Sequential Equilibrium Distributions in Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Sequential Equilibrium Distributions in Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions"

Transcription

1 Sequential Equilibrium Distributions in Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions by Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny* Draft notes October Abstract: Guided by several key examples, we formulate a definition of a sequential equilibrium distribution for multi-stage games with infinite type sets and infinite action sets, and we prove its existence for a class of games. * Department of Economics, University of Chicago 1

2 Goal: formulate a definition of sequential equilibrium for multi-stage games with infinite type sets and infinite action sets, and prove existence for some broad class of games. Sequential equilibria were defined for finite games by Kreps-Wilson 1982, but rigorously defined extensions to infinite games have been lacking. Various formulations of perfect bayesian equilibrium (defined for finite games in Fudenberg-Tirole 1991) have been used for infinite games; no general existence theorem. Harris-Stinchcombe-Zame 2000 explored definitions with nonstandard analysis. It is natural to try to define sequential equilibria of an infinite game can by taking limits of sequential equilibria of finite games that approximate it. But no general definition of good finite approximation has been found. It is easy to define sequences of finite games that seem to be converging to the infinite game (in some sense) but have limits of equilibria that seem wrong. We therefore take another route. A strategy is an epsilon-sequential equilibrium if for any finite partition of the players type (information) spaces, each player's strategy is epsilon-optimal at each element of the partition when the strategies of players and Nature are perturbed with epsilon probability, independently across players and coordinates of the state, so that each partition element has positive probability. A sequential equilibrium distribution (over outcomes) is a limit of epsilon-sequential equilibrium distributions as epsilon tends to zero. The definition presented here is based on intuitive judgments about what is reasonable. Others are encouraged to explore alternative definitions. 2

3 Multi-stage games =(N,K,A,T,J,,d,M,p,,u) i N = {players}, a finite set; k {1,...,K} dates of the game. L = {(i,k) i N, k {1,...,K}} = {dated players}. We write ik for (i,k). A ik = {possible actions for player i at date k}; history independent. T ik = {possible informational types for player i at date k}. k = j J kj = {possible date k states}; J a finite set. kj is metrized by d kj. -algebras (closed under countable and complements) of measurable subsets are specified for A ik, T ik, and kj. kj has its Borel -algebra. Products are given their product -algebras. A = k K i N A ik = {possible vectors of actions in the whole game}. T = k K i N T ik = {possible vectors of types in the whole game}. = k K k = {possible states in the whole game}; A = {possible outcomes of the game}. The subscript, <k, denotes the projection onto periods before k, and k weakly before. e.g., A <k = h<k i N A ih = {possible action sequences before period k} (A <1 = { }), and for a A, a <k = h<k i N a ih is the partial sequence of actions before period k. For any of the sets X above, M(X) denotes its set of measurable subsets. Let (X) denote the set of countably additive probability measures on M(X). The date k state is determined by a regular conditional probability (r.c.p.) p k from <k A <k to ( k ). i.e., for each ( <k,a <k ), p k ( <k,a <k ) is in ( k ), and for each B M( k ), p k (B <k,a <k ) is a measurable function of ( <k,a <k ). Nature s probability function is p=(p 1,,p K ). Player i's date k information is given by a measurable onto type function ik : k A <k T ik. Assume perfect recall: ik L, m < k, there is a measurable ikm :T ik T im A im such that ikm ( ik ( k,a <k )) = ( im ( m,a <m ),a im ),, a A. Each player i has a measurable and bounded utility function u i : A R. 3

4 Strategies and induced distributions A strategy, s ik for any ik L is any regular conditional probability from T ik to (A ik ). i.e., for each t ik T ik, s ik ( t ik ) is a countably additive probability on the measurable subsets of A ik, and for each measurable subset B of A ik, s ik (B t ik ) is a measurable function of t ik. Let S ik denote ik s set of strategies, let S i = k S ik, denote i s set of strategies, and let S = ik L S ik denote the set of all strategy profiles. For any s k i N S ik and any t k i N T ik, let s k ( t k ) denote the product measure i N s ik ( t ik ) on i N A ik. Let A k = i N A ik. Each s k i N S ik determines a regular conditional probability q k from <k A <k to ( k A k ) as follows. For any measurable subset Z of k A k, and any ( <k,a <k ) <k A <k, q k (Z <k,a <k,s k ) = k s k (Z k ( k ) k ( k,a <k ))p k (d k <k,a <k ), where Z k ( k )={a k i N A ik :( k,a k ) Z}, and k ( k,a <k ) = i N ik ( k,a <k ). Set Q 1 = q 1, and define the probability measures Q 2,,Q K inductively as follows. For each k and any measurable subset W of k A k, Q k (W s) = <k A<k q k (W k ( <k,a <k ) <k,a <k,s k )Q k-1 (d( <k,a <k ) s), where W k ( <k,a <k ) = {( k,a k ) : ( k, <k, a k,a <k ) W}. Q K ( s) ( A) is the probability measure over outcomes induced by the strategy s. 4

5 Observable events, conditional probabilities and payoffs For any s S, any ik L, and any C M(T ik ), let P(C s) = Q K ({(,a): ik ( k,a <k ) C} s). For any 0, let C ik ( ) denote the set of measurable subsets of T ik that can have probability more than under some strategy profile, that is C ik ( ) = {C M(T ik ): P(C s) > for some s S}. We may say that the events in C ik ( ) are -observable by player i at date k. Let C( ) = ik L C ik ( ) (a disjoint union) denote the set of all events that are -observable by some player at some date. Then C(0) is the set of all observable events for the players in this game. Let Y denote the set of measurable subsets Y of A. That is, Y is the set of all outcome events. If P(C s) > 0, then we may define: a. the conditional probability P( C,s) on A by P(Y C,s) = Q K ({(,a) Y: ik ( k,a <k ) C} s)/p(c s), for any Y Y, and b. player i s conditional payoff by U i (s C) = A u i (,a) P(d(,a) C,s). To make explicit the dependence of the above conditionals on Nature s probability function, p = (p 1,,p K ), we may sometimes write P(C s,p), P(Y C,s,p), and U i (s C,p). To motivate our definition, we consider a number of examples. 5

6 Strategic entanglement in limits of approximate equilibria (Harris-Reny-Robson 1995) Example 1: Date 1: Player 1 chooses a 1 from [-1,1], player 2 chooses from {L,R}. Date 2: Players 3 and 4 observe the date 1 choices and each choose from {L,R}. For i=3,4, player i s payoff is -a 1 if i chooses L and a 1 if i chooses R. Player 2 s payoff depends on whether she matches 3 s choice. If 2 chooses L then she gets 1 if player 3 chooses L but -1 if 3 chooses R; and If 2 chooses R then she gets 2 if player 3 chooses R but -2 if 3 chooses L. Player 1 s payoff is the sum of three terms: (First term) If 2 and 3 match he gets - a 1, if they mismatch he gets a 1 ; plus (second term) if 3 and 4 match he gets 0, if they mismatch he gets -10; plus (third term) he gets - a 1 2. There is no subgame perfect equilibrium of this game. But it has an obvious solution which is the limit of strategy profiles where everyone's strategy is arbitrarily close to optimal. Approximations in which 3 and 4 can distinguish between a 1 = +,0,- and in which 1 s action set is {-1,,-2/m,-1/m,1/m,2/m,,1} have a unique subgame perfect (hence sequential) equilibrium in which player 1 chooses ±1/m with probability ½ each, player 2 chooses L and R each with probability ½, and players i=3,4 both choose L if a 1 =-1/m and both choose R if a 1 =1/m. The limiting outcome distribution is a 1 = 0, a 2 = L or R each with probability ½, and (a 3,a 4 ) = (L,L) or (R,R) each with probability ½. Player 3 s and player 4 s strategies are entangled in the limit, that is, independent strategies cannot yield their joint behavior in the limit distribution. 6

7 Limitations of step-strategy approximations Example 2: Player 1 chooses a 1 [0,1]. Player 2 observes t 2 = a 1 and chooses a 2 [0,1]. The game is zero-sum. Player 1 receives 1 if their choices do not match and -1 otherwise. (This discontinuous game could be a reduced form of a continuous game with another stage.) There should be no equilibrium in which player 2 fails to match player 1 s choice. However, for any fixed partition of player 2 s type space T 2 = [0,1], player 1 can mix uniformly over a large enough finite set of actions within a single element of 2 s partition so that player 2 has an arbitrarily small chance of matching 1 s choice. Player 2 would like to use the strategy "choose a 2 = t 2," but this strategy can be approximated only by step functions when player 2 has finitely many feasible actions. Step functions close to this strategy yield very different expected payoffs because 2 s utility function is discontinuous (but such discontinuities can arise in the reduced form of a continuous game with one additional stage). If we gave player 2 the strategy s 2 (t 1 ) = t 1, she would use it! This example suggests that, because certain strategies can be particularly important for players, we should include strategies (not just actions) in our finite approximations. 7

8 Problems of spurious signaling in naïve finite approximations Example 3: Nature chooses {1,2}, p( ) = /3. Player 1 observes t 1 = and chooses a 1 [0,1]. Player 2 observes t 2 = (a 1 ) and chooses a 2 {1,2}. Payoffs are as follows. a 2 = 1 a 2 = 2 = 1 (1,1) (0,0) = 2 (1,0) (0,1) 1 s payoff should be 0. Otherwise, in any Nash equilibrium (similarly for epsilon-nash equilibrium), for some a 1 =x (0,1) in the support of 1 s strategy, a 1 =x 2 is less than twice as likely as x, and so player 2 chooses a 2 =2 after observing t 2 =x 2 ; hence 1 s payoff is Pr(a 2 =1 t 2 =x)/3. But choosing a 1 =(x) 1/2 gives 1 at least 2Pr(a 2 =1 t 2 =x)/3; so 1 s payoff is 0. But choose any finite partition of 2 s types where sequential rationality will be checked, and consider filling in the players pure strategy sets. For any finite set F of pure strategies (actions) for player 1, we can always add one more pure strategy a 1 = x such that 0<x<1 and (x) 1/2 is not in F. And we can add to player 2 s finite set of strategies the pure strategy s 2 such that s 2 (t 2 ) = 1 iff (t 2 ) 1/2 F {x}; so s 2 (x)=2. In this approximating game with finitely many strategies, we find a subgame-perfect equilibrium in which player 1 chooses x, player 2 applies s 2, and player 1 s payoff is 1/3. Taken together, the examples indicate that attempting to approximate the true game with a finite game is unreliable because it can produce unwanted equilibria. (Harris-Stinchcombe-Zame 2000 provide many excellent additional examples of this kind.) Thus we define optimality for a player relative to the player's entire set of strategies. But we use finite partitions of type spaces to define where sequential rationality is checked. 8

9 Spurious miscoordination: the need for uniform sequential rationality Example 4: There are two teams and a referee. The odd team consists of players 1 and 3. The even team consists of players 2 and 4. Players 1 and 2 each choose an action from [0,1] at date 1. Players 3 and 4 each choose an action from [0,1] at date 2. Each date 2 player observes the date 1 choice of his teammate. The referee, player 5, is equally likely to observe the choices of team 1 or of team 2, but he does not know which team s choices he observes. After the observation, player 5 chooses an action from {0,1}, which determines the common payoff of the two players whose choice he observed. All other players receive a payoff of zero, including the referee. It should not be possible for each of the two players on the odd team to receive an expected payoff close to 1/2 without each of the two players on the even team also being able to do so. However, for any finite partition of the players type spaces, let x and y be distinct actions in some common element of player 4 s partition. Consider strategies that give positive probability to all partition elements and that also satisfy the following. Players 1 and 3 place most of their probability weight on, respectively, a 1 =x and s 3 (t 3 )=x t 3, and players 2 and 4 place most of their probability weight on, respectively, a 2 =y and s 4 (t 4 )=y t 4. Player 5 s strategy chooses action 1 iff he observes (x,x). These strategies reach every element of the partition with positive probability and are sequentially rational there. Nevertheless, these strategies are nonsensical. The problem is that the strategies are permitted to vary with the partition, so player 3's sequential rationality is never checked on the sets where player 4 finds opportunities to win. For fixed strategies, we need to check sequential rationality uniformly in observable events. 9

10 The need to perturb Nature as well as players' strategies for positive probabilities Example 5: Player 1 chooses a 11 {L,R}. If a 11 = L, then Nature chooses [0,1] uniformly, whereas if a 11 = R, then player 1 moves again and chooses a 12 [0,1]. In either case, player 2 moves next. Player 2 observes t 2 = if a 11 = L and observes t 2 = a 12 if a 11 = R, and then chooses a 2 {L,R}. Payoffs (battle of the sexes) are as follows. a 2 = L a 2 = R a 11 = L (1,2) (0,0) a 12 = R (0,0) (2,1) All BoS equilibria are reasonable (the choice, or a 12, from [0,1] is payoff irrelevant). However, if all events that can have positive probability under some strategies must eventually receive positive probability along a sequence (or net) for consistency, then the only possible equilibrium payoff is (2,1). Indeed, for any x [0,1], the event t 2 = x can have positive probability, but only if positive probability is given to the strategy (a 11 = R, a 12 = x), because = x has probability 0. So, in any strategy assigning positive probability to t 2 = x, player 2 s strategy must choose a 2 = R when t 2 = x by sequential rationality. But then player 1 can obtain a payoff of 2 with the strategy (a 11 = R, a 12 = x) and so the unique equilibrium outcome is (2,1)! To allow other equilibria we should perturb Nature. 10

11 The need to perturb the coordinates of Nature's state independently Example 6 (Harris-Stinchcombe-Zame 2000): Nature chooses (, ) { 1,1} [0,1]. The coordinates are independent and uniform. Player 1 observes t 1 = and chooses a 1 [0,1]. Player 2 observes t 2 = a 1 and chooses a 2 { 1,0,1}. Payoffs are: u 1 (,,a 1,a 2 ) = a 2, u 2 (,,a 1,a 2 ) = (a 2 ) 2. Thus, player 2 should choose a 2 to equal her expected value of, and player 1 wants to hide information about from 2. Player 1 can hide information about from player 2 by using the strategy s 1 ( ) =. Hence, the most natural equilibrium gives player 1 a payoff of zero. It is the only sequential equilibrium if [0,1] is approximated by a discrete set both for Nature and for player 1. However, consider the strategy profile s 1 ( ) = 1; s 2 (t 2 ) = 1 if t 2 0, and s 2 (t 2 ) = 1 if t 2 < 0. This profile is sequentially rational at every t 2 except t 2 = 0 and gives player 1 a payoff of -1. To verify whether s 2 (0)=1 could be sequentially rational here, we need to consider perturbed scenarios where player 1 or nature might behave differently with small probability. The question is whether E( a 1 = ) could ever be different from 0 in such a scenario. This could happen if we perturbed (, ) jointly to equal (1,1) with some probability >0. Then learning a 1 = would cause 2 to believe that =1, making s 2 (0)=1 sequentially rational. But this perturbation violates the structural independence of and in the given game. Thus, we should only consider perturbations of Nature that treat separate coordinates of the state independently. As long as a 1 and are both independent of, we must have E( a 1 = ) = 0. 11

12 Problems from allowing large perturbations of Nature even with small probability Example 7 : Nature chooses ( 11, 12 ) [0,1] 2. With probability ½, the coordinates are independent and uniform on [0,1], and with probability ½ the coordinates are equal and uniform on [0,1]. Player 1 observes t 1 = 11 and chooses a 1 {-1,1}. Player 2 observes t 2 = a 1 and chooses a 2 { 1,1}. Payoffs are: u 1 ( 11, 12,a 1,a 2 ) = a 1 a 2, u 2 ( 11, 12,a 1,a 2 ) = a 2 (1/ ). Thus, player 2 should choose a 2 = 1 if she expects to be less than 1/3 and she should choose a 2 = -1 otherwise. Player 1 wants to choose an action that player 2 will match. Since for every 11, 12 is equally likely to be equal to 11 (in which case =0) as to be uniform on [0,1] (in which case ½), player 2 should expect to be no greater than ¼, regardless of 1 s strategy. So player 2 should choose a 2 = 1. Thus all sensible equilibria involve strategies that give probability 1 to (a 1,a 2 ) = (1,1). But consider the strategy profile (s 1,s 2 ) where s 1 ( 11 ) = -1 iff 11 1, and s 2 (a 1 ) = 1 iff a 1 = -1. This profile gives probability 1 to (a 1,a 2 ) = (-1,1), and is supported in an epsilon-sequential equilibrium by the perturbation of Nature that never perturbs 12 but that with probability epsilon perturbs the distribution of 11 so that it is a mass point on 11 = 1. With this perturbation of Nature it is sequentially rational for player 2 to choose a 2 = -1 when she observes a 1 = 1 because she attributes this observation to 11 being a mass point on 1 and therefore expects the value of to be ½. This difficulty can be eliminated if Nature s states can be perturbed only to nearby states. 12

13 -close perturbations of Nature Arbitrary perturbations of Nature could have dramatic effects on the players information. To avoid this, we consider here only perturbations such that separate coordinates of Nature s dated states (in k = j J kj for each date k) are independently perturbed, so that the perturbation of one coordinate adds no information about any other coordinate. In close perturbations, states can be changed only slightly and only with small probability. Let kj be the set of regular conditional probabilities from kj to ( kj ), and let = k K,j J kj denote the set of all coordinatewise-independent perturbation mappings. Any in induces a perturbation of Nature p where, for each period k, ( p) k is the regular conditional probability from <k A <k to ( k ) such that for any B = j J B j k, [ p] k (B <k,a <k ) = k j J kj (B j kh ) p k (d k <k,a <k ). Here denotes multiplication, as state coordinates are independently perturbed. Say that p is an -close perturbation of p if there is such that p = p and kj ({ jh } kh ) 1 and kj ({ kj : d kj ( kj, kj ) < } kj ) =1, kj kj, j, k. Remark. Given, the -close perturbation p of p works as follows. At each date k a provisional state k =( kj ) j J is drawn according to p k ( <k,a <k ), where <k is the actual (not provisional) vector of past dated-states. Then, for each coordinate j J, the actual jth coordinate is drawn independently according to kj ( kj ) which assigns probability 1- to the event that the actual jth coordinate of the date k state is equal to its provisional value kj, and which assigns probability 0 to anything farther than from the provisional value. Thus, for each date, for each coordinate of Nature s state, for any past history, p generates a state-coordinate value which may deviate slightly from the value generated by p, but such deviations must be unlikely and must be independent across coordinates. 13

14 -sequential equilibria Say that r i S i is a date-k continuation of s i S i if r ij = s ij for all dates j < k. We say that s is an -small perturbation of the strategy s in S iff there exists some ŝ in S such that s = (1- )s+ ŝ, that is, s ik ( t ik ) = (1 )s ik ( t ik )+ ŝ ik ( t ik ) ik, t ik. For any > 0, say that s S is an -sequential equilibrium of if for every F that is a finite subset of C( ) containing at most 1/ events, there exist some p that is an -close perturbation of p and some s that is an -small perturbation of s, such that ik L, C F C ik ( ), 1. P(C s,p ) > 0, and 2. U i (r i,s i C,p ) U i (s C,p ) +, for any r i that is a date-k continuation of s i. Note. Changing i s choice only at dates j k does not change the probability of i's types at k, so P(C r i,s i,p ) = P(C s,p ) > 0. Thus as becomes small, a strategy profile can satisfy -sequential rationality if, for any arbitrarily large collection of events that are observable with arbitrarily small probability, there is some arbitrarily small perturbation of the strategy profile and some arbitrarily close perturbation of nature such that the players come arbitrarily close to maximizing their conditional expected utilities on all their observable events in the given collection. 14

15 Sequential equilibrium distributions in the limit. Recall that Q K ( s) is the (countably additive) probability measure over A induced by s, and Y denotes the set of measurable subsets of A. Call a finitely additive probability measure : Y [0,1] a pointwise sequential equilibrium distribution of iff for every > 0 and every finite subset F of Y, there is an -sequential equilibrium s such that Y F, (Y)-Q K (Y s ) <. (Example 1 shows that a sequence of -sequential equilibria may, in the limit, yield a distribution that is only finitely additive. For any >0, the events that player 1's action is in {a 1 : <a 1 <0} or in {a 1 : 0<a 1 < } must each have probability 1/2.) Now suppose that and A each have a topology, and let M( ) and M(A) be the Borel sets. Then Y ={Borel subsets of A}. A countably additive probability measure : Y [0,1] is a weak* sequential equilibrium distribution of iff there is a sequence, s, of -sequential equilibria such that Q K ( s ) weak* converges to. (For Example 1, the weak* sequential equilibrium distribution would put probability 1 on player 1 choosing a 1 =0. But at date 2, the actions of players 3 and 4 will still be perfectly correlated, both choosing L or R with probability 1/2 independently of 2's action.) 15

16 Regular multi-stage games with projected types Let = (N,K,A,T,J,,d,M,p,,u) be a multi-stage game (with perfect recall ). is a regular game with projected types if there are sets A ikj such that, for every ik L: (R.1) A ik = j J A ikj, (R.2) kj and A ikj are nonempty compact metric spaces j J (with all spaces, including products, given their Borel sigma-algebras), (R.3) u i : A R is continuous, (R.4) there is a continuous nonnegative density function f k : k A <k [0, ), and for each j in J, there is a probability measure kj ( kj ) such that p k (B <k,a <k ) = B f k ( k <k,a <k ) k (d k ) B M( k ), ( <k,a <k ) <k A <k, where k = j J kj is a product measure. (R.5) there exist sets M 1ik {1,,k} J and M 2ik N {1,,k-1} J, such that ik ( k,a <k ) = (( hj ) hj M 1ik, (a nhj ) nhj M 2ik) ( k,a <k ); that is, i's type at k is just a list of state coordinates and action coordinates from periods up to k. Remarks:. (1) One can always reduce the cardinality of J to (K+1) N or less by grouping, for any ik L, the variables {a ikj } j J and { kj } j J according to the N -vector of dates at which each player observes them, if ever. (2) Regular multi-stage games with projected types can include all finite multi-stage games (simply by letting each player's type be a coordinate of the state). (3) Since distinct players can observe the same kj, regular multi-stage games with projected types need not satisfy the Milgrom-Weber (1985) absolute continuity condition. 16

17 Existence Theorems Theorem 1. In all finite multi-stage games, a strategy is part of a Kreps-Wilson sequential equilibrium iff it is the limit, as tends to zero, of a sequence of -sequential equilibria (as defined here), and the sets of pointwise and weak* sequential equilibrium distributions here both coincide with the set of Kreps-Wilson sequential equilibrium distributions. Theorem 2. Consider any multi-stage game in which all state and action spaces are Polish, all action spaces are compact, and all spaces are given their Borel sigma algebras. If for every date k, p k ( <k,a <k ) is weak* continuous in ( <k,a <k ), then a weak* sequential equilibrium distribution exists if and only if an -sequential equilibrium exists for all > 0. Theorem 3. In all regular multi-stage games with projected types, the set of weak* sequential equilibrium distributions is nonempty. Theorem 4. A pointwise sequential equilibrium distribution exists if an -sequential equilibrium exists for every >0, which is true if the game is regular with projected types. (The proof applies Tychonoff s theorem to the compact product space [0,1] Y.) 17

18 References David Kreps and Robert Wilson (1982): "Sequential Equilibria," 50: Drew Fudenberg and Jean Tirole (1991): "Perfect Bayesian and Sequential Equilibrium," Journal of Economic Theory 53: Christopher J. Harris, Maxwell B. Stinchcombe, and William R. Zame (2000): "The Finitistic Theory of Infinite Games," UTexas.edu working paper. Christopher J. Harris, Philip J. Reny, and Arthur J. Robson (1995): "The existence of subgame-perfect equilibrium in continuous games with almost perfect information," Econometrica 63(3): John L. Kelley, General Topology (Springer-Verlag, 1955). Milgrom, P. and R. Weber (1985): "Distributional Strategies for Games with Incomplete Information," Mathematics of Operations Research, 10,

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 2: Strategic Form Games

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 2: Strategic Form Games 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 2: Strategic Form Games Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 4, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Decisions, utility maximization Strategic form games Best responses

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 15: Repeated Games and Cooperation

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 15: Repeated Games and Cooperation 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 15: Repeated Games and Cooperation Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT November 2, 2009 1 Introduction Outline The problem of cooperation Finitely-repeated prisoner s dilemma

More information

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send email to: permissions@pupress.princeton.edu

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send email to: permissions@pupress.princeton.edu COPYRIGHT NOTICE: Ariel Rubinstein: Lecture Notes in Microeconomic Theory is published by Princeton University Press and copyrighted, c 2006, by Princeton University Press. All rights reserved. No part

More information

MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 6.436J/15.085J Fall 2008 Lecture 5 9/17/2008 RANDOM VARIABLES

MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 6.436J/15.085J Fall 2008 Lecture 5 9/17/2008 RANDOM VARIABLES MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 6.436J/15.085J Fall 2008 Lecture 5 9/17/2008 RANDOM VARIABLES Contents 1. Random variables and measurable functions 2. Cumulative distribution functions 3. Discrete

More information

Notes on metric spaces

Notes on metric spaces Notes on metric spaces 1 Introduction The purpose of these notes is to quickly review some of the basic concepts from Real Analysis, Metric Spaces and some related results that will be used in this course.

More information

INDISTINGUISHABILITY OF ABSOLUTELY CONTINUOUS AND SINGULAR DISTRIBUTIONS

INDISTINGUISHABILITY OF ABSOLUTELY CONTINUOUS AND SINGULAR DISTRIBUTIONS INDISTINGUISHABILITY OF ABSOLUTELY CONTINUOUS AND SINGULAR DISTRIBUTIONS STEVEN P. LALLEY AND ANDREW NOBEL Abstract. It is shown that there are no consistent decision rules for the hypothesis testing problem

More information

1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set.

1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set. 1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set. Basic Topology Written by Men-Gen Tsai email: b89902089@ntu.edu.tw Proof: For any element x of the empty set, x is also an element of every set since

More information

Chapter 7. Sealed-bid Auctions

Chapter 7. Sealed-bid Auctions Chapter 7 Sealed-bid Auctions An auction is a procedure used for selling and buying items by offering them up for bid. Auctions are often used to sell objects that have a variable price (for example oil)

More information

Mathematical Induction

Mathematical Induction Mathematical Induction In logic, we often want to prove that every member of an infinite set has some feature. E.g., we would like to show: N 1 : is a number 1 : has the feature Φ ( x)(n 1 x! 1 x) How

More information

ALMOST COMMON PRIORS 1. INTRODUCTION

ALMOST COMMON PRIORS 1. INTRODUCTION ALMOST COMMON PRIORS ZIV HELLMAN ABSTRACT. What happens when priors are not common? We introduce a measure for how far a type space is from having a common prior, which we term prior distance. If a type

More information

When is Reputation Bad? 1

When is Reputation Bad? 1 When is Reputation Bad? 1 Jeffrey Ely Drew Fudenberg David K Levine 2 First Version: April 22, 2002 This Version: November 20, 2005 Abstract: In traditional reputation theory, the ability to build a reputation

More information

Théorie de la décision et théorie des jeux Stefano Moretti

Théorie de la décision et théorie des jeux Stefano Moretti héorie de la décision et théorie des jeux Stefano Moretti UMR 7243 CNRS Laboratoire d'analyse et Modélisation de Systèmes pour l'aide à la décision (LAMSADE) Université Paris-Dauphine email: Stefano.MOREI@dauphine.fr

More information

FEGYVERNEKI SÁNDOR, PROBABILITY THEORY AND MATHEmATICAL

FEGYVERNEKI SÁNDOR, PROBABILITY THEORY AND MATHEmATICAL FEGYVERNEKI SÁNDOR, PROBABILITY THEORY AND MATHEmATICAL STATIsTICs 4 IV. RANDOm VECTORs 1. JOINTLY DIsTRIBUTED RANDOm VARIABLEs If are two rom variables defined on the same sample space we define the joint

More information

Lecture 2: Universality

Lecture 2: Universality CS 710: Complexity Theory 1/21/2010 Lecture 2: Universality Instructor: Dieter van Melkebeek Scribe: Tyson Williams In this lecture, we introduce the notion of a universal machine, develop efficient universal

More information

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 3. Spaces with special properties

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 3. Spaces with special properties SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR MATHEMATICS 205A Part 3 Fall 2008 III. Spaces with special properties III.1 : Compact spaces I Problems from Munkres, 26, pp. 170 172 3. Show that a finite union of compact subspaces

More information

CPC/CPA Hybrid Bidding in a Second Price Auction

CPC/CPA Hybrid Bidding in a Second Price Auction CPC/CPA Hybrid Bidding in a Second Price Auction Benjamin Edelman Hoan Soo Lee Working Paper 09-074 Copyright 2008 by Benjamin Edelman and Hoan Soo Lee Working papers are in draft form. This working paper

More information

No: 10 04. Bilkent University. Monotonic Extension. Farhad Husseinov. Discussion Papers. Department of Economics

No: 10 04. Bilkent University. Monotonic Extension. Farhad Husseinov. Discussion Papers. Department of Economics No: 10 04 Bilkent University Monotonic Extension Farhad Husseinov Discussion Papers Department of Economics The Discussion Papers of the Department of Economics are intended to make the initial results

More information

E3: PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS lecture notes

E3: PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS lecture notes E3: PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS lecture notes 2 Contents 1 PROBABILITY THEORY 7 1.1 Experiments and random events............................ 7 1.2 Certain event. Impossible event............................

More information

Working Paper Series

Working Paper Series RGEA Universidade de Vigo http://webs.uvigo.es/rgea Working Paper Series A Market Game Approach to Differential Information Economies Guadalupe Fugarolas, Carlos Hervés-Beloso, Emma Moreno- García and

More information

Game Theory and Algorithms Lecture 10: Extensive Games: Critiques and Extensions

Game Theory and Algorithms Lecture 10: Extensive Games: Critiques and Extensions Game Theory and Algorithms Lecture 0: Extensive Games: Critiques and Extensions March 3, 0 Summary: We discuss a game called the centipede game, a simple extensive game where the prediction made by backwards

More information

Separation Properties for Locally Convex Cones

Separation Properties for Locally Convex Cones Journal of Convex Analysis Volume 9 (2002), No. 1, 301 307 Separation Properties for Locally Convex Cones Walter Roth Department of Mathematics, Universiti Brunei Darussalam, Gadong BE1410, Brunei Darussalam

More information

Infinitely Repeated Games with Discounting Ù

Infinitely Repeated Games with Discounting Ù Infinitely Repeated Games with Discounting Page 1 Infinitely Repeated Games with Discounting Ù Introduction 1 Discounting the future 2 Interpreting the discount factor 3 The average discounted payoff 4

More information

ON SEQUENTIAL CONTINUITY OF COMPOSITION MAPPING. 0. Introduction

ON SEQUENTIAL CONTINUITY OF COMPOSITION MAPPING. 0. Introduction ON SEQUENTIAL CONTINUITY OF COMPOSITION MAPPING Abstract. In [1] there was proved a theorem concerning the continuity of the composition mapping, and there was announced a theorem on sequential continuity

More information

Tiers, Preference Similarity, and the Limits on Stable Partners

Tiers, Preference Similarity, and the Limits on Stable Partners Tiers, Preference Similarity, and the Limits on Stable Partners KANDORI, Michihiro, KOJIMA, Fuhito, and YASUDA, Yosuke February 7, 2010 Preliminary and incomplete. Do not circulate. Abstract We consider

More information

FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: QUOTIENT SPACES

FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: QUOTIENT SPACES FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: QUOTIENT SPACES CHRISTOPHER HEIL 1. Cosets and the Quotient Space Any vector space is an abelian group under the operation of vector addition. So, if you are have studied

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lectures 19-21: Incomplete Information: Bayesian Nash Equilibria, Auctions and Introduction to Social Learning

6.207/14.15: Networks Lectures 19-21: Incomplete Information: Bayesian Nash Equilibria, Auctions and Introduction to Social Learning 6.207/14.15: Networks Lectures 19-21: Incomplete Information: Bayesian Nash Equilibria, Auctions and Introduction to Social Learning Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT November 23, 25 and 30, 2009 1 Introduction

More information

n k=1 k=0 1/k! = e. Example 6.4. The series 1/k 2 converges in R. Indeed, if s n = n then k=1 1/k, then s 2n s n = 1 n + 1 +...

n k=1 k=0 1/k! = e. Example 6.4. The series 1/k 2 converges in R. Indeed, if s n = n then k=1 1/k, then s 2n s n = 1 n + 1 +... 6 Series We call a normed space (X, ) a Banach space provided that every Cauchy sequence (x n ) in X converges. For example, R with the norm = is an example of Banach space. Now let (x n ) be a sequence

More information

Metric Spaces. Chapter 7. 7.1. Metrics

Metric Spaces. Chapter 7. 7.1. Metrics Chapter 7 Metric Spaces A metric space is a set X that has a notion of the distance d(x, y) between every pair of points x, y X. The purpose of this chapter is to introduce metric spaces and give some

More information

MA651 Topology. Lecture 6. Separation Axioms.

MA651 Topology. Lecture 6. Separation Axioms. MA651 Topology. Lecture 6. Separation Axioms. This text is based on the following books: Fundamental concepts of topology by Peter O Neil Elements of Mathematics: General Topology by Nicolas Bourbaki Counterexamples

More information

NOTES ON LINEAR TRANSFORMATIONS

NOTES ON LINEAR TRANSFORMATIONS NOTES ON LINEAR TRANSFORMATIONS Definition 1. Let V and W be vector spaces. A function T : V W is a linear transformation from V to W if the following two properties hold. i T v + v = T v + T v for all

More information

Duality of linear conic problems

Duality of linear conic problems Duality of linear conic problems Alexander Shapiro and Arkadi Nemirovski Abstract It is well known that the optimal values of a linear programming problem and its dual are equal to each other if at least

More information

Chapter 4 Lecture Notes

Chapter 4 Lecture Notes Chapter 4 Lecture Notes Random Variables October 27, 2015 1 Section 4.1 Random Variables A random variable is typically a real-valued function defined on the sample space of some experiment. For instance,

More information

Microeconomic Theory Jamison / Kohlberg / Avery Problem Set 4 Solutions Spring 2012. (a) LEFT CENTER RIGHT TOP 8, 5 0, 0 6, 3 BOTTOM 0, 0 7, 6 6, 3

Microeconomic Theory Jamison / Kohlberg / Avery Problem Set 4 Solutions Spring 2012. (a) LEFT CENTER RIGHT TOP 8, 5 0, 0 6, 3 BOTTOM 0, 0 7, 6 6, 3 Microeconomic Theory Jamison / Kohlberg / Avery Problem Set 4 Solutions Spring 2012 1. Subgame Perfect Equilibrium and Dominance (a) LEFT CENTER RIGHT TOP 8, 5 0, 0 6, 3 BOTTOM 0, 0 7, 6 6, 3 Highlighting

More information

Games of Incomplete Information

Games of Incomplete Information Games of Incomplete Information Jonathan Levin February 00 Introduction We now start to explore models of incomplete information. Informally, a game of incomplete information is a game where the players

More information

1 if 1 x 0 1 if 0 x 1

1 if 1 x 0 1 if 0 x 1 Chapter 3 Continuity In this chapter we begin by defining the fundamental notion of continuity for real valued functions of a single real variable. When trying to decide whether a given function is or

More information

A Game Theoretical Framework for Adversarial Learning

A Game Theoretical Framework for Adversarial Learning A Game Theoretical Framework for Adversarial Learning Murat Kantarcioglu University of Texas at Dallas Richardson, TX 75083, USA muratk@utdallas Chris Clifton Purdue University West Lafayette, IN 47907,

More information

Introduction to Topology

Introduction to Topology Introduction to Topology Tomoo Matsumura November 30, 2010 Contents 1 Topological spaces 3 1.1 Basis of a Topology......................................... 3 1.2 Comparing Topologies.......................................

More information

Christmas Gift Exchange Games

Christmas Gift Exchange Games Christmas Gift Exchange Games Arpita Ghosh 1 and Mohammad Mahdian 1 Yahoo! Research Santa Clara, CA, USA. Email: arpita@yahoo-inc.com, mahdian@alum.mit.edu Abstract. The Christmas gift exchange is a popular

More information

3. Mathematical Induction

3. Mathematical Induction 3. MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION 83 3. Mathematical Induction 3.1. First Principle of Mathematical Induction. Let P (n) be a predicate with domain of discourse (over) the natural numbers N = {0, 1,,...}. If (1)

More information

Matrix Representations of Linear Transformations and Changes of Coordinates

Matrix Representations of Linear Transformations and Changes of Coordinates Matrix Representations of Linear Transformations and Changes of Coordinates 01 Subspaces and Bases 011 Definitions A subspace V of R n is a subset of R n that contains the zero element and is closed under

More information

MEASURE AND INTEGRATION. Dietmar A. Salamon ETH Zürich

MEASURE AND INTEGRATION. Dietmar A. Salamon ETH Zürich MEASURE AND INTEGRATION Dietmar A. Salamon ETH Zürich 12 May 2016 ii Preface This book is based on notes for the lecture course Measure and Integration held at ETH Zürich in the spring semester 2014. Prerequisites

More information

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2015

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2015 ECON 459 Game Theory Lecture Notes Auctions Luca Anderlini Spring 2015 These notes have been used before. If you can still spot any errors or have any suggestions for improvement, please let me know. 1

More information

How To Find Out How To Calculate A Premeasure On A Set Of Two-Dimensional Algebra

How To Find Out How To Calculate A Premeasure On A Set Of Two-Dimensional Algebra 54 CHAPTER 5 Product Measures Given two measure spaces, we may construct a natural measure on their Cartesian product; the prototype is the construction of Lebesgue measure on R 2 as the product of Lebesgue

More information

BANACH AND HILBERT SPACE REVIEW

BANACH AND HILBERT SPACE REVIEW BANACH AND HILBET SPACE EVIEW CHISTOPHE HEIL These notes will briefly review some basic concepts related to the theory of Banach and Hilbert spaces. We are not trying to give a complete development, but

More information

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Nathaniel Hendren January, 2014 Abstract Both Akerlof (1970) and Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976) show that

More information

Metric Spaces Joseph Muscat 2003 (Last revised May 2009)

Metric Spaces Joseph Muscat 2003 (Last revised May 2009) 1 Distance J Muscat 1 Metric Spaces Joseph Muscat 2003 (Last revised May 2009) (A revised and expanded version of these notes are now published by Springer.) 1 Distance A metric space can be thought of

More information

ECO 199 B GAMES OF STRATEGY Spring Term 2004 PROBLEM SET 4 B DRAFT ANSWER KEY 100-3 90-99 21 80-89 14 70-79 4 0-69 11

ECO 199 B GAMES OF STRATEGY Spring Term 2004 PROBLEM SET 4 B DRAFT ANSWER KEY 100-3 90-99 21 80-89 14 70-79 4 0-69 11 The distribution of grades was as follows. ECO 199 B GAMES OF STRATEGY Spring Term 2004 PROBLEM SET 4 B DRAFT ANSWER KEY Range Numbers 100-3 90-99 21 80-89 14 70-79 4 0-69 11 Question 1: 30 points Games

More information

Compact Representations and Approximations for Compuation in Games

Compact Representations and Approximations for Compuation in Games Compact Representations and Approximations for Compuation in Games Kevin Swersky April 23, 2008 Abstract Compact representations have recently been developed as a way of both encoding the strategic interactions

More information

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 2

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 2 CS 70 Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 2 Proofs Intuitively, the concept of proof should already be familiar We all like to assert things, and few of us

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 1: Introduction

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 1: Introduction 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 1: Introduction Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 2, 2010 1 Introduction Optimization Theory: Optimize a single objective over a decision variable x R

More information

Mathematical Induction

Mathematical Induction Mathematical Induction (Handout March 8, 01) The Principle of Mathematical Induction provides a means to prove infinitely many statements all at once The principle is logical rather than strictly mathematical,

More information

On strong fairness in UNITY

On strong fairness in UNITY On strong fairness in UNITY H.P.Gumm, D.Zhukov Fachbereich Mathematik und Informatik Philipps Universität Marburg {gumm,shukov}@mathematik.uni-marburg.de Abstract. In [6] Tsay and Bagrodia present a correct

More information

THE BANACH CONTRACTION PRINCIPLE. Contents

THE BANACH CONTRACTION PRINCIPLE. Contents THE BANACH CONTRACTION PRINCIPLE ALEX PONIECKI Abstract. This paper will study contractions of metric spaces. To do this, we will mainly use tools from topology. We will give some examples of contractions,

More information

Gambling Systems and Multiplication-Invariant Measures

Gambling Systems and Multiplication-Invariant Measures Gambling Systems and Multiplication-Invariant Measures by Jeffrey S. Rosenthal* and Peter O. Schwartz** (May 28, 997.. Introduction. This short paper describes a surprising connection between two previously

More information

1 The Brownian bridge construction

1 The Brownian bridge construction The Brownian bridge construction The Brownian bridge construction is a way to build a Brownian motion path by successively adding finer scale detail. This construction leads to a relatively easy proof

More information

Basic Concepts of Point Set Topology Notes for OU course Math 4853 Spring 2011

Basic Concepts of Point Set Topology Notes for OU course Math 4853 Spring 2011 Basic Concepts of Point Set Topology Notes for OU course Math 4853 Spring 2011 A. Miller 1. Introduction. The definitions of metric space and topological space were developed in the early 1900 s, largely

More information

i/io as compared to 4/10 for players 2 and 3. A "correct" way to play Certainly many interesting games are not solvable by this definition.

i/io as compared to 4/10 for players 2 and 3. A correct way to play Certainly many interesting games are not solvable by this definition. 496 MATHEMATICS: D. GALE PROC. N. A. S. A THEORY OF N-PERSON GAMES WITH PERFECT INFORMA TION* By DAVID GALE BROWN UNIVBRSITY Communicated by J. von Neumann, April 17, 1953 1. Introduction.-The theory of

More information

23. RATIONAL EXPONENTS

23. RATIONAL EXPONENTS 23. RATIONAL EXPONENTS renaming radicals rational numbers writing radicals with rational exponents When serious work needs to be done with radicals, they are usually changed to a name that uses exponents,

More information

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces Dan Collins The textbook defines a subspace of a vector space in Chapter 4, but it avoids ever discussing the notion of a quotient space. This is understandable

More information

Bayesian Nash Equilibrium

Bayesian Nash Equilibrium . Bayesian Nash Equilibrium . In the final two weeks: Goals Understand what a game of incomplete information (Bayesian game) is Understand how to model static Bayesian games Be able to apply Bayes Nash

More information

The sample space for a pair of die rolls is the set. The sample space for a random number between 0 and 1 is the interval [0, 1].

The sample space for a pair of die rolls is the set. The sample space for a random number between 0 and 1 is the interval [0, 1]. Probability Theory Probability Spaces and Events Consider a random experiment with several possible outcomes. For example, we might roll a pair of dice, flip a coin three times, or choose a random real

More information

1 Error in Euler s Method

1 Error in Euler s Method 1 Error in Euler s Method Experience with Euler s 1 method raises some interesting questions about numerical approximations for the solutions of differential equations. 1. What determines the amount of

More information

When is Reputation Bad? The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters.

When is Reputation Bad? The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. When is Reputation Bad? he Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation Published Version Accessed Citable Link erms

More information

Geometrical Characterization of RN-operators between Locally Convex Vector Spaces

Geometrical Characterization of RN-operators between Locally Convex Vector Spaces Geometrical Characterization of RN-operators between Locally Convex Vector Spaces OLEG REINOV St. Petersburg State University Dept. of Mathematics and Mechanics Universitetskii pr. 28, 198504 St, Petersburg

More information

6.3 Conditional Probability and Independence

6.3 Conditional Probability and Independence 222 CHAPTER 6. PROBABILITY 6.3 Conditional Probability and Independence Conditional Probability Two cubical dice each have a triangle painted on one side, a circle painted on two sides and a square painted

More information

x a x 2 (1 + x 2 ) n.

x a x 2 (1 + x 2 ) n. Limits and continuity Suppose that we have a function f : R R. Let a R. We say that f(x) tends to the limit l as x tends to a; lim f(x) = l ; x a if, given any real number ɛ > 0, there exists a real number

More information

Peer Pressure. June 28, 2008 Revised: April 18, 2009 Forthcoming in the Journal of the European Economic Association. Abstract

Peer Pressure. June 28, 2008 Revised: April 18, 2009 Forthcoming in the Journal of the European Economic Association. Abstract Peer Pressure Antoni Calvó-Armengol and Matthew O. Jackson June 28, 2008 Revised: April 18, 2009 Forthcoming in the Journal of the European Economic Association Abstract We present a model where agents

More information

Maximum Likelihood Estimation

Maximum Likelihood Estimation Math 541: Statistical Theory II Lecturer: Songfeng Zheng Maximum Likelihood Estimation 1 Maximum Likelihood Estimation Maximum likelihood is a relatively simple method of constructing an estimator for

More information

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium When players move sequentially and have private information, some of the Bayesian Nash equilibria may involve strategies that are not sequentially rational. The problem is

More information

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 10

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 10 CS 70 Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 10 Introduction to Discrete Probability Probability theory has its origins in gambling analyzing card games, dice,

More information

Bad Reputation. March 26, 2002

Bad Reputation. March 26, 2002 Bad Reputation Jeffrey C. Ely Juuso Välimäki March 26, 2002 Abstract We study the classical reputation model in which a long-run player faces a sequence of short-run players and would like to establish

More information

Capital Structure. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Capital Structure. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Capital Structure Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania 1 Debt and Equity There are two main types of financing: debt and equity. Consider a two-period world with dates 0 and 1. At

More information

I d Rather Stay Stupid: The Advantage of Having Low Utility

I d Rather Stay Stupid: The Advantage of Having Low Utility I d Rather Stay Stupid: The Advantage of Having Low Utility Lior Seeman Department of Computer Science Cornell University lseeman@cs.cornell.edu Abstract Motivated by cost of computation in game theory,

More information

Some other convex-valued selection theorems 147 (2) Every lower semicontinuous mapping F : X! IR such that for every x 2 X, F (x) is either convex and

Some other convex-valued selection theorems 147 (2) Every lower semicontinuous mapping F : X! IR such that for every x 2 X, F (x) is either convex and PART B: RESULTS x1. CHARACTERIZATION OF NORMALITY- TYPE PROPERTIES 1. Some other convex-valued selection theorems In this section all multivalued mappings are assumed to have convex values in some Banach

More information

4.5 Linear Dependence and Linear Independence

4.5 Linear Dependence and Linear Independence 4.5 Linear Dependence and Linear Independence 267 32. {v 1, v 2 }, where v 1, v 2 are collinear vectors in R 3. 33. Prove that if S and S are subsets of a vector space V such that S is a subset of S, then

More information

IEOR 6711: Stochastic Models I Fall 2012, Professor Whitt, Tuesday, September 11 Normal Approximations and the Central Limit Theorem

IEOR 6711: Stochastic Models I Fall 2012, Professor Whitt, Tuesday, September 11 Normal Approximations and the Central Limit Theorem IEOR 6711: Stochastic Models I Fall 2012, Professor Whitt, Tuesday, September 11 Normal Approximations and the Central Limit Theorem Time on my hands: Coin tosses. Problem Formulation: Suppose that I have

More information

Modern Optimization Methods for Big Data Problems MATH11146 The University of Edinburgh

Modern Optimization Methods for Big Data Problems MATH11146 The University of Edinburgh Modern Optimization Methods for Big Data Problems MATH11146 The University of Edinburgh Peter Richtárik Week 3 Randomized Coordinate Descent With Arbitrary Sampling January 27, 2016 1 / 30 The Problem

More information

The Prison S Dilemma and Its Connections

The Prison S Dilemma and Its Connections Games Played in a Contracting Environment V. Bhaskar Department of Economics University College London Gower Street London WC1 6BT February 2008 Abstract We analyze normal form games where a player has

More information

Reading 13 : Finite State Automata and Regular Expressions

Reading 13 : Finite State Automata and Regular Expressions CS/Math 24: Introduction to Discrete Mathematics Fall 25 Reading 3 : Finite State Automata and Regular Expressions Instructors: Beck Hasti, Gautam Prakriya In this reading we study a mathematical model

More information

k, then n = p2α 1 1 pα k

k, then n = p2α 1 1 pα k Powers of Integers An integer n is a perfect square if n = m for some integer m. Taking into account the prime factorization, if m = p α 1 1 pα k k, then n = pα 1 1 p α k k. That is, n is a perfect square

More information

Finite dimensional topological vector spaces

Finite dimensional topological vector spaces Chapter 3 Finite dimensional topological vector spaces 3.1 Finite dimensional Hausdorff t.v.s. Let X be a vector space over the field K of real or complex numbers. We know from linear algebra that the

More information

SECTION 10-2 Mathematical Induction

SECTION 10-2 Mathematical Induction 73 0 Sequences and Series 6. Approximate e 0. using the first five terms of the series. Compare this approximation with your calculator evaluation of e 0.. 6. Approximate e 0.5 using the first five terms

More information

F. ABTAHI and M. ZARRIN. (Communicated by J. Goldstein)

F. ABTAHI and M. ZARRIN. (Communicated by J. Goldstein) Journal of Algerian Mathematical Society Vol. 1, pp. 1 6 1 CONCERNING THE l p -CONJECTURE FOR DISCRETE SEMIGROUPS F. ABTAHI and M. ZARRIN (Communicated by J. Goldstein) Abstract. For 2 < p

More information

Equilibrium computation: Part 1

Equilibrium computation: Part 1 Equilibrium computation: Part 1 Nicola Gatti 1 Troels Bjerre Sorensen 2 1 Politecnico di Milano, Italy 2 Duke University, USA Nicola Gatti and Troels Bjerre Sørensen ( Politecnico di Milano, Italy, Equilibrium

More information

God created the integers and the rest is the work of man. (Leopold Kronecker, in an after-dinner speech at a conference, Berlin, 1886)

God created the integers and the rest is the work of man. (Leopold Kronecker, in an after-dinner speech at a conference, Berlin, 1886) Chapter 2 Numbers God created the integers and the rest is the work of man. (Leopold Kronecker, in an after-dinner speech at a conference, Berlin, 1886) God created the integers and the rest is the work

More information

I. GROUPS: BASIC DEFINITIONS AND EXAMPLES

I. GROUPS: BASIC DEFINITIONS AND EXAMPLES I GROUPS: BASIC DEFINITIONS AND EXAMPLES Definition 1: An operation on a set G is a function : G G G Definition 2: A group is a set G which is equipped with an operation and a special element e G, called

More information

Fixed Point Theorems

Fixed Point Theorems Fixed Point Theorems Definition: Let X be a set and let T : X X be a function that maps X into itself. (Such a function is often called an operator, a transformation, or a transform on X, and the notation

More information

Games Manipulators Play

Games Manipulators Play Games Manipulators Play Umberto Grandi Department of Mathematics University of Padova 23 January 2014 [Joint work with Edith Elkind, Francesca Rossi and Arkadii Slinko] Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem All

More information

Dynamics and Equilibria

Dynamics and Equilibria Dynamics and Equilibria Sergiu Hart Presidential Address, GAMES 2008 (July 2008) Revised and Expanded (November 2009) Revised (2010, 2011, 2012, 2013) SERGIU HART c 2008 p. 1 DYNAMICS AND EQUILIBRIA Sergiu

More information

The Graphical Method: An Example

The Graphical Method: An Example The Graphical Method: An Example Consider the following linear program: Maximize 4x 1 +3x 2 Subject to: 2x 1 +3x 2 6 (1) 3x 1 +2x 2 3 (2) 2x 2 5 (3) 2x 1 +x 2 4 (4) x 1, x 2 0, where, for ease of reference,

More information

Extension of measure

Extension of measure 1 Extension of measure Sayan Mukherjee Dynkin s π λ theorem We will soon need to define probability measures on infinite and possible uncountable sets, like the power set of the naturals. This is hard.

More information

Elements of probability theory

Elements of probability theory 2 Elements of probability theory Probability theory provides mathematical models for random phenomena, that is, phenomena which under repeated observations yield di erent outcomes that cannot be predicted

More information

Vector and Matrix Norms

Vector and Matrix Norms Chapter 1 Vector and Matrix Norms 11 Vector Spaces Let F be a field (such as the real numbers, R, or complex numbers, C) with elements called scalars A Vector Space, V, over the field F is a non-empty

More information

Definition 11.1. Given a graph G on n vertices, we define the following quantities:

Definition 11.1. Given a graph G on n vertices, we define the following quantities: Lecture 11 The Lovász ϑ Function 11.1 Perfect graphs We begin with some background on perfect graphs. graphs. First, we define some quantities on Definition 11.1. Given a graph G on n vertices, we define

More information

Lecture Notes on Measure Theory and Functional Analysis

Lecture Notes on Measure Theory and Functional Analysis Lecture Notes on Measure Theory and Functional Analysis P. Cannarsa & T. D Aprile Dipartimento di Matematica Università di Roma Tor Vergata cannarsa@mat.uniroma2.it daprile@mat.uniroma2.it aa 2006/07 Contents

More information

Online Appendix to Stochastic Imitative Game Dynamics with Committed Agents

Online Appendix to Stochastic Imitative Game Dynamics with Committed Agents Online Appendix to Stochastic Imitative Game Dynamics with Committed Agents William H. Sandholm January 6, 22 O.. Imitative protocols, mean dynamics, and equilibrium selection In this section, we consider

More information

Section 1.3 P 1 = 1 2. = 1 4 2 8. P n = 1 P 3 = Continuing in this fashion, it should seem reasonable that, for any n = 1, 2, 3,..., = 1 2 4.

Section 1.3 P 1 = 1 2. = 1 4 2 8. P n = 1 P 3 = Continuing in this fashion, it should seem reasonable that, for any n = 1, 2, 3,..., = 1 2 4. Difference Equations to Differential Equations Section. The Sum of a Sequence This section considers the problem of adding together the terms of a sequence. Of course, this is a problem only if more than

More information

Lecture 11: Sponsored search

Lecture 11: Sponsored search Computational Learning Theory Spring Semester, 2009/10 Lecture 11: Sponsored search Lecturer: Yishay Mansour Scribe: Ben Pere, Jonathan Heimann, Alon Levin 11.1 Sponsored Search 11.1.1 Introduction Search

More information

Fairness with an Honest Minority and a Rational Majority

Fairness with an Honest Minority and a Rational Majority Fairness with an Honest Minority and a Rational Majority The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation Published

More information

10 Evolutionarily Stable Strategies

10 Evolutionarily Stable Strategies 10 Evolutionarily Stable Strategies There is but a step between the sublime and the ridiculous. Leo Tolstoy In 1973 the biologist John Maynard Smith and the mathematician G. R. Price wrote an article in

More information