1 On differences between Complements and Adjuncts

Similar documents
Phrase Structure Rules, Tree Rewriting, and other sources of Recursion Structure within the NP

Structure of Clauses. March 9, 2004

Syntax: Phrases. 1. The phrase

Estudios de Asia y Africa Idiomas Modernas I What you should have learnt from Face2Face

Ling 201 Syntax 1. Jirka Hana April 10, 2006

According to the Argentine writer Jorge Luis Borges, in the Celestial Emporium of Benevolent Knowledge, animals are divided

SYNTAX: THE ANALYSIS OF SENTENCE STRUCTURE

Language at work To be Possessives

Syntactic and Semantic Differences between Nominal Relative Clauses and Dependent wh-interrogative Clauses

Online Tutoring System For Essay Writing

English auxiliary verbs

The parts of speech: the basic labels

Rethinking the relationship between transitive and intransitive verbs

MARY. V NP NP Subject Formation WANT BILL S

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 3: Covert Movement vs. Type Shifting 1

Sentence Structure/Sentence Types HANDOUT

The Structure of English Language - Clause Functions

English Appendix 2: Vocabulary, grammar and punctuation

Pupil SPAG Card 1. Terminology for pupils. I Can Date Word

Unit 1. Language at work Present simple and continuous. Present simple. Present continuous

Year 3 Grammar Guide. For Children and Parents MARCHWOOD JUNIOR SCHOOL

English Grammar Passive Voice and Other Items

GMAT.cz GMAT.cz KET (Key English Test) Preparating Course Syllabus

Get Ready for IELTS Writing. About Get Ready for IELTS Writing. Part 1: Language development. Part 2: Skills development. Part 3: Exam practice

I have eaten. The plums that were in the ice box

Nouns are naming words - they are used to name a person, place or thing.

Parts of Speech. Skills Team, University of Hull

English. Universidad Virtual. Curso de sensibilización a la PAEP (Prueba de Admisión a Estudios de Posgrado) Parts of Speech. Nouns.

LESSON THIRTEEN STRUCTURAL AMBIGUITY. Structural ambiguity is also referred to as syntactic ambiguity or grammatical ambiguity.

Morphology. Morphology is the study of word formation, of the structure of words. 1. some words can be divided into parts which still have meaning

stress, intonation and pauses and pronounce English sounds correctly. (b) To speak accurately to the listener(s) about one s thoughts and feelings,

Sample only Oxford University Press ANZ

THERE ARE SEVERAL KINDS OF PRONOUNS:

GESE Initial steps. Guide for teachers, Grades 1 3. GESE Grade 1 Introduction

Albert Pye and Ravensmere Schools Grammar Curriculum

Non-nominal Which-Relatives

Grammar and Mechanics Test 3

Glossary of literacy terms

Chapter 13, Sections Auxiliary Verbs CSLI Publications

Index. 344 Grammar and Language Workbook, Grade 8

IP PATTERNS OF MOVEMENTS IN VSO TYPOLOGY: THE CASE OF ARABIC

Constraints in Phrase Structure Grammar

Compound Sentences and Coordination

Nouns may show possession or ownership. Use an apostrophe with a noun to show something belongs to someone or to something.

7.5 Emphatic Verb Tense

Mixed Sentence Structure Problem: Double Verb Error

Checklist for Recognizing Complete Verbs

REPORTED SPEECH. Reported speech is used to retell or report what other person has actually said. It is a very usual function in everyday language.

Year 7. Grammar booklet 3 and tasks Sentences, phrases and clauses

The structure of the English Sentence

Bullying 101: Guide for Middle and High School Students

Points of Interference in Learning English as a Second Language

Making Inferences Picture #1

Handouts for Conversation Partners: Grammar

Paraphrasing controlled English texts

THEME: Jesus wants us to grow in Him and be holy.

Pronouns. Their different types and roles. Devised by Jo Killmister, Skills Enhancement Program, Newcastle Business School

MODIFIERS. There are many different types of modifiers. Let's begin by taking a look at the most common ones.

KET for Schools Reading and Writing Part 9 teacher s notes

19. Morphosyntax in L2A

Cross-linguistic differences in the interpretation of sentences with more than one QP: German (Frey 1993) and Hungarian (É Kiss 1991)

A Comparative Analysis of Standard American English and British English. with respect to the Auxiliary Verbs

Gerunds, Participles, and Infinitives

Sentence Blocks. Sentence Focus Activity. Contents

Grammar Unit: Pronouns

The 5 P s in Problem Solving *prob lem: a source of perplexity, distress, or vexation. *solve: to find a solution, explanation, or answer for

Self-Acceptance. A Frog Thing by E. Drachman (2005) California: Kidwick Books LLC. ISBN Grade Level: Third grade

Sentences: Kinds and Parts

Outline of today s lecture

Keep your English up to date 4. Teacher s pack Lesson plan and student worksheets with answers. Facebook

The compositional semantics of same

The Book of Grammar Lesson Six. Mr. McBride AP Language and Composition

POLITE ENGLISH. Giving advice FREE ON-LINE COURSE. Lesson 2: version without a key SZKOLENIA JĘZYKOWE DLA FIRM ZREALIZUJEMY TWÓJ CEL!

Three Ways to Clarify Your Writing

A test based on the grammar-grade one

Cambridge English: Advanced Speaking Sample test with examiner s comments

L130: Chapter 5d. Dr. Shannon Bischoff. Dr. Shannon Bischoff () L130: Chapter 5d 1 / 25

Double Genitives in English

Structural Ambiguity for English Teachers

PUSD High Frequency Word List

B.A. ENGLISH ENTRANCE TEST

Writing Topics WRITING TOPICS

An adverb clause is a dependent clause that modifies a verb, adjective or another adverb. It usually modifies the verb.

Adjective, Adverb, Noun Clauses. Gerund,Participial and Infinitive Phrases. English Department

The English Relative Clause*

openmind 1 Practice Online

Simple Present Tense. Simple Present Tense in the Negative. Grammar Practice Worksheets

Holy Family Canossian College Second Term Test Form 1 English

Modal Verbs. Modal verbs for BSL are Can, Must, Should, Want (these are productive requirements)

Writing Thesis Defense Papers

CELC Benchmark Essays Set 3 Prompt:

Reading aloud to a child

2. Argument Structure & Standardization

Early Morphological Development

The finite verb and the clause: IP

Lecture 9. Phrases: Subject/Predicate. English 3318: Studies in English Grammar. Dr. Svetlana Nuernberg

Assessing Writing Performance Level B1

Arguments and Dialogues

Comparatives, Superlatives, Diminutives

Constituency. The basic units of sentence structure

Transcription:

(1) a student of Physics with long hair Syntax 380L September 18, 2001 Φ D specifier a N student N 0 N 0 Φ Φ Φ PP complement Φ Φ P of N Physics PP adjunct Φ Φ P with long hair 1 On differences between Complements and Adjuncts 1.1 Semantic Arguments Each N 0 denotes a semantic property. To attribute (1) to someone is to attribute two properties to them - one of studying Physics and another of having long hair. On the other hand, (2a, b) both involve only one property attribution: that of being a student in (2a) and that of studying Physics in (2b). (2) a. John is a student. b. John is a student of Physics. Note that the post-copular 1 s contain only one N 0 each. On the other hand, (1) contains two N 0 s and involves two property attributions. ffl In some cases, PPs are quite unambiguously either adjuncts (with long hair) or complements (of Physics). In most cases, however, PPs don t so wear their complement/adjunct status on their sleeves. Consider the ambiguous (3). (3) a student [of high moral principles] a. a person who studies high moral principles b. a student who has high moral principles This ambiguity can be characterized in structural terms: on the reading in (3a), the PP of high moral principles is a complement of student, while on the reading in (3b), the PP of high moral principles is an adjunct. A similar point is made by (4). (4) a. Arguments [with Tim] are often pointless. (complement) b. Arguments [with few premises] are often pointless. (adjunct) 1 be is also called the copula. a post-copular is an that follows the copula.

Evidence for the proposal that with Tim in (4a) is a complement and that with few premises in (4b) is an adjunct comes from the contrast in (5). (5) a. Arguments [with Tim] [with few premises] are often pointless. b. *Arguments [with few premises] [with Tim] are often pointless. 1.2 Syntactic Arguments (6) Phrase Structure Rules for Noun Phrases a. N 00! DN 0 (Determiner Rule) b. N 0! N 0 PP (Adjunct Rule) c. N 0! N (PP) (Complement Rule) One consequence of these rules that we saw last time is that a complement must precede an adjunct. (7) a. a student [of Physics] [with long hair] b. * a student [with long hair] [of Physics] These rules have other consequences too. Note that the adjunct rule is recursive i.e. in principle, it could apply an arbitrarily large number of times. On the other hand, the complement rule is not recursive i.e. it can apply only once. These predictions are borne out: (8) a. a student [with long hair] [with short arms] b. * a student [of Physics] [of Chemistry] Further, unlike complements which have to precede adjuncts, adjuncts can be freely reordered with respect to each other. (9) a. a student [with long hair] [with short arms] b. a student [with short arms] [with long hair] 1.2.1 Co-ordination Complements can be co-ordinated with other complements. (10) a student [of Physics] and [of Chemistry] Likewise, adjuncts can be co-ordinated with other adjuncts. (11) a student [with short arms] and [with long hair] But adjunct PPs and complements PPs cannot be co-ordinated. (12) a. * a student [of Physics] and [with short arms] b. * a student [with short arms] and [of Physics] Since a students of Physics and professors with long hair are both N 0 s, our analysis predicts that it should be possible to co-ordinate them. (13) the [ [students of Physics] and [professors with long hair]] 2

1.2.2 Extraposition Adjuncts are less tightly bound to the head noun than complements. This can be seen by the fact that it is possible to extrapose adjuncts PPs but not possible to extrapose complement PPs. (14) a. (?) A student came to see me yesterday [with long hair]. b. * A student came to see me yesterday [of Physics]. 1.2.3 Preposing Complements and Adjuncts behave differently with respect to preposing. (15) a. [What branch of Physics] is Jack a student of? b. * [What kind of hair] is Paco a student with? (Note that Complements and Adjuncts go in opposite directions with respect Extraposition and Preposing.) 1.3 Co-occurrence Restrictions eads place significant restrictions (i.e. subcategorise) on what can appear as their complement. (16) a. a student of Physics b. * a boy of Physics c. * a girl of Physics d. * a teenager of Physics e. * a goth of Physics No similar restrictions are imposed on adjuncts. (17) a. a student with long hair b. a boy with long hair c. a girl with long hair d. a teenager with long hair e. a goth with long hair Generalisation: heads are more closely related to their complements than to their adjuncts. Subcategorisation restrictions hold only between a head and its complement, not between a head and its adjuncts. 1.4 Some more examples Complements: (18) a. your reply [to my letter] b. the attack [on Starr] c. the loss [of the ship] 3

d. Joan s disgust [at Tamara s behavior] e. his disillusionment [with life] Adjuncts: (19) a. the book [on the table] b. the advertisement [on the television] c. the fight [after the match] d. his resignation [because of the scandal] e. a cup [with a broken handle] 1.5 Non-PP Complements and Adjuncts So far we have only considered cases of PP complements and adjuncts. Can other kinds of phrases also be complements/adjuncts of nouns? Complements: It seems that only PPs and full clauses (Ss) can be complements of nouns. (20) a. the suggestion [that we should abandon ship] b. the demand [for him to resign] c. the question [whether euthanasia is ethical] On the other hand, a much wider range of phrases can occur as adjuncts e.g. temporal s, APs, and Relative Clauses. (21) a. the [ [ N 0 abolition of taxes] [ next year]] b. the [ [ N 0 students of Physics] [ AP absent from class]] c. the [ [ N 0 king of England] [ S who abdicated]] The greater freedom found with adjuncts reflects the fact that fewer restrictions are imposed by a head on its adjuncts than on its complement. 1.6 Complex s What happens when the PP complement or adjunct itself contains a non-trivial (i.e. an with internal structure)? (22) a. an advocate of the abolition of indirect taxation b. a woman with an umbrella with a red handle c. his dislike of men with big egos ow can we account for the ambiguity of (23)? (23) a woman with three children with ginger hair 4

2 Prenominal Modifiers Nouns can have three different kinds of prenominal (i.e. preceding the noun) modifiers: Determiners: a Attributes (Prenominal Adjuncts): Cambridge Complements: Physics (24) a [Cambridge][Physics] student We already have the following two phrase structure rules: (25) a. N 00! DN 0 (Determiner Rule) b. N 0! N 0 PP (Adjunct Rule) c. N 0! N (PP) (Complement Rule) In addition, we will add the following two rules: (26) a. N 0! N 0 (Adjunct Rule) b. N 0! () N (Complement Rule) Consider the two readings of (24): (27) a. a student of Physics in Cambridge b. a student of Cambridge Physics (as opposed to New York Physics) The case of (27b) is somewhat straightforward so we can set it aside for now. As for (27a), we know from our discussion on postnominal modifiers that in (27a), of Physics is a complement and in Cambridge is an adjunct. If we want to maintain maximal structural symmetry between (24) and its postnominal version in (27a), we are led to the following structure for the reading of (24) paraphrased by (27a). (28) N 00 Φ N 0 D a Cambridge Φ N 0 Physics N student 2.1 Evidence for the above tree ffl Ordering: We know that complements have to be closer to the head than adjuncts while adjuncts can be more freely reordered with respect to each other. Note that Cambridge and Physics cannot be reordered. Physics has to be closer to the head noun. (29) a. a [Cambridge] [Physics] student 5

b. * a [Physics] [Cambridge] student ffl Co-ordination: Prenominal adjuncts cannot be co-ordinated with prenominal complements. (30) a. * several [[Physics] and [Cambridge]] students b. * several [[Cambridge] and [Physics]] students c. several [[Physics] and [Chemistry]] students d. several [[Cambridge] and [New York]] students Also since both Physics student and Cambridge Physics student are N 0 s, they can both be co-ordinated with another N 0. (31) a. a Cambridge [hockey player and Physics student] b. a [hockey player and Cambridge Physics student] ffl Recursion: The attribute/adjunct rule is recursive, the complement rule is not. This means that we can have an arbitrarily large number of attribute/adjuncts but only one complement. (32) a. * a Physics Economics Agriculture student b. a [Cambridge] [middle class] student c. a [middle class] [Cambridge] student 2.2 The Prenominal/Postnominal Parallel In general, for most postnominal structures, whether they involve complements or adjuncts, we can produce corresponding prenominal structures. (33) a. i. the ban [on controversial art] (Complement) ii. the [controversial art] ban b. i. recruitment [of personnel] (Complement) ii. [personnel] recruitment c. i. the shop [on the corner] (Adjunct) ii. the [corner] shop d. i. the lady [of iron] (Adjunct) ii. the iron lady owever, there is a difference - only nominals can occur in the preverbal position. Unlike postnominal modifiers which could be PPs, prenominal modifiers can only be s or adjectives 2. Not all postnominal modifiers can be paraphrased by prenominal modifiers: (34) a. the carrot [on the pan] b. * the [on the carrot] pan c. * the [pan] carrot Further the meaning of a prenominal modifer, esp. if it is an adjunct, can differ substantially from the postnominal PP version. 2 Also participles as in the eaten apple. 6

(35) a. the book [on the coffee table] b. the [coffee table] book A book kept on the coffee-table is not the same thing as a coffee-table book. 3 Adjectival Premodifiers So far, we have only considered nominal attributes. Where do adjectives fit into the picture? (36) a. a [really excellent] book b. a [patently obvious] lie For the most part, adjectival premodifiers are like premodifiers. We can handle them by adding the following rule: (37) N 0! AP N 0 (Adjunct AP Rule) Points to consider: ffl recursiveness ffl Ambiguity of cases like: (38) an English teacher a. someone who teaches English b. someone who teaches, and who is English 4 S in X 0 -theory 4.1 VP in X 0 -theory In (39), the the city is the comeplement of the verb destroy. (39) The Romans [ VP destroyed [ the city]]. What goes into the [Spec, VP] position? Let us consider the case of nominalizations: (40) The Romans destruction of the city Φ Φ The Romans N 0 N destruction PP Φ Φ P of the city 7

In (40), we see that all the arguments of N occur within its own phrase (maximal projection). A natural idea, within the spirit of cross-categorial symmetry, is to extend the idea that all the arguments of a head should occur within its own phrase (maximal projection). This gives us the tree in (42) for (41). (41) The Romans destroyed the city. (42) XP Φ The Romans X 0 Φ X -ed specifier The Romans VP Φ V 0 V destroy But there is no The Romans inside the VP? Yes, there isn t because now it is in the [Spec, XP]. Questions: 1. What is XP? 2. Why does the move from [Spec, VP] to [Spec, XP]? We will answer Question 1 in this section and Question 2 in the next. complement the city 4.2 What is XP? XP=S owever, if XP = S, what is X 0, the head of XP = S? We know from our discussion of X 0 theory that every XP has to have a head of the same kind i.e. XP cannot be headed by Y 0. This property is know as endocentricity. Now let us consider how we have been analyzing cases like (43). (43) Mark believes that Laetitia should kiss Ophelia. S 0 Φ Φ Comp that Laetitia S Modal should VP Φ Φ V kiss Ophelia 8

Neither S nor S 0 are endocentric. ow can we reformulate S and S 0 so that they are endocentric and fit within the X 0 -schema? ffl Approach 1: The element which we have labeled Modal could be head of S. This is the most natural approach because: (i) heads are atmost lexical items (there may be heads that are smaller than words). (ii) S has only three constituents, out of which Modal is the only lexical item What then about cases which don t have a modal such as (44a, b)? (44) a. Mark believes that Laetitia is kissing Ophelia (right now). b. Mark believes that Laetitia kissed Ophelia (yesterday). (44a) is easier to take care of. We can just create a class of Auxiliary verbs which includes all modal verbs, be and one kind of have. But cases like (44b) pose a greater challenge. One option is to say what we have been saying up until now i.e. the following structure: (45) S Φ Φ Φ Laetitia VP Φ Φ V kissed Ophelia The immediate problem for this representation is that there is no candidate for the head of S. The immediate constituents of S are and VP and neither of them are heads. So we seem to be stuck. At this point we should look back to cases of VP-preposing (VP-topicalization). We had seen there that some kinds of VPs could be preposed but others couldn t: (46) a. [ VP Kiss Ophelia], Laetitia did. b. *[ VP Kissed Ophelia], Laetitia. c. *[ VP Kissed Ophelia], Laetitia did. A similar point can be made with pseudoclefts (cf. 47a). (47) a. What Ophelia did was [ VP kiss Ophelia]. b. *What Ophelia did was [ VP kissed Ophelia]. What distinguishes the grammatical examples in (46) and (47) from the ungrammatical examples? The grammatical cases involve VPs without tense/person/number marking. The verb appears in its bare form. VPs in the ungrammatical cases involve verbs which are marked for tense/person/number marking. In the case at hand, the verb kissed is marked for Past Tense. We want to distinguish between these two kinds of VPs and yet also retain a link between them. The solution lies in postulating a node Inflection where the inflectional information associated with a verb could be stored. This node Inflection will head a phrase InflectionP (IP) which will be equivalent to an S. 9

(48) Laetitia kissed Ophelia. (49) IP Φ Laetitia I 0 Φ I 0 -ed VP Φ specifier V 0 Laetitia V kiss complement Ophelia ffl Clearly, there has to be a way for the -ed suffix under I 0 and the verb kiss to combine. Inflection Proposal: An I 0 and a V 0 that heads the complement VP of the I 0 combine in the phonological output. i.e. when you try to pronounce the above tree, the I 0 node and the V 0 node combine and are pronounced together. Cases like (46b) are bad because they would involve topicalization of an I 0 and only full phrases can be moved around. (46c, 47b) are bad because there are two sets of tense/agreement markings floating around while there is only one I 0 to supply the information. 4.3 X 0 rules for IP Since we have adopted X 0 -theory, the form of the rules will be quite familiar: (50) a. I 00! Specifier I 0 b. I 0! IVP Complement We can now give a new definition of the notion subject of a sentence : The subject of a sentence is the that occurs in the [Spec, IP]. In English (and many other languages), the subject of a sentence agrees with the verb. What it means for a subject to agree with its verb is illustrated in (51). (51) a. John eats pizza. b. *John eat pizza. c. I eat pizza. d. *I eats pizza. This relationship between the verb and its subject can be stated extremely locally within our new system as the reflex if the Specifier-head relationship. (52) Agreement Rule: Copy the person-number features of the in [Spec, IP] on the I 0. The person-number features of an are also referred to as its ffi-features (phi-features). The ffi-features of some pronouns are shown below: 10

(53) a. I = [+1stperson; +singular] b. we = [+1stperson; +plural] c. you = [+2ndperson] d. s/he = [+3rdperson; +singular] e. they = [+3rdperson; +plural] In English, gender is not part of the verbal agreement system, so she and he can be taken to have the same ffi-features but in languages where they are part of the agreement system, they would also need to be represented. 4.4 What can go under I 0? In sentences without any auxiliary element, the inflection is all there is in I 0. owever, other elements can also appear under I 0. (54) a. I must/should/could [eat some waffles]. (Modals) b. I am [eating some waffles]. (be) c. I have [eaten some waffles today]. (auxiliary have) d. I did [not eat the waffles]. (auxiliary do) e. I want to [eat waffles].(infinitival to) Earlier we saw two syntactic processes - VP Topicalization and pseudocleft formation - which were sensitive to the presence of inflection. Another grammatical process that is sensitive to the presence of inflection is VP Ellipsis. VP Ellipsis in English involves a silent tenseless VP together with an overt realization of I 0. (55) a. Jerry shouldn t leave town. Bill should [ VP leave town]. b. Tyrone isn t eating waffles today, but Ken is [ VP is eating apples]. c. Max hasn t finished his homework, but Jose has [ VP finished his homework]. d. Ana doesn t want to leave, but Mona wants to [ VP leave]. e. Chunghye doesn t like unicorns, but Maribel does [ VP like unicorns]. (*Chunghye doesn t like unicorns, but Maribel [ VP likes unicorns].) Each of the elements in (54) has distinct properties. Let us consider them individually. To provide contrast, we will start by looking at one verbal element that cannot occur in I 0, namely a main verb. 4.4.1 Main Verbs Main verbs have non-tensed forms: past participles, present participles, and infinitival forms. (56) a. Talvin ate the pizza. b. Talvin has eaten the pizza. (past participle) c. Talvin is eating the pizza. (present participle) d. Talvin wants to eat the pizza. (infinitival form) 11

When negated or questioned, a form of the verb do is needed. Otherwise, the sentence is ungrammatical. (57) a. Talvin didn t eat the pizza. b. *Talvin eatn t the pizza. c. Did Talvin eat the pizza? d. *Eat Talvin the pizza? e. Why did Talvin eat the pizza? f. *Why ate Talvin the pizza? Cases such as these can be explained by noting that the presence of the negation disrupts the local relationship needed by the I 0 and the V 0 in order to combine together. 3 Crucially main verbs stay in V 0 and do not move to I 0. The verb do comes in and saves the day by giving a realization to the suffix in I 0, which could not have been pronounced on its own. This process is called do support. 4.4.2 Modals Modals are set apart by the fact that they can never occur in non-tensed environments. (58) a. *Talvin wants to must/should/could win this game. b. *[To must/should/could play baseball] is fun. Modals invert in questions and precede negation. 4 (59) a. Must/should/could Talvin win this game? b. Why must/should/could Talvin win this game? c. Talvin must/should/could not win this game. The facts follow if we assume that Modal verbs are always generated in a [+Tensed] I 0. Since modal verbs are generated in I 0, they can realize whatever features I 0 has and the I 0 does not need to be close to V 0. 4.4.3 Auxiliaries: be and have P erfect Unlike Modals, auxiliaries can occur in non-finite environments. (60) a. Talvin wants to be popular. b. Talvin wants to have been popular. owever, like modals, auxiliaries invert in questions and precede negation. 5 (61) a. Is Talvin winning this game? b. as Talvin won this game? 3 The structure is something like [IP [Negation [VP]]]. Where do adverbs go? 4 In fact, do-support is not a possibility here. 5 Do-support is not a possibility here either. Consider what happens with have to, possessive have. 12

c. Why is Talvin winning this game? d. Why has Talvin won this game? e. Talvin isn t winning this game. f. Talvin hasn t won this game. The above examples suggest that the auxiliaries have/be are generated in V 0 (like main verbs) but can move up to I 0 (unlike main verbs). 6 ffl to: only occurs in [-tense] I 0. ffl do: only occurs in [+tense] I 0 when the I 0 is unable to combine locally with V 0. 7 4.5 S 0 in X 0 theory S 0 as it stands is an exocentric projection i.e. it is not headed by a head of its own category. Actually, things are even worse. It is quite unclear whether S 0 has a head. (62) S 0 Comp that S Tim is nuts A neat solution, and one that is compatible with X 0 -theory is to take Comp as the head of S 0. In fact this solution is forced upon us since the only potential head among the immediate constituents of S 0 is Comp. We cannot look inside the S/IP for a head because the IP is a complete phrase by itself. Assuming the IP to be a complement of Comp, we have the following tree. (63) CP Φ Specifier C 0 Comp that IP Tim is nuts What goes into the [Spec, CP]? We will answer this question when we discuss wh-movement (questions, relative clauses etc.). We now move to discuss why the in [Spec, VP] moves to [Spec, IP]. The answer lies in the domain of Case Theory. 6 What does the tree look like now? 7 What about the other do? 13