1.2 Forms and Validity



Similar documents
def: An axiom is a statement that is assumed to be true, or in the case of a mathematical system, is used to specify the system.

Hypothetical Syllogisms 1

Likewise, we have contradictions: formulas that can only be false, e.g. (p p).

DISCRETE MATH: LECTURE 3

DEDUCTIVE & INDUCTIVE REASONING

CHAPTER 3. Methods of Proofs. 1. Logical Arguments and Formal Proofs

INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC

Lecture 2: Moral Reasoning & Evaluating Ethical Theories

Philosophical argument

Rules of Inference Friday, January 18, 2013 Chittu Tripathy Lecture 05

Deductive versus Inductive Reasoning

Arguments and Dialogues

What Is Induction and Why Study It?

Deductive reasoning is the application of a general statement to a specific instance.

Logic in general. Inference rules and theorem proving

PHILOSOPHY 101: CRITICAL THINKING

A DIVISION OF THE MENO. Meno proposes a question: whether virtue can be taught. Three conversations or discussions following question

Translation Guide. Not both P and Q ~(P Q) Not either P or Q (neither/nor)

Read this syllabus very carefully. If there are any reasons why you cannot comply with what I am requiring, then talk with me about this at once.

A. Arguments are made up of statements, which can be either true or false. Which of the following are statements?

Invalidity in Predicate Logic

You will by now not be surprised that a version of the teleological argument can be found in the writings of Thomas Aquinas.

6.1 Standard Form, Mood, and Figure

Inductive Reasoning Page 1 of 7. Inductive Reasoning

Logic Appendix. Section 1 Truth Tables CONJUNCTION EXAMPLE 1

Lecture 2. What is the Normative Role of Logic?

Kant s deontological ethics

Chapter 5: Fallacies. 23 February 2015

Logic and Reasoning Practice Final Exam Spring Section Number

PABLO PICASSO PRE-READING QUESTIONS. 1. What kind of art do you like? 2. Do you have a favorite artist?

Cosmological Arguments for the Existence of God S. Clarke

HUMN-218 COURSE SYLLABUS FOR LOGIC AND CRITICAL THINKING. Jill R. Wood Instructor

Beyond Propositional Logic Lukasiewicz s System

Mathematical Induction

Predicate logic Proofs Artificial intelligence. Predicate logic. SET07106 Mathematics for Software Engineering

3. Mathematical Induction

1.6 The Order of Operations

5544 = = = Now we have to find a divisor of 693. We can try 3, and 693 = 3 231,and we keep dividing by 3 to get: 1

Point of View, Perspective, Audience, and Voice

The Refutation of Relativism

Developing Critical Thinking Skills with The Colbert Report

Religious Studies (Specification B) Religious Studies (Specification B) (Short Course)

Grammar Unit: Pronouns

Chapter 10. Key Ideas Correlation, Correlation Coefficient (r),

Lecture 9 Maher on Inductive Probability

Chapter 9. Systems of Linear Equations

Five Roles of Political Parties

Arguments and Methodology INTRODUCTION

Handout #1: Mathematical Reasoning

Philosophy 104. Chapter 8.1 Notes

Math 3000 Section 003 Intro to Abstract Math Homework 2

CONSTRUCTING A LOGICAL ARGUMENT

This document has been produced to support the development of effective questioning and dialogue between teacher and pupils.

CHAPTER 2. Logic. 1. Logic Definitions. Notation: Variables are used to represent propositions. The most common variables used are p, q, and r.

Writing Thesis Defense Papers

Section 11. Giving and Receiving Feedback

Section 1- Geography and the Early Greeks

What Is Circular Reasoning?

6.3 Conditional Probability and Independence

Guide to Writing a Project Report

Predicate Logic. Example: All men are mortal. Socrates is a man. Socrates is mortal.

Quine on truth by convention

3. Logical Reasoning in Mathematics

PHI 201, Introductory Logic p. 1/16

Syllogisms and Fallacies 101

Development of a computer system to support knowledge acquisition of basic logical forms using fairy tale "Alice in Wonderland"

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC

Program Level Learning Outcomes for the Department of Philosophy Page 1

Examination paper for MA0301 Elementær diskret matematikk

5. Develop two test questions based on the first chapter:

A Short Course in Logic Example 8

Last time we had arrived at the following provisional interpretation of Aquinas second way:

CHAPTER 7 GENERAL PROOF SYSTEMS

Mathematical Induction

Montezuma II.

Sentences, Statements and Arguments

THE MORAL AGENDA OF CITIZENSHIP EDUCATION

Science and Religion

RTI Statement for New Starters Please tick the relevant box below:

Cubes and Cube Roots

Descriptive Statistics and Measurement Scales

1/9. Locke 1: Critique of Innate Ideas

Patient Education Connecting patients to the latest multimedia resources. Marra Williams, CHES

Fallacies are deceptive errors of thinking.

Live in the Spirit. A Disciple s Identity. In order to be a follower of Christ, it is essential that we learn how

Section 4.1 Rules of Exponents

ON WHITCOMB S GROUNDING ARGUMENT FOR ATHEISM Joshua Rasmussen Andrew Cullison Daniel Howard-Snyder

REPUTATION MANAGEMENT SURVIVAL GUIDE. A BEGINNER S GUIDE for managing your online reputation to promote your local business.

THERE ARE SEVERAL KINDS OF PRONOUNS:

2. What is the place of this film within the culture?

Boolean Design of Patterns

~SHARING MY PERSONAL PERSPECTIVE~

Test 1: Inference. Directions

Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?

Income-tax PAN S. 206AA TDS from Payments to Non-Residents

Does rationality consist in responding correctly to reasons? John Broome Journal of Moral Philosophy, 4 (2007), pp

Z.6: The Identity Thesis

P1. All of the students will understand validity P2. You are one of the students C. You will understand validity

Critical Analysis So what does that REALLY mean?

Draft Copy: Do Not Cite Without Author s Permission

Transcription:

1.2 Forms and Validity Deductive Logic is the study of methods for determining whether or not an argument is valid. In this section we identify some famous valid argument forms. Argument Forms Consider the following two arguments: 1. If Pepé is a Chihuahua, then Pepé is a dog. 2. Pepé is a Chihuahua. 3. Pepé is a dog. 1. If Clinton is a US president, then Clinton is a US citizen 2. Clinton is a US president. 3. Clinton is a US citizen. Both argument are valid if the premises are true, the conclusion must be true as well. Again: it is not possible both for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. And both share the same pattern or argument form: An argument form is a pattern of reasoning. The form in this case is known as modus ponens. Modus Ponens 1. If A, then B 2. A 3. B

The letters A and B are variables that stand for statements. The grammatical pattern in statement 1 is known as a conditional. The arguments above are substitution instances of modus ponens. A substitutions instance of an argument form is an argument that results from uniformly replacing the variables in that form with statements (or terms). Modus ponens is what is known as a valid argument form: A valid argument form is one in which every substitution instance is valid. It is enough, therefore, to determine the validity of an argument, if it can be identified as an instance of a valid argument form. Such arguments are known as formally valid: A formally valid argument is an argument that is valid in virtue of its form (that is, in virtue of being an instance of a valid argument form). While most valid arguments are formally valid, the converse isn t true although most examples of valid arguments that are not formally valid: 1. All logicians are fastidious. 2. No squares are circles. 2

The validity of this argument is simply due to the fact that it is not possible for its conclusion to be false. For given that, it is not possible both for the conclusion to be false the premises to be true, i.e., it is valid. But the form of this argument is simply: 1. A 2. B And there are clearly invalid instances of this argument, e.g., 1. All logicians are fastidious. 2. All logicians love porridge. Understanding Conditional Statements Consider the following: (a) (b) If it is raining, then the ground is wet. If Lincoln was born in 1709, then he was born before the Civil War. Important Characteristics of Conditionals 1. The statement in the if -clause is called the antecedent of the conditional; the statement in the then -clause is called its consequent. The antecedent of (a) is it is raining, not if it is raining. The consequent of (a) is the ground is wet, not then the ground is wet. 2. Conditionals are hypothetical in nature They say, in effect, that if the antecedent is true, the consequent is true. 3. There are many ways to express conditionals in ordinary English. (More on this later in the semester.) 3

Some Famous Valid Argument Forms 1. If it is raining, then the ground is wet. 2. The ground is not wet. 3. It is not raining. 1. If there is fire in the room, then there is air in the room. 2. There is no air in the room. 3. There is no fire in the room. These arguments are clearly valid. Their form is modus tollens: Modus Tollens 1. If A, then B. 2. Not B. 3. Not A. The difference between modus ponens and modus tollens is the presence of the negations Not B and Not A. The negation of a statement S is its denial, the claim that S is false. Three general points 1. The order of the premises does not matter to the validity of an argument. So the numbering of the premises in an argument or argument form is only to provide us with labels for referring to them. It does not mean that, e.g., the conditional in an instance of modus tollens must come first. 2. The conditionals in a valid argument can be rather long and complex. The only thing that matters is form! 4

3. Putting an argument into explicit form helps to focus attention on key issues. Consider the argument from the text: 1. If the physical universe has existed for an infinite period, then all the energy in the universe is spread out evenly (as opposed to being concentrated in such bodies as planets and stars). 2. It is not true that all the energy in the universe is spread out evenly (as opposed to being concentrated in such bodies as planets and stars). 3. It is not true that the physical universe has existed for an infinite period. The truth of premise 2 is not in doubt, nor is the argument s validity, since it is an instance of modus tollens. The only controversial element of the argument, premise 1. Putting the argument in this form enables us to focus on that element alone. (If the universe oscillates between a Big Bang and a Big Crunch then it could be infinite without the energy in the universe ever being spread out evenly.) The next form is hypothetical syllogism: 1. If tuition continues to increase, then only the wealthy will be able to afford a college education. 2. If only the wealthy will be able to afford a college education, then class divisions will strenthen. 3. If tuition continues to increase, then class divisions will strenthen. Hypothetical Syllogism 1. If A, then B. 2. If B, then C. 3. If A, then C. 5

So far our argument forms have only involved conditional and negations. Our final forms involve disjunctions, indicated by or. 1. Either Picasso painted Woman with a Guitar or Braque painted it. 2. Picasso did not paint Woman with a Guitar. 3. Braque painted Woman with a Guitar. 1. Either experimentation on live animals should be banned or experimentation on humans should be permitted. 2. Experimentation on humans should not be permitted. 3. Experimentation on live animals should be banned. These arguments are instances of disjunctive syllogism: Disjunctive Syllogism (two versions) 1. Either A or B. 2. Not A. 3. B. 1. Either A or B. 2. Not B. 3. A. Statements A and B in a disjunction A or B are known as its disjuncts. Inclusive vs Exclusive Disjunction Note that we will understand or in its inclusive sense; that is, we will count it as true if at least one of its premises is true. Consider an ad for a job: The successful applicant will have either 5 years of programming experience or a BS in computer science. Clearly, someone meeting both conditions would be considered a legitimate applicant. 6

When or is meant to exclude one disjunct, it is being used in its exclusive sense. The inclusive sense is sometimes emphasized by adding or both to a disjunction. Similarly, the exclusive sense is sometimes forced by adding but not both : 1. Either Jones will get the job or Smith will (but not both). 2. Jones will get the job. 3. Smith will not get the job. Be sure to distinguish this argument from: 1. Either Jones will get the job or Smith will. 2. Jones will get the job. 3. Smith will not get the job. That argument, without the not both qualification, is clearly invalid. (Why?) Finally, consider the following: 1. Either God cannot prevent suffering or God does not want to prevent any of it. 2. If God cannot prevent suffering, then God is weak. 3. If God does not want to prevent suffering, then God is not good 4. Either God is weak or God is not good. This notorious atheological argument known as the Problem of Evil is an instance of the form constructive dilemma: Constructive Dilemma 1. Either A or B. 2. If A, then C. 3. If B, then D. 4. Either C or D. 7

The Famous Forms Method An argument is valid if it is an instance of a valid argument form. This suggests a very simple method for determining that some arguments are valid. The Famous Forms Method Step 1: Step 2: Step 3: Identify the component statements in the argument (ignoring stylistic variation), uniformly labeling each with its own capital letter. Rewrite the argument using capital letters instead of English statements. Check to see whether the pattern of reasoning is one of our famous argument forms. If it is, conclude the argument is valid. Important Limitations of the Famous Forms Method 1. Many valid arguments are not instances of our five famous forms. Hence, the method is incomplete; the fact that this method does not show that an argument is valid does not mean that it is not valid. For all the method tells us, an argument whose form is not among our five forms could be valid or invalid. This entails our second limitation: 2. The method does nothing to help us determine that an invalid argument is invalid. 8