4. CLASSES OF RINGS 4.1. Classes of Rings class operator A-closed Example 1: product Example 2:



Similar documents
Chapter 4, Arithmetic in F [x] Polynomial arithmetic and the division algorithm.

Chapter 13: Basic ring theory

Mathematics for Computer Science/Software Engineering. Notes for the course MSM1F3 Dr. R. A. Wilson

11 Ideals Revisiting Z

ADDITIVE GROUPS OF RINGS WITH IDENTITY

it is easy to see that α = a

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces

EXERCISES FOR THE COURSE MATH 570, FALL 2010

How To Prove The Dirichlet Unit Theorem

1 Homework 1. [p 0 q i+j p i 1 q j+1 ] + [p i q j ] + [p i+1 q j p i+j q 0 ]

(a) Write each of p and q as a polynomial in x with coefficients in Z[y, z]. deg(p) = 7 deg(q) = 9

3. Prime and maximal ideals Definitions and Examples.

Quotient Rings and Field Extensions

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products

FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 22

So let us begin our quest to find the holy grail of real analysis.

MA651 Topology. Lecture 6. Separation Axioms.

GROUPS ACTING ON A SET

COMMUTATIVE RINGS. Definition: A domain is a commutative ring R that satisfies the cancellation law for multiplication:

26 Ideals and Quotient Rings

TOPOLOGY: THE JOURNEY INTO SEPARATION AXIOMS

I. GROUPS: BASIC DEFINITIONS AND EXAMPLES

Group Theory. Contents

Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part IV: Vector Spaces

Chapter 7: Products and quotients

ZORN S LEMMA AND SOME APPLICATIONS

DEGREES OF ORDERS ON TORSION-FREE ABELIAN GROUPS

Solutions to TOPICS IN ALGEBRA I.N. HERSTEIN. Part II: Group Theory

INTRODUCTORY SET THEORY

2. Let H and K be subgroups of a group G. Show that H K G if and only if H K or K H.

Unique Factorization

The Division Algorithm for Polynomials Handout Monday March 5, 2012

4. FIRST STEPS IN THE THEORY 4.1. A

Elementary Number Theory and Methods of Proof. CSE 215, Foundations of Computer Science Stony Brook University

SUBGROUPS OF CYCLIC GROUPS. 1. Introduction In a group G, we denote the (cyclic) group of powers of some g G by

SOLUTIONS TO ASSIGNMENT 1 MATH 576

This chapter is all about cardinality of sets. At first this looks like a

Algebraic Structures II

FACTORING IN QUADRATIC FIELDS. 1. Introduction. This is called a quadratic field and it has degree 2 over Q. Similarly, set

G = G 0 > G 1 > > G k = {e}

WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT?

1 if 1 x 0 1 if 0 x 1

IRREDUCIBLE OPERATOR SEMIGROUPS SUCH THAT AB AND BA ARE PROPORTIONAL. 1. Introduction

7. Some irreducible polynomials

Module MA3411: Abstract Algebra Galois Theory Appendix Michaelmas Term 2013

MATH 304 Linear Algebra Lecture 9: Subspaces of vector spaces (continued). Span. Spanning set.

Mathematical Induction. Mary Barnes Sue Gordon

1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set.

(0, 0) : order 1; (0, 1) : order 4; (0, 2) : order 2; (0, 3) : order 4; (1, 0) : order 2; (1, 1) : order 4; (1, 2) : order 2; (1, 3) : order 4.

Linear Algebra I. Ronald van Luijk, 2012

CHAPTER 7 GENERAL PROOF SYSTEMS

RINGS WITH A POLYNOMIAL IDENTITY

4.1 Modules, Homomorphisms, and Exact Sequences

Introduction to Modern Algebra

GROUP ALGEBRAS. ANDREI YAFAEV

3 1. Note that all cubes solve it; therefore, there are no more

1 = (a 0 + b 0 α) (a m 1 + b m 1 α) 2. for certain elements a 0,..., a m 1, b 0,..., b m 1 of F. Multiplying out, we obtain

POLYNOMIAL RINGS AND UNIQUE FACTORIZATION DOMAINS

Factoring of Prime Ideals in Extensions

a 11 x 1 + a 12 x a 1n x n = b 1 a 21 x 1 + a 22 x a 2n x n = b 2.

3. INNER PRODUCT SPACES

Continued Fractions and the Euclidean Algorithm

U.C. Berkeley CS276: Cryptography Handout 0.1 Luca Trevisan January, Notes on Algebra

1 VECTOR SPACES AND SUBSPACES

Dedekind s forgotten axiom and why we should teach it (and why we shouldn t teach mathematical induction in our calculus classes)

Introduction to Finite Fields (cont.)

The Banach-Tarski Paradox

FACTORING CERTAIN INFINITE ABELIAN GROUPS BY DISTORTED CYCLIC SUBSETS

Non-unique factorization of polynomials over residue class rings of the integers

Factoring Polynomials

Elements of Abstract Group Theory

Galois representations with open image

Irreducibility criteria for compositions and multiplicative convolutions of polynomials with integer coefficients

6 EXTENDING ALGEBRA. 6.0 Introduction. 6.1 The cubic equation. Objectives

Factorization in Polynomial Rings

Revised Version of Chapter 23. We learned long ago how to solve linear congruences. ax c (mod m)

6. Fields I. 1. Adjoining things

SMALL SKEW FIELDS CÉDRIC MILLIET

3. Mathematical Induction

MOP 2007 Black Group Integer Polynomials Yufei Zhao. Integer Polynomials. June 29, 2007 Yufei Zhao

Solutions to In-Class Problems Week 4, Mon.

PUTNAM TRAINING POLYNOMIALS. Exercises 1. Find a polynomial with integral coefficients whose zeros include

An Innocent Investigation

Row Ideals and Fibers of Morphisms

WRITING PROOFS. Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology

A CONSTRUCTION OF THE UNIVERSAL COVER AS A FIBER BUNDLE

Commutative Algebra Notes Introduction to Commutative Algebra Atiyah & Macdonald

Modern Algebra Lecture Notes: Rings and fields set 4 (Revision 2)

How To Know If A Domain Is Unique In An Octempo (Euclidean) Or Not (Ecl)

If A is divided by B the result is 2/3. If B is divided by C the result is 4/7. What is the result if A is divided by C?

A number field is a field of finite degree over Q. By the Primitive Element Theorem, any number

Homework until Test #2

1 Sets and Set Notation.

Vector and Matrix Norms

Undergraduate Notes in Mathematics. Arkansas Tech University Department of Mathematics

Polynomial Invariants

r + s = i + j (q + t)n; 2 rs = ij (qj + ti)n + qtn.

Galois Theory III Splitting fields.

CHAPTER 3. Methods of Proofs. 1. Logical Arguments and Formal Proofs

Introduction to Algebraic Geometry. Bézout s Theorem and Inflection Points

Transcription:

4. CLASSES OF RINGS 4.1. Classes of Rings Normally we associate, with any property, a set of objects that satisfy that property. But problems can arise when we allow sets to be elements of larger sets in an uncontrolled way. For example the Russell Paradox comes from considering the set S = {x x x} and asking whether S S. Constructions such as the set of all sets are just not on, and if we were pursuing axiomatic set theory we d have to lay down certain axioms to restrict which properties are allowed to give rise to a set. But, we re doing ring theory and we want to turn adjectives that describe properties of rings into nouns. We use the word class in place of set to avoid these logical problems. Now it s not the fact that we re using a different word that avoids logical difficulties. It s the fact that, while sets are allowed to be elements of other sets, classes are not. So we ll talk about the class of all rings, the class of all nilpotent rings etc. The only assumption that we make is that if a certain ring belongs to a class, all isomorphic copies belong to it as well. In other words, in this context, we consider all rings isomorphic to a single one as being identical. We re not concerned with the nature of the underlying set, but rather the structure of the ring. As well as having a rich supply of classes to play with we want to consider certain recipes for obtaining a new class from a given one. We define these as class operators. Essentially they re functions on the class of all classes of all rings, but as we ve said, classes are not allowed to be considered as elements of other classes. So a class operator is not to be considered as a set of ordered pairs, or even a class of ordered pairs it s simply a rule that associates with each class X a certain class fx. We shall write operators on the left but avoid the usual f(x) notation as a way of reminding ourselves that these operators are not exactly functions in the usual sense in set theory. A class operator A is a rule that creates a ring class AX from a class X. If a ring R belongs to a class X we say that R is an X-ring. If AX X (subclass being defined in exactly the same way as subset) we say that X is A-closed. Example 1: We define the class operator S by stating that a ring is in SX if it is a subring of an X-ring. If N denotes the class of all nil rings, N is S-closed is just shorthand for the statement every subring of a nil ring is a nil ring. Another construct that produces new classes out of existing ones is the product of classes. We define the product of class operators by defining (AB)X = A(BX). Example 2: If QX is defined as the class of all quotients of X-rings then (SQ)X would become the class of all rings that are subrings of quotients of X-rings, while (QS)X would be all quotients of subrings of X-rings. Multiplication of class operators is clearly associative and, as is typical, when we define any sort of associative product, we can define powers. We define A 0 X = X; A 2 X = A(AX) and so on. Moreover we define A X to be the union of the A n X. 19

Examples 3: Here are a few classes of rings: F = class of finite rings; C = class of commutative rings; T = class of torsion rings (every element having finite additive order); D = class of all integral domains. Here are a few class operators: QX = quotients of X-rings; X = rings that are the sum of an ideal and a subring, each of which is an X-ring; UX = unions of ascending chains of X ideals of some ring; PX = rings R with an ideal I such that both I and R/I are X -rings. D isn t closed under P, Q or. Is it U-closed? C is closed under Q, U. But it is not closed under P (or as we say, not poly-closed ). For example if R = * * 0 *, meaning the set of all matrices of the form a b 0 d and I = 0 * 0 0, then I is an ideal of R. But, although both I and R/I are commutative rings, R is not. 0 * * 0 0 * Nor is C -closed. For example 0 0 0 and 0 0 * are commutative ideals yet their sum, 0 0 0 0 0 0 * * * 0 * * is not commutative. 0 0 * F is closed under Q,, P, but not U. Consider the infinite restricted direct sum of countably many finite rings. T is closed under Q,, U and P. The first three of these closure properties are obvious. We can show that T is poly-closed as follows. Suppose that R/I and I are torsion rings and r R. Then nr I for some n > 0. Hence (mn)r = m(nr) = 0 for some m > 0. Theorem 1: Closure under both P and Q implies -closure. Proof: Suppose I, J X with J a 2-sided ideal of R. Then (I + J)/J I/(I J) X and hence I + J X. 4.2. Zorn s Lemma The rings we re interested in are infinite and infinite sets can have some strange properties. Given a certain property we want to find the largest ideal that has that property. But such a largest might not exist. One reason why a set fails to have a largest is because there may be more than one possible candidate. For example we might ask which proper subspace of R 3 is largest. There are plenty of 2-dimensional subspaces but none contains any of the others. The other, and more subtle reason why a set may not have a largest is that there may be larger and larger elements, but no largest. For example there s no largest real number x for which x 2 < 2. We shall focus on the second problem. This will take us into the rarefied world of Axiomatic Set Theory where we discuss Zorn s Lemma. It isn t our role here to give a complete account of the necessary set theory, but, before we start using Zorn s Lemma, we need some discussion as to its logical status. 20

A partially-ordered set is a set X, together with a relation, that we shall denote by (though keep in mind that it may not bear any relation to any ordering we ve ever met). But, like ordinary less-than-or-equals we do insist that it have the following three properties: (i) x x for all x X (the reflexive property); (ii) if x y and y x then x = y (the anti-symmetric property); (iii) if x y and y z then x x (the transitive property). An example of such an ordering is that of subset of. Now notice that subset of fails to have a fourth property that we expect of ordinary : (iv) for all x, y X either x y or y x. We can easily have subsets where neither is a subset of the other. This fourth property is not required for a set to be a partial ordering. But if it does hold we say that the set is totally ordered, or simply that the set is a chain. By analogy with ordinary of numbers we define, < and >. If X is a partially ordered set, and S X then b X is an upper bound for S if x b for all x S. There is no need for the upper bound to be in the set, but if it is it is called a greatest element. A set may not have a greatest element, but it may have maximal elements. These are elements where nothing in the subset is bigger. A maximal element of S is thus an element m S such that if x m for some x S then x = m. Finally we can combine a couple of these together and talk of a least upper bound. Similarly we define lower bound, least element, minimal element and greatest lower bound. Example 4: Consider the set {A, B, C, D, E, F, G} where the ordering is described by the following diagram (x y if and only if you can get from x to y in the diagram by a path consisting of one or more edges, each traversed in an upwards direction). F G E C D Let S = {B, C, D}. Then E and G are upper bounds for S, with E the least upper bound. But S has no largest element, though C, D are maximal elements. S has a least element, B and this is the only minimal element. A, B are both lower bounds, but B is the greatest lower bound. In finite partially ordered sets there will always be at least one maximal element. If x is not maximal there s an element y with x y. If y is not maximal then there is an element z with y z, and so on. With finitely many elements we must eventually reach a maximal element. On the other hand, with infinite partially ordered sets, there may be no maximal element. For example the set of real numbers is partially ordered in the usual way and the subset {x 0 x 2 < 2} has no maximal element. But it does have a least upper bound, 2. If we restricted ourselves to just rational numbers there will not even be a least upper bound. B A 21

ZORN S LEMMA: If every chain in the non-empty partially ordered set X has an upper bound then X has a maximal element. Proof : A pseudo proof of this goes along the following lines. Take an element x 1 X. If x 1 isn t maximal there s an element x 2 that s bigger than x 1. If that isn t maximal there s an x 3 bigger than x 2, and so on. So if X doesn t have a maximal element there must be a chain x 1 < x 2 < in X. By our assumption, every chain in X has an upper bound, and so there exists y 1 that is bigger than all of the x i. By the same argument we can produce a chain of y i s so that x 1 < x 2 < < y 1 < y 2 < So far so good. The pseudo nature of the pseudo proof comes when we say surely the process must eventually terminate. We haven t called Zorn s Lemma a theorem because it isn t one. We can prove that there can be no proof of it. But that doesn t mean that it s false, because we can prove there cannot exist a counter-example. This is an example of an undecidable proposition in set theory. We set up a collection of axioms that attempt to avoid a contradiction like the Russell Paradox. Now if you were to set up a random collection of axioms it s possible that they would be self-contradictory. The simplest way to show that they re consistent is to give a concrete example that satisfies them all. The group axioms are consistent because we can give examples of groups. But when it comes to the axioms of set theory, how are we going to produce an example of a universe of sets satisfying the axioms without making use of sets in order to construct such a model? So it would seem that we ll probably never be able to prove that any set of axioms for set theory is consistent. What has been proved is that if the axioms of set theory are consistent, and therefore that there is a model that satisfies them, then it is possible to construct within it another model that satisfies all the set theory axioms together with Zorn s Lemma. This proves that Zorn s Lemma is consistent with the other axioms of set theory. If ever a contradiction is reached after using Zorn s Lemma, the problem would lie with the basic set theory axioms and not with Zorn s Lemma. On the other hand, again assuming that a model for set theory exists, we can construct within it a different model that satisfies the basic axioms of set theory but in which Zorn s Lemma is false! This proves that Zorn s Lemma is independent from the other axioms of set theory. It can never be proved from them, otherwise such a model couldn t exist. So Zorn s Lemma isn t a theorem it isn t even a lemma it is in fact an optional extra axiom that we are logically free to accept or reject. There are other axioms that are equivalent to Zorn s Lemma. The most famous of these is the Axiom of Choice. At least this one goes by the correct name of axiom. Axiom of Choice: If X is a set of non-empty sets, and Y is the set of all the elements of the elements of X, there is a function f:x Y such that f(x) x. Example 5: Let X 1 = {1, 2, 3}, X 2 = {1, 5, 9, 10}, X 3 = the set of prime numbers. Let X = {X 1, X 2, X 3 }. Then Y consists of all the prime numbers, together with 1, 9 and 10. An example of a function described in the Axiom of Choice is: f(x 1 ) = 2, f(x 2 ) = 10, f(x 3 ) = 17. In other words, the function f is a choice function it chooses a specific element from each of the non-empty sets. It may well seem to you obvious that the Axiom of Choice is obvious. If we have a bunch of non-empty sets surely we can choose one element from each! Certainly if the sets 22

are finite and there are finitely many of them it is not only obvious, it is in fact true. But making infinitely many arbitrary choices is a bit different. It has been shown that if we assume the Axiom of Choice we can prove Zorn s Lemma, and vice versa. The Axiom of Choice therefore has the status of an optional axiom, equivalent to Zorn s Lemma. We are logically free to assume the Axiom of Choice, but if we do we must also accept Zorn s Lemma. We are logically free to deny the Axiom of Choice, but if we do we must deny Zorn s Lemma. What are the practical consequences of deciding to accept the Zorn s Lemma/Axiom of Choice package? In terms of the truth of specific examples there can be none. No bridge will fall down because the engineer based his mathematics on the Axiom of Choice. The differences are more aesthetic. Assuming the Axiom of Choice and Zorn s Lemma will allow, in some cases, theorems that are cleaner and simpler to state and in some cases easier to prove, though the specific consequences of mathematics with or without it will be identical. In the following we shall assume Zorn s Lemma. 4.3. Radical Classes A class of rings is a radical class if it is closed under Q, U and P, and hence also under. Being Q-closed every radical class must contain the trivial ring, 0. Theorem 2: If X is a radical class then every ring has a largest X-ideal, R X, called the X-radical of R. Proof: The set of X-ideals is a partially ordered set under. Since X is U-closed, every chain, C, has an upper bound, the union of all the sets in the chain, and so by Zorn s Lemma there s a maximal element M. If I is any X-ideal then M + I is an X -ring so I M. Hence M is the union of all the X-ideals. Theorem 3: If X is a radical property (RS) X = R X S X. Proof: The ideals of R S are of the form I J where I, J are ideals of R, S respectively. If X is a radical property, a ring R is defined to be X-semisimple if its X-radical is zero. The class of X-semisimple rings is denoted by X. Clearly X X = {0}, that is the only ring that is an X-ring and X-semisimple is the trivial ring. Most rings are neither X-rings or X-semisimple, but of course simple rings have to be one or the other the X-radical of a simple ring R is either R or 0. If we factor out the X-radical of any ring we will be left with an X-semisimple ring. This might seem obvious, but remember it doesn t work for rings that are not poly closed. Theorem 4: R/R X. is X-semisimple. Proof: Suppose (R/R X ) X = S/R X. Since X is P-closed, S X so S = R X. Theorem 5: A class of rings X is a radical class if and only if it is Q-closed and every ring R contains an X-ideal R X containing all X-ideals with R/R X X. Proof: Suppose X is a class satisfying these properties. We must show that it is both U- and P-closed. Suppose R/I, I X. Then I R X. R/R X (R/I)/(R X /I) X so R X = R, ie R X. Suppose R 1 R 2 is an ascending chain of X-ideals of a ring R and let U = R i. For each n R n U and (U X + R n )/U X R n /(R n U X X so R n U X. Hence U = U X ie U X. 23

4.4. Nil and Jacobson Radicals Theorem 6: The class, N, of nil rings is a radical class. Proof: N is clearly Q-closed. If I 1 I 2 is an ascending chain of nil ideals then I r is clearly nil, for if x I r, x I r for some r. Since I r is nil, x n = 0 for some n. Finally we must show that N is poly-closed. Suppose I is an ideal of R and both I and R/I are nil rings. Let x R. Since R/I is nil, (r + I) n = r n + I = I, for some n. Thus r n I. Since I is nil, (r n ) m = 0 for some m. The class of nilpotent rings is probably a more useful class than the class of nil rings, but unfortunately it isn t a radical class. Theorem 7: The class of nilpotent rings is closed under P, Q and, but not under U. Proof: Let R = x a x x R where a x a y = a x+y if x + y < 1 0 if x + y 1 0<x<1 This is a non-nilpotent ring. For each positive integer n, let R n = are nilpotent ideals, and R is the union of them all. 1/2 n <x<1 x a x x R. These Example 6: R = {all n n upper triangular matrices over a field F}. The nil-radical R N. consists of those matrices with 0 s on the diagonal and R/R N. F F (n copies). Theorem 8: If R is a commutative ring the set of all nilpotent elements is an ideal and is thus the nil radical of R. Proof: Let a, b be elements of the commutative ring R. If a m = b n = 0 then (a + b) m+n1 = 0 and (ab) min(m,n) = 0. Commutativity is needed since in the ring of 22 matrices 0 0 1 0 and 0 1 0 0 are nilpotent yet their sum and product aren t. Let J be the class of rings in which every element is right quasi-regular. Example 7: J contains, the set of all rational numbers of the form even odd. Theorem 9: J is a radical class. Proof: P-closure follows from the associativity of. Theorem 10: N is a proper subclass of J. Proof: If x is nilpotent, y = x + x 2 x 3... exists as a finite sum and x y = 0. So N is a subclass of J. Since J N, it is a proper subclass. Theorem 11 (Machke s Theorem): Let G = {g 1,..., g n } be a finite group and suppose that char F does not divide G. Then the group ring FG is nil semi-simple. Proof: Suppose 0 S is a nil ideal and let 0 x = a g g S. Since S is an ideal we may suppose, without loss of generality, that a 1 = 1. Let :FG End F FG be the ring homomorphism defined by x(y) = xy. Since x is nilpotent, so is x and hence tr(x) = 0. Now tr(g) = 0 for g 1 and tr(1) = n. Hence n1 = 0 so the characteristic of F divides n. 24

4.5. Upper and Lower Radical Properties We have used two closely related radical classes, nil rings and Jacobson rings. In this chapter we consider radical classes in general and three class operators in particular. HX = {R every 0 quotient of R has a 0 ideal in X}. IX = {R every 0 ideal of R has a 0 quotient in X}. NX = {R R has no 0 quotient in X}. Theorem 12: QHX = HX Proof: Let R QHX. Then R = S/I where S HX. Every quotient of R is isomorphic to a quotient of S so R HX. Theorem 13: I 2 X IX Proof: Let R I 2 X and let I be a non-zero ideal of R. Then there exists an ideal J of I with I < J and I/J IX. Hence there exists an ideal K of I with I/K X and so R I X. Theorem 14: NX NIX Proof: Let R NIX. Then there exists an ideal I of R with 0 R/I IX. Hence there exists an ideal J of R with 0 R/J X and so R NX. Theorem 15: A class of rings X is a radical class if and only if it is Q-closed and H-closed. Proof: Suppose X is a radical class and R X. Then R/R X is non-zero and has no non-zero X-ideal, so R HX. Hence X is H-closed. Suppose X is both Q- and H-closed. Let I, R/I X. and suppose R/J is non-zero. If I J then R/J (R/I)/(J/I) X. Otherwise 0 (I + J)/J I/(I J) X. So R HX X. Suppose R 1 R 2 is an ascending chain of X-ideals of a ring R and let U = R i. Let 0 U/J. For each n, (J + R n )/J R n /(J R n ) X and for some n, (J + R n )/J 0. Theorem 16: If IX = X. then: (i) NX is a radical class. (ii) X = (NX) Proof: (i) Clearly NX is Q-closed. Suppose R HNX NX. Since R NX, there exists a non-zero quotient R/I X. Since R HNX, there exists a non-zero quotient J/I NX. But since R/I IX, J/I NX, a contradiction. (ii) Suppose R X = IX. If R NX 0 then R has a non-zero homomorphic image in X, so R NX NX, a contradiction. Hence R NX = 0. Let R (NX) and let I be a non-zero ideal of R. Then I NX. Hence there exists a nonzero quotient I/J X. Hence R IX = X. Theorem 17: If X IX then NIX is a radical class. Proof: X IX so I 2 X = IX. Let X be a class of rings. The upper radical class determined by X. is X + = NIX. The lower radical class determined by X is X = H QX. Theorem 18: H QX = H n QX is a radical class. Proof: Q(H QN) = (QH)(H QN) = H(H QN) = H QN. 25

Theorem 19: Suppose (M, N) is any partition of the class of simple rings. If X is any radical class with N = S X and M = S X then N X M +. Proof: H n QN H n QX X for all n. If R/I M X X = {0}. Theorem 20: If (M, N) is any partition of S then N M +. Proof: Zp is the Prüfer p-group, being the abelian group generated by a 0, a 1, and subject to the relations pa 0 = 0, pa n+1 = a n, for all n 0. It is an infinite p-group where all non-zero quotients are isomorphic to itself. If H < G let n = max[a n H]. Then H = a n and G/H [a n+1, a n+2, pa n+1 = 0, pa m+1 = a m ] Zp. Z is the infinite cyclic group and every non-zero subgroup is isomorphic to itself. Denote Zero(G) by G. Case I: M contains a zero ring: Z p M for some prime p. Let n = min[ zero ring on a 0 p-group H n N]. Since all 0 quotients of a 0 p-group are 0 p-groups, n = 0. But Z p N. Hence H N = H QN = N contains no 0 zero ring on a p-group. Hence Zp N. If there exists a non-zero quotient Zp/I Zp M, we get a contradiction. Hence Zp NM NIM = M +. So Zp M + N. Case II: M contains no zero rings: Let n = min[z H n N]. Since all non-zero ideals of Z are isomorphic to Z, n = 0. But Z N. Hence Z N. Every quotient of Z is a zero ring and so is not in M. Hence Z NM NIM = M + and so Z M + N. 26