L(A): (1) L Y A; and () {x Y : x is a focus point with respect to a triple in A Y } A; and (3) {L Y : L is a screen with respect to a triple in A Y } A. Lemma.1. Let Y be an ℵ 0 point set such that each triple of distinct points in Y has at most countably many focus points and let A R be such that A is countably infinite. Then there exists B R such that A B B is countably infinite and B is fat with respect to Y. Further B may be chosen to be minimal with respect to set inclusion. Proof. Let T 1 T and T 3 be transformations of P(R ) such that for all X R T 1 (X) = {L Y : L L(X)}

4 BEN CHAD AND ROBIN KNIGHT AND ROLF SUABEDISSEN T (X) = {x Y : x is a focus point with respect to a triple in X Y } T 3 (X) = {L Y : L is a screen with respect to a triple in X Y }. Let B n : n < ω be an increasing sequence defined for n < ω by B 0 = A and B n+1 = B n T 1 (B n ) T (B n ) T 3 (B n ) and let B = n<ω B n. Then it is easily verified that B is countably infinite that B is fat with respect to Y and that B is minimal. We now introduce our final pieces of terminology. For each A R and each partial two-point set X A we say that X is full with respect to A if and only if L(X) = L(A). We say that Z R is a finite extension of a partial two-point set X if and only if Z is a partial two-point set such that Z X and Z \ X < ℵ 0. Given an ℵ 0 -point set Y and a partial two-point set X Y we let P(X Y ) be the set {Z Y : Z is a finite extension of X} equipped with its partial order of reverse inclusion. Recall that given a partial order P a subset D of P is dense in P if and only if for every p P there is d D such that d p. Lemma.. Let Y be an ℵ 0 -point set let A R be fat with respect to Y and let X A be a partial two-point set such that X is full with respect to A. Then for all lines L {Z P(X Y ) : L Z = } is dense in P(X Y ). Proof. Let L be a line and let W P(X Y ) be such that L W <. Then L L(A) for otherwise L L(X) L(W ). Suppose that there does not exist a finite extension Z Y of W such that L L(Z). Then every point of L Y except perhaps one belongs to a member of L(W ). We will show that each of ( ) ( ) ( ) L Y L(X) L Y L(X W \ X) L Y L(W \ X) is finite which is then clearly a contradiction. Suppose that there exist distinct x 1 x L Y ( L(X)). Then x 1 L 1 and x L for some L 1 L L(X) = L(A) and so by fatness both x 1 and x belong to A whence by fullness we obtain the contradiction that L L(X). Now L(X W \ X) = w W \X L(X {w}) and it is easily seen that each L Y L(X {w}) is at most a pair set otherwise L is a screen with respect to a triple in X A Y. Since W \ X is finite it follows that L Y ( L(W \ X)) is finite. Since L(W \ X) is finite it is obvious that L Y ( L(W \ X)) is finite. We are now in a position to prove the first of our two main results. Our proof is similar to that of Theorem 1.1 which treats lines sequentially the

SET-THEORETIC CONSTRUCTIONS OF TWO-POINT SETS 5 main difference being that we do not trust an arbitrary well-ordering of the collection of all lines to be sufficient for our purposes. Intuitively extending a countable partial two-point set X to meet some countable collection K of lines in exactly two points may create a situation where there exist lines which our new partial two-point set cannot be extended to (within our given ℵ 0 -point set). The preceding lemmas allow us to identify the family K of lines which may be in future danger of witnessing this problem and since K is also countable instead of extending X to meet all members of K in exactly two points we extend it to meet all members of K K in exactly two points. Theorem.3 (ZFC + CH). Let Y be an ℵ 0 point set such that each triple of distinct points in Y has at most countably many focus points. Then Y contains a two-point set. Proof. By applying Lemma.1 there exists a sequence A α : α < c of increasing countable sets which are fat with respect to Y and such that α<c A α = R. We will construct an increasing sequence {X α : α < c} of partial two-point sets such that each β α X β is a countable set which is full with respect to A α and α<c X α is a two-point set. Suppose that the partial sequence X β : β < α has been chosen. Then L(A α ) is countable and so by Lemma. and the Rasiowa-Sikorski Lemma [5] there exists a ) filter F in P( β<α X β Y such that for all L L(A α ) there exists F F such that L L(F ). Hence letting X α = ( F) A α we have a countable partial two-point set which extends β<α X β and is full with respect to A α. Now letting the X α be chosen for all α < c we see that α<c X α is a two-point set contained in Y. 3. The existence of two-point sets in a union of countably many concentric circles We now show that a union of countably many concentric circles of unbounded radii consistently contains two-point sets. Let S 1 denote the unit circle in C and for all α β γ C and all r α r β r γ R + let E( α β γ r α r β r γ ) denote the (formal) expression r α r β γ ( α β) + rβ r γ α ( β γ) + rγ r α β ( γ α) which is derived from writing down the length of the vector product ( α γ ) ( β γ ) where the complex numbers are thought of as being vectors in the plane. Note that for all α β γ C \ {0} it can be seen that α β and γ are

6 BEN CHAD AND ROBIN KNIGHT AND ROLF SUABEDISSEN collinear over R if and only if ( ) α E α β β γ γ α β γ = 0. Further for all α β γ C and all r α r β r γ R + it can be seen that α α /r α β β /r β γ γ /r γ C are collinear over C if and only if E( α β γ r α r β r γ ) = 0. r a r b r c r x r u r v r w R + and all a b c x u v w C let φ( a b c x u v w r a r b r c r x r u r v r w ) For all be a sentence which is true if and only if each of E( a x u r a r x r u ) E( b x v r b r x r v ) E( c x w r c r r w ) and E( u v w r u r v r w ) are equal to ero. Lemma 3.1. Let r a r b r c r x r u r v r w R + let a b c S 1 be such that r a a r b b r c c C are distinct let S be the set { x S 1 : u v w S 1 φ( a b c x u v w r a r b r c r x r u r v r w ) } and let T be the set { x C: u v w C φ( a b c x u v w r a r b r c r x r u r v r w )}. If S is uncountable then T = C. Proof. For each x C we consider E( a x u r a r x r u ) to be a polynomial in u which is non-trivial when x r a a /r x. By choosing one of finitely many branch cuts each of u v w can be viewed as complex differentiable functions of x. Supposing that S is uncountable let { S ra a = S \ r b b r } c c r x r x r x which is uncountable. It can then be seen that some choice of branches takes the value ero uncountably often on S and for this choice we substitute u v w as functions of x into E( u v w r u r v r w ). This gives us a complex differentiable function of x except on perhaps the branch cuts. By choosing an appropriate branch cut and applying the Identity Theorem the result then follows. For each r > 0 let C r denote the circle in C of radius r and centered at the origin. Lemma 3.. Let a b c C \ {0} be distinct let r x r u r v r w R + and let S be the set of all x C rx such that there exists u C ru v C rv and w C rw with the property that ( a φ a b b c c x x u u v v w ) a b c x u v w. w

SET-THEORETIC CONSTRUCTIONS OF TWO-POINT SETS 7 If S is uncountable then a b and c are collinear. Proof. Suppose that S is uncountable. We write r α = α and α = α/r α for α = a b c. By elementary algebra we can show that there exists x C such that a a /r a b b /r b x x /r x C (1) are collinear over C. Using Lemma 3.1 let u v w C be such that () (3) (4) (5) E( a x u r a r x r u ) = 0 E( b x v r b r x r v ) = 0 E( c x w r c r x r w ) = 0 E( u v w r u r v r w ) = 0. Using (1) () and (3) we add u u /r u and v v /r v to the list of collinear points in (1) then using (4) we add w w /r w to the list and finally using (3) we add c c /r c to the list. Thus E( a b c r a r b r c ) = 0 giving that a b and c are collinear over R. It is now easily seen that: Lemma 3.3. Let C be a collection of countably many concentric circles of unbounded radii and let a b c C be distinct. Then there are only countably many focus points with respect to a b and c. Theorem 3.4 (ZFC + CH). Let C be a collection of countably many concentric circles of unbounded radii. Then C contains a two-point set. 4. A non-sequential construction of a two-point set Working in a certain model of ZF we will now construct a two-point set without explicitly invoking the Axiom of Choice. We achieve this by changing the strictly sequential nature of the classical construction and instead of dealing with lines one-by-one we deal with collections of lines simultaneously. We start with a technical lemma. Lemma 4.1. Let L 1 and L be distinct lines and let a R \ (L 1 L ). Then there are at most twenty-two r > 0 such that there exist b L 1 \ L and c L \ L 1 having the properties that a b and c are collinear and b = c = r. Proof. For some r > 0 consider the circle C = {x y R : x + y = r }. Given x 0 R and a line of the form L = {x y R : x = x 0 } the members of C L (if they exist) are of the form x 0 ± r x 0

8 BEN CHAD AND ROBIN KNIGHT AND ROLF SUABEDISSEN and given m b R and a line of the form L = {x y R : y = mx + b} the members of C L (if they exist) are of the form mb ± (m + 1)r b b ± m (m + 1)r b. m + 1 m + 1 Suppose that r b and c are as in the statement of the lemma. By applying a rotation to our system we may assume that L 1 is a vertical line with parameter x 1 R. We consider two cases depending on the form of L. Case 1: L = {x y R : x = x } for some x R. In this case ± r x 1 a () = ± r x a () x 1 a (1) x a (1) and by repeated squaring to eliminate the radicals in this equality we obtain a polynomial equation in r whose highest formal power is 4. If the coefficient of r 4 vanishes then the coefficient of r does not vanish and so the polynomial is non-trivial. Since the polynomial is of degree at most four r can be only one of four possibilities. Case : L = {x y R : y = mx + b} for some m b R. If the line spanned by a b and c is vertical then we can argue that ( ) a (1) + = 0 r m + 1 b (m + 1) mb m + 1 This represents a non-trivial quadratic equation in r and so r can be only one of two possibilities. Otherwise we have that ± r x 1 a () = b ± m (m + 1)r b a () (m + 1) x 1 a (1) mb ± (m + 1)r b a (1) (m + 1) If we rationalise the denominator of the value on the right-hand side of this expression make (r x 1)/(x 1 a (1) ) the subject and multiply both sides of the resulting equality by (m + 1)r b ( mb a (1) (m + 1)) then the left-hand side is a rational function in r with the coefficient of r 4 being (m + 1)/ ( x 1 a (1)) 0 and the right-hand side is a rational function in r with no occurrences of r 4. By repeated squaring to eliminate the radicals in this equality we obtain a polynomial in r of degree 16 with coefficient of r 16 being (m + 1)/ ( x 1 a (1)) 0 and so r can be only one of sixteen possibilities. We are now in a position to demonstrate our construction. It is hoped the axioms required for this construction may be found to be true in some model of ZF + AC(R) but as we will later note they are certainly true in some models of ZFC and can be proved from ZFC + CH.

SET-THEORETIC CONSTRUCTIONS OF TWO-POINT SETS 9 Theorem 4. (ZF). Suppose that there exists a well-orderable cardinal κ such that: (1) κ + is regular; and () R can be written as the union of a well-orderable and increasing collection of sets with cardinality κ; and (3) R contains a well-orderable set of cardinality κ +. Then there exists a two-point set. Proof. By condition () there exists an increasing sequence A α : α < λ of subsets of R where each A α is of cardinality κ and λ is a well-orderable cardinal less than or equal to κ + and such that R = α<λ A α. By condition (3) there exists an injective sequence x α : α < κ + on R. By applying suitable transformations we will assume that each x α is positive and that for all M > 0 {α < κ + : x α > M} is of cardinality κ +. Let L α : α < λ be an increasing sequence such that α<λ L α is the collection of all lines in R where for all α < λ L α = κ and L α+1 \ L α. We will construct our two-point set as an increasing union α<λ X α where for each α < λ X α is a partial two-point set of cardinality κ which meets every member of L α in exactly two points. Suppose that for some α < λ we have constructed the partial sequence X β : β < α. We now show how to extend β<α X β to a partial two-point set Y α where Y α \ β<α X β contains exactly one point on each member of L α which does not meet β<α X β in two points. Letting On denote the class of all ordinals we will achieve this by constructing an increasing term X αβ : β On and a decreasing term L αβ : β On both consisting of sets of cardinality at most κ. Let X α0 = β<α X β L α0 = { L L α : } X β meets L in fewer than two points. β<α Suppose that for some β On \ {0} we have chosen X αγ : γ < β and L αγ : γ < β. If γ<β L αγ = then we set X αβ = γ<β X αγ and L αβ =. Otherwise let { L αβ = L ( ) } L αγ : X γ L =. γ<β γ<β X αγ \ γ<α Given a partial two-point set P recall from Section that L(P ) denotes the set of lines meeting P in exactly two points. Note that if P contains at least two points then P L(P ). Let φ(l δ) be a sentence such that for L L αβ and δ < κ + φ(l δ) is true if and only if:

10 BEN CHAD AND ROBIN KNIGHT AND ROLF SUABEDISSEN there exists b L \ ( ) ( )) L( γ<β X αγ γ<α L γ \ {L} such that b = x δ and for all a and c where a γ<β X αγ and K γ<β L αγ \ {L} and c K and c = x δ the distinct points a b and c are not collinear. Now for all L L αβ the set {δ < κ + : φ(l δ)} is non-empty since: (1) {δ < κ + : L meets the circle of radius x δ } = κ + ; and () γ<β X αγ and γ<β L αγ \ {L} are of cardinality at most κ and for all a γ<β X αγ and all K γ<β L αγ \ {L} there are at most twenty-two δ such that we can find b L and c K with the properties that a b and c are collinear and b = c = x δ ; and ) ( ) (3) L( γ<β X αγ γ<α L γ \ {L} is of cardinality at most κ and does not contain L. (Note that in clause () we rely on the fact that from ZF we may prove the existence of a choice function on finite subsets of the plane.) Let f : L αβ κ + be the function defined for L L αβ by f(l) = min { δ < κ + : φ(l δ) } let δ = min {f(l): L L αβ } and let X αβ be chosen to enlarge γ<β X αγ by selecting one point on each L such that f(l) = δ. We can make such a selection without the aid of the Axiom of Choice since we will only choose points with norm x δ and we can deterministically choose between two points on a line of norm x δ. Clearly X αβ is of cardinality at most κ and we now verify that it is a partial two-point set. Let L be any line. If L does not meet γ<β X αγ then by selecting points in a (fixed) circle we have ensured that X αβ meets L in at most two points and if L meets γ<β X αγ in exactly one (resp. two) point(s) then condition () (resp. (3)) above ensures that X αβ meets L in at most two points. Consider the mapping g : κ + P(L α ) defined for β < κ + by g(β) = L αβ \ L αβ+1. Noting that g is a disjointification of a decreasing sequence of subsets of L α it must eventually take the constant value otherwise g is an injection from κ + into a partition of β<κ g(β) L + α which is a contradiction. Hence we set Y α = β<α X αβ which is an extension of β<α X β meeting every member of L α in exactly one additional point. We now repeat the above process one more extending β<α X β Y α instead of β<α X β to obtain a partial two-point set X α which meets every member of L α in exactly two points. By working in ZFC and taking κ = ℵ 0 we see that: Theorem 4.3 (ZFC + CH). There exists a two-point set.

SET-THEORETIC CONSTRUCTIONS OF TWO-POINT SETS 11 In comparison to the construction given in Sections and 3 this construction also refines the union of some collection of concentric circles to a two-point set and we have obtained its non-sequential nature at the price of making our collection of circles uncountable. This proof was originally developed with the hope that it could be made to work in a model of ZF where the reals can be written as a countable union of countable sets. The standard model of ZF where the reals have this property is due to Fefferman and Lévy and is described by Cohen [4]; in the Fefferman-Lévy model the reals do not contain an uncountable well-ordered set. In response to private communication with the authors Miller [10] has shown in that in any model of ZF where the reals are a countable union of countable sets the reals do not contain an uncountable well-ordering and also that by using the method of forcing one can find models of ZF where the reals cannot be well-ordered but which contain two-point sets. References [1] V. J. Baston and F. A. Bostock. On a theorem of Larman. J. London Math. Soc. () 5:715 718 197. [] Ben Chad and Rolf Suabedissen. On affine groups admitting invariant two-point sets. Manuscript http://people.maths.ox.ac.uk/chad 008. [3] Ben Chad and Rolf Suabedissen. Symmetries of two-point sets. Topol. Appl. 155:113 10 008. [4] Paul J. Cohen. Set theory and the continuum hypothesis. W. A. Benjamin Inc. New York-Amsterdam 1966. [5] Kenneth Kunen. Set theory volume 10 of Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics. North-Holland Publishing Co. Amsterdam 1983. [6] D. G. Larman. A problem of incidence. J. London Math. Soc. 43:407 409 1968. [7] R. Daniel Mauldin. Problems in topology arising from analysis. In Open problems in topology pages 617 69. North-Holland Amsterdam 1990. [8] S. Maurkiewic. O pewnej mnogości plaskiej która ma każda prosta dwa i tylko dwa punkty wspólne. C. R. Varsovie 7:38 384 1914. [9] Stefan Maurkiewic. Travaux de topologie et ses applications. Comité de rédaction: K. Borsuk R. Engelking B. Knaster K. Kuratowski J. Loś R. Sikorski. Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe-Éditions Scientifiques de Pologne Warsaw 1969. [10] Arnold W. Miller The axiom of choice and two-point sets in the plane. Manuscript http://www.math.wisc.edu/ miller/res 008. Ben Chad St Edmund Hall Oxford OX1 4AR UK. Robin Knight Worcester College Oxford OX1 UK. Rolf Suabedissen Lady Margaret Hall Oxford OX 6QA UK.