Lecture Notes in Microeconomics

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Lecture Notes in Microeconomics"

Transcription

1 Lecture Notes in Microeconomics Lecturer: Adrien Vigier, University of Oslo Fall Foreword The aim of these notes is to provide a concise introduction to microeconomic modeling at the advanced undergraduate level No final year undergraduate student in economics is expected to find in these notes any concept or idea he is not already familiar with These old ideas will however be presented in a way that is likely to be new to most students at that stage in the course of their curriculum Some familiarity with the language of Mathematics will undoubtly help the reader of these notes While a number of key mathematical results are briefly presented in the appendix to these notes, these results are intended for immediate reference only In no way do they substitute an introductory course in real analysis Sydsaeter s Mathematical Analysis is an excellent reference for economists Those with a stronger background in Mathematics may want to use Rudin s Principles of Mathematical Analysis instead All introductory textbooks on microeconomics cover most of the material found in these notes, and indeed very often more than that Students are therefore encouraged to satisfy their curiosity by consulting alternative sources Rubinstein s outstanding Lecture Notes in Microeconomics for instance are freely available online Bear in mind however that any set of notes derives as much of its added value from what it chooses to leave out as from what it effectively contains Finally, while in principle usable on a stand-alone basis, these notes are primarily designed to support lectures Attending lectures should therefore help you improve your understanding of the material covered in the notes These notes are organized as follows Section 2 is devoted to the study of the consumer Section 21 elaborates a general framework in which to study issues related to consumption Section 22 illustrates some of the most important applications of the framework: intertemporal consumption (221), consumption under uncertainty (222), as well as labor supply 1

2 (223) We show in section 3 how our approach to consumption can be transferred over to think about production Section 4 introduces General Equilibrium Section 5 develops the concept of a financial asset That section unifies the applications covered in 22, and allows us to explicitly deal with temporal aspects of general equilibrium which constitute the theme of section 6 Results are divided into lemmas and propositions The lemmas tend to be purely technical results They are mere tools in the build-up to the propositions, in which the economic insights really lie Scattered in the text is also a series of questions While these questions are meant to give you an opportunity to exert the knowledge you have acquired, the results developed in them are often important complement to the material covered in the lectures As such they are part and parcel of these notes Sketch answers to all questions are provided in the Appendix More detailed answers will be given during the weekly seminars 2

3 2 The Consumer 21 General Framework Wherever possible, we will in these notes confine our analysis to a world containing two goods All results developed here naturally extend to higher dimensions, but our aim is to keep the analysis simple in order to focus on economic content Restricting attention to the 2-dimensional case also offers the great advantage of accommodating a complete graphical representation The ultimate foundation of our approach is the utility function, used to represent preferences 1 of the consumer over vectors of goods x = (x 1, x 2 ) A consumer having utility function u is one who prefers x to y iff u(x) > u(y) 2 Always bear in mind that utility functions are mere numerical tools used to represent underlying preferences In particular, if v is strictly increasing and a consumer has utility function u then v u is an equally valid utility function for that consumer A consumer s utility function is thus determined only up to an increasing transformation In principle, utility functions may take a variety of forms In order to make progress, one is bound to make certain restrictive assumptions regarding consumers preferences While these assumptions may to some extent be justified economically, their main asset is to greatly simplify the analysis of the model we build We will immediately state these assumptions in terms of utility functions You should convince yourself however that all these assumptions are preserved under any (smooth) increasing transformation This is critical, given we are claiming to make assumptions concerning consumers underlying preferences Our first assumption embodies the idea that consumers exhibit smooth preferences Assumption A1: u is C (u is smooth) Our second assumption embodies the idea that consumers always prefer consuming more Assumption A2: i u > 0, i (u is strictly increasing) 1 We could spend an entire course examining the relationship between consumers underlying preferences and the utility function representation of these preferences The interested reader is referred to Rubinstein s outstanding Lecture Notes in Microeconomics, freely available online 2 Notice that this immediately precludes certain preferences, in particular non-transitive preferences It is possible to show however that any well-behaved preferences can be represented using a utility function 3

4 Our third assumption embodies the idea that consumers prefer balanced baskets of goods 3 This is the natural assumption for complementary goods, but is also very compelling in the contexts of intertemporal consumption and consumption under uncertainty We explore these topics in detail later in the notes Assumption A3: u(λx + (1 λ)y) > min{u(x), u(y)}, λ (0, 1) (u is strictly quasiconcave) We will in these notes develop a set of results concerning utility functions satisfying the former assumptions Utility functions which fail to satisfy one or more of these assumptions have to be dealt with on an individual basis Definition 1 A consumer with utility function u is one who prefers x to y iff u(x) > u(y) A function u : R n R is a standard utility function iff it satisfies assumptions A1-A3 Henceforth, all utility functions we will be dealing with in these notes will be assumed to be standard utility functions, unless stated otherwise The following technical lemma records a useful way to check whether a given utility function satisfies the standard assumptions Lemma 1 Consider u such that A1-A2 hold Then assumption A3 holds iff u has convex level curves 4 Proof Suppose A3 holds, let L an arbitrary level curve of u (u(x) = l, x L), and f such that L = {(x, f(x)) : x R} We want to show that f is convex Let x and y belong to L By strict quasi-concavity u(λx + (1 λ)y) > min{u(x), u(y)} = l And, since u is strictly increasing, L lies below the line segment joining x and y But this implies f convex, since x and y were chosen arbitrarily For the converse, suppose u has convex level curves and let x and y be two consumption bundles Suppose moreover, wlog, that u(y) u(x) Let y the point on the same level curve as x such that y 2 = y 2 Note that y lies to the left of y, so that if we can show that u(λx + (1 λ)y ) > u(x) then we are done But the previous inequality indeed holds since the level curve containing x and y is decreasing, convex, and i u > 0, i, by A2 3 Observe that any concave function is also quasi-concave However, quasi-concavity is preserved under increasing transformation, while concavity is not So quasi-concavity is a statement about underlying preferences, while concavity is not 4 Recall that a level curve of u represents the set of points such that u(x) = l, for some fixed l 4

5 [Q1] Let α (0, 1) and consider the Cobb-Douglas functional form: u(x) = x α 1 x 1 α 2 Show that the Cobb-Douglas is (almost) a standard utility function We next introduce an important class of utility functions: Definition 2 A utility function u has the additive property iff there exists U : R R and (α i ) 1 i n, α i > 0, i, such that: u(x) = i α i U(x i ) (1) Utility functions satisfying the additive property are particularly convenient to handle and occupy for that reason a prominent place in microeconomic theory The following lemma shows for instance that assumptions A1-A3 take a particularly simple form for that class of utility functions Lemma 2 Let u satisfy the additive property, u(x) = i α iu(x i ) Then u satisfies A1-A3 iff 1 U is C 2 U > 0 3 U < 0 Proof Note first that 1 and 2 are evidently necessary and sufficient for A1 and A2 to hold, respectively We next show that if 3 holds then so does A3 We have u(λx + (1 λ)y) = i α i U(λx i + (1 λ)y i ) > i α ( λu(x i ) + (1 λ)u(y i ) ) (2) Hence u(λx + (1 λ)y) > λu(x) + (1 λ)u(y) We finally show that concavity of U is in fact a necessary condition for A3 to hold Suppose U not strictly concave We can thus find x such that U (x) 0 Let x 2 (x 1 ) denote the level curve of u passing through x = (x, x), so that α 1 U(x 1 ) + α 2 U(x 2 (x 1 )) = α 1 U(x) + α 2 U(x) (3) 5

6 Differentiating twice with respect to x 1 yields [ ] x α1 U (x 1 ) + α 2 U (x 2 )(x 2 = 2) 2 α 2 U (x 2 ) (4) In particular x 2(x) 0 By Lemma 1 therefore, u violates A3 [Q2] Using this time Lemma 2, show once more that the Cobb-Douglas is (almost) a standard utility function The problem of the consumer is straightforward to formulate on the basis of Definition 1 Let m denote the budget of a consumer with utility function u, and p the given vector of prices A consumer choosing his most preferred affordable bundle of goods effectively solves max u(x) st px m (5) x 0 Notice that if p i = 0 for some good i then, by A2, the consumer will demand an infinite amount of that good We will therefore suppose throughout that p i > 0, i Under this assumption, a solution to (5) always exists 5 There is moreover a unique optimal consumption bundle x Indeed, if there were two we could take a weighted average of them and, owing to the strict quasi-concavity of u, obtain a strictly higher utility level Note also that px = m at the optimum, by A2 We will say that the solution is interior if x i > 0, i Our first result embodies the following idea: prices establish the rate at which the consumer can trade goods against one another So unless this rate reflects his own valuation of the goods the consumer always has an incentive to trade goods at the market rate Thus, at an optimum, the consumer s marginal rate of substitution (MRS) must equal the price ratio The proposition also provides a useful set of sufficient conditions to elicit the optimal consumption bundle Proposition 1 Let p > 0 Any interior solution to (5) satisfies u/ x i u/ x j = p i p j (ie MRS = price ratio) (6) 5 All so-called existence results of microeconomics follow from standard results in topology These results are however beyond the scope of these notes 6

7 Moreover, if x satisfies (6) and px = m then x solves the consumer problem Proof Necessity of condition (6) is an immediate application of the Karush-Kuhn-Tucker Theorem (notice that we are here using the fact that the constraint is binding at an optimum) Suppose next x satisfies (6), and px = m By the Implicit Function Theorem the level curve of u at x is then tangent to the hyperplane px = m But utility functions have convex level curves by Lemma 1 The level curve of u at x thus lies entirely above its tangent This shows that x is optimal for the consumer problem We record for future reference the following definitions: Definition 3 The optimal consumption bundle in (5) is called Marshallian demand, and denoted x(p, m) Definition 4 The maximum utility level attained in (5) is called indirect utility, and denoted v(p, m) Definition 5 A good is said normal 6 iff the Marshallian demand for it satisfies x i (p, m)/ m 0 [Q3] Suppose two goods are perfect complements for a given consumer What functional form does this imply for this consumer s utility function? Comment What if the two goods are perfect substitutes instead? [Q4] Show that Marshallian demand is homogenous degree zero in (p, m), and satisfies px = m Show moreover that indirect utility is homogenous degree zero in (p, m), increasing in income, decreasing in prices, and quasiconvex in (p, m) [Q5] Let u a standard utility function and v : R R smooth and strictly increasing Apply (6) to v(u(x)) instead of u What do you observe? Comment [Q6] Let α (0, 1) and consider a consumer with Cobb-Douglas utility function Find the Marshallian demand functions and indirect utility function in this case Show that both goods are normal goods for this consumer 6 The definition is slightly misleading since a good may be normal for one consumer but not for another 7

8 [Q7] Let u(x) = x 1 +φ(x 2 ) Under what conditions is u a standard utility function? Assuming these conditions to be satisfied, find the Marshallian demand functions Comment Some careful inspection 7 will bring you to the observation that the solution to the consumer problem (5) is also the solution to a different closely related problem We next develop this intuition Consider the following problem and definitions: min px st u(x) u (7) x 0 Definition 6 The optimal consumption bundle in (7) is called Hicksian demand, and denoted h(p, u) Definition 7 The minimum expenditure attained in (7) is called expenditure function, and denoted e(p, u) [Q8] Show that the expenditure function is homogenous degree one in p, increasing in u as well as in prices, and concave in p The dual formulation of consumer theory rests on the following, mirror, results: Lemma 3 x(p, m) = h(p, v(p, m)) (8) Proof Let u = v(p, m) Note first that e ( p, u ) m Indeed, suppose we can find x such that u(x) u all the while px < m Since i u > 0, i, we can also find y close to x such that u(y) u and py < m But this contradicts u = v(p, m) So e ( p, u ) m Note also that e ( p, v(p, m) ) m since we have in particular px(p, m) = m, while u(x(p, m)) = u Hence e ( p, u ) = m The result follows since, once again, px(p, m) = m Lemma 4 h(p, u) = x(p, e(p, u)) (9) 7 Though admittedly mixed with a fair amount of intuition 8

9 Proof Let m = e(p, u) Note first that v(p, m) u Indeed, suppose we can find x such that u(x) > u and px m then we could also find y close to x such that u(y) > u and py < m But this implies e(p, u) < m, a contradiction So v(p, m) u But we also have v(p, m) u, since u ( h(p, u) ) = u while ph(p, u) = e(p, u) = m Hence v(p, m) = u The result now follows, since like we said already u ( h(p, u) ) = u and ph(p, u) = e(p, u) = m Corollary 1 m = e ( p, v(p, m) ) (10) Proof This was proven within the proof of lemma 3 Corollary 2 u = v ( p, e(p, u) ) (11) Proof This was proven within the proof of lemma 4 [Q9] Consider a consumer with Cobb-Douglas preferences Compute the Hicksian demand and expenditure functions in this case The dual formulation is somewhat more than a simple theoretical curiosity It is useful for at least two reasons It first allows us to illustrate income and substitution effects, and opens the way to comparative statics exercises Second, and maybe more importantly, it suggests an ingenious way of providing a unified treatment of consumption and production Leave production aside for now Our second result embodies the following idea: An increase in the price of good 1 makes good 1 relatively more expensive compared to other available goods In addition, it reduces the purchasing power of the consumer These effects substitution effect on the one hand, income effect on the other are essentially distinct effects The slutsky equation establishes this distinction formally and confirms that in so far as normal goods are concerned, the total effect on demand of an own-price increase is negative 9

10 Proposition 2 [Slutsky Equation] Suppose all goods are normal goods 8 For all i, j: x i (p, m) p j = h i(p, v(p, m)) x j (p, m) x i(p, m) p j m (12) In particular if i = j then both sides in (12) are negative Moreover, v(p, m)/ p i < 0 Proof By (9), and using the chain rule h i (p, u) p j = x i(p, e(p, u)) p j + x i(p, e(p, u)) e(p, u) (13) m p j By the Envelope Theorem, we also have e(p, u) p j = h j (p, u) (14) This establishes (12) Moreover, from (14): h i (p, u) p i = 2 e(p, u) p 2 i (15) But we have shown in [Q3] that e(p, u) is concave in p Hence h i(p,u) p i normal, both sides in (12) are negative < 0 and, if goods are That dv(p, m(p))/dp i < 0 is immediate since an increase in prices strictly reduces the set of goods affordable [Q10] Show that the substitution effect following an own-price increase is always negative The general framework we have developed remains silent on the source of the consumer s budget m As we will later see when using this framework for practical purposes, a recurrent scenario is one in which 9 m = m(p), ie in which wealth itself is a function of prices In the canonical example for instance, the consumer is originally endowed with a vector of goods e, 8 Observe that the Slutsky Equation holds for all goods, normal or not The sign however of the total effect of an own-price increase is determined only if the good is normal 9 Notice that m = m(p) allows for the possibility that m/ p = 0 So the truly general framework is the one in which m = m(p) I follow here however common practice and treat this case as an extension 10

11 so that he is both a seller and buyer of the goods he consumes Given prices p then: m = pe The consumer is a net buyer of good i iff x i > e i, and a net seller otherwise Naturally, extending the framework in this way creates important distortions regrading the effect of price changes and we must look beyond the Slutsky equation It is in particular no longer generally true that the total effect on demand of an own-price increase is negative If the consumer is a net seller of the good whose price increases he may benefit so much that he actually ends up raising his consumption of that good In a similar vein, the consumer need not be worse off following a price increase Indeed if he is a net seller of the good whose price increases then his old consumption bundle remains affordable, and he will even be left with a little cash in hand That consumer is thus in fact unambiguously better off Our next proposition formalizes these ideas Proposition 3 Suppose all goods normal and consider a consumer with endowment e, so that m = pe Then, for all i: 1 dx i(p,m(p)) dp i 2 dv(p,m(p)) dp i < 0 if x i > e i < 0 if x i > e i, dv(p,m(p)) dp i > 0 if e i > x i Proof Using the chain rule, we obtain the total derivative: dx i (p, m(p)) dp i = x i(p, m(p)) p i + x i(p, m(p)) m(p) (16) m p i We then obtain by (12) and the fact that m(p) p i = e i : [ dx i (p, m(p)) hi (p, v(p, m(p))) = x i (p, m(p)) x ] i(p, m(p)) dp i p i m + x i(p, m(p)) e i (17) m And, rearranging: dx i (p, m(p)) dp i = h i(p, v(p, m(p))) p i x ] i(p, m(p)) [x i (p, m(p)) e i m (18) This concludes the first part of the proof since, as already indicated in the proof of Proposition 2, h i(p,u) p i < 0 Suppose next e i > x i A rise in the price of good i leaves consumption bundle x strictly affordable Thus dv(p,m(p)) dp i > 0 in this case 11

12 Finally, suppose x i > e i Let u = v(p, m(p)) and assume for a contradiction that dv(p,m(p)) dp i 0, ie assume that the consumer remains able to reach level curve u following a rise in the price of good i By revealed preference the new consumption bundle must lie to the left of e But x i > e i, which implies that the demand for good i must be making a discontinuous jump This is impossible, owing to the continuity of demand (which itself is a consequence of the Maximum Theorem) 22 Applications 221 Intertemporal Consumption Consider a consumer with a two periods horizon, x i his consumption in period i, and U(x) his (ex post) utility from consuming quantity x 10 We are interested in the consumer s ex ante preferences over profiles of consumption over time x, represented by the (ex ante) utility function u While there are in principle infinitely many ways in which to define u, the time-discount assumption is by far the most convenient to work with 11 assumption sets u(x) = U(x 1 ) + δu(x 2 ), where δ 1 Let y i denote income received by the consumer in period i = 1, 2 The time-discount If the consumer is able to freely borrow and lend at the market interest rate r, his budget constraint is x 2 y 2 + (1 + r)(y 1 x 1 ): he can in period 2 consume his income from period 2 plus capital and 1 interest from any saving he has from period 1 Letting p = (1, ) we can then formulate the 1+r consumer problem as max u(x) st px py (19) x 0 Note that in case borrowing constraints apply we then have the additional condition that x 1 y 1 [Q11] Consider a consumer with a two periods horizon receiving income y i in period i = 1, 2, and such that u(x) = U(x 1 ) + δu(x 2 ) Show that consumption is greater in period 2 than in period 1 iff δ > (1 + r) 1 Can you say anything concerning the effect of changing the interest 10 We suppose here that this utility is time-independent 11 While extremely convenient analytically, bear in mind that the time-discount assumption is far from innocuous Indeed, it supposes important restrictions on consumers underlying preferences The fact for instance that cross-effects are excluded from the framework ( 2 u/ x 1 x 2 = 0) is hard to reconcile with certain aspects of human behavior such as habits 12

13 rate on saving? What if the utility function has the Cobb-Douglas functional form? [Q12] Consider a consumer with a two periods horizon receiving income y i in period i = 1, 2 Suppose we know that if the consumer can freely borrow and lend he consumes x 1 > y 1 Find that consumer s optimal consumption profile if now he can freely lend but cannot borrow money What if x 1 < y 1 instead? 222 Consumption under Uncertainty Uncertainty is conveniently illustrated by means of bets, or lotteries A bet B with n possible outcomes is a vector-pair (p, b) where p is the vector of probabilities and b the associated vector of contingent gains In particular µ(b), the expected gain of bet B, is then given by pb Definition 8 A bet is said to be fair iff it entails an expected gain/loss of 0, ie µ(b) = pb = 0 Let 1 denote the vector with all entries equal to 1 It is sometimes convenient to think of B as composed of a sure gain µ(b) on the one hand and a fair bet B 0 on the other hand, where b 0 = b µ(b)1 The attractiveness of this representation lies in the fact that we thereby separate the gain component of B from the risk component of B A risk-averse consumer for instance is one who would ideally like to part with the risk component of B Definition 9 A consumer is said to be risk-averse iff to any bet B = (p, b) he prefers the sure gain µ(b) The following definition is useful in the context of insurance, a theme we later investigate Definition 10 Let B = (p, b) The hedge of B is the bet B such that B = (p, b), B yielding b i whenever B yields b i [Q13] Consider a risk-averse consumer facing bet B, where µ(b) < 0 Show that B is worth strictly more than µ(b) for that consumer Comment We next introduce a very central concept in the study of consumption under uncertainty 13

14 Definition 11 Consider an uncertain environment with n contingencies and associated probabilities (p i ) 1 i n Let x i represent consumption under contingency i and u the utility function representing consumer preferences over vectors of contingent consumption A consumer is an expected-utility maximizer iff 12 there exists a function U such that u(x) = i p iu(x i ) The expected-utility assumption is quite compelling However, its greatest credential lies in the extent to which it simplifies the analysis of most problems 13 In particular, while riskaversion in no way invokes expected-utility, the latter phenomena takes a remarkably simple form under the expected-utility assumption Indeed, the following Lemma establishes that, in the expected-utility model, risk-averse consumers are precisely those with concave ex post utility function U Lemma 5 Consider an expected-utility maximizing consumer, and let U denote his ex post utility function The consumer is risk-averse iff U is concave Proof If U is concave then the consumer is risk-averse by Jensen s Inequality If U is not concave then we can find y, z, and λ such that U(λy + (1 λ)z) < λu(y) + (1 λ)u(z) But then consider bet B = (p, b) where p = (λ, 1 λ) and b = (y, z) We have u(b) = λu(y) + (1 λ)u(z) > U(λy + (1 λ)z) = u(i µ(b) ), where I µ(b) denotes the bet in which the consumer receives µ(b) for sure This shows that the consumer is not risk averse It is noteworthy to underline in lieu of concluding remark that Lemma 5, together with Lemma 2, show that in the context of expected-utility the general framework we developed in section 21 is, in fact, precisely a model of risk-aversion [Q14] Consider an expected-utility maximizing consumer Let U his ex post utility and m his wealth Show that the set of small bets he is willing to make expands according to U (m)/u (m) 12 In this definition p is treated as a parameter Of course, p may be a variable of the problem under study The interested reader is referred to Section While extremely convenient analytically, bear in mind that the expected-utility assumption is far from innocuous Indeed, it supposes important restrictions on consumers underlying preferences The Allais Paradox in particular indicates that human behavior is to some extent irreconcilable with the expected-utility assumption Section 81 elaborates on this important point 14

15 Application to the market for insurance: We saw in Q13 that risk-averse consumers are precisely those willing to pay a premium to hedge themselves against uncertain outcomes An insurance company is just another firm whose business model is to take advantage of this observation We develop here the simplest possible model of insurance Consider a consumer (or insuree), with initial wealth M, facing the risk of an accident occurring with probability q 14 If an accident occurs the consumer loses L M, otherwise nothing happens An insurance company offers to insure the consumer for a unit price p In other words, it offers for a price pk a contract specifying that the insurance company commits to pay the consumer amount K in case an accident occurs The object of what follows is to show that the problem of the consumer, namely choosing K, is in fact nothing more than a special case of the general problem we examined at length in section 21 Let x 1 denote consumption in case of no accident and x 2 denote consumption in case of accident We will start by showing that choosing K is equivalent to choosing x = (x 1, x 2 ) satisfying (1 p)x 1 + px 2 M pl (20) If the consumer purchases K units of insurance he is left with M pk if no accident takes place, ie he can choose x 1 M pk If an accident occurs on the other hand he will end up with M pk L + K = M L + (1 p)k He can thus choose to consume x 2 M L + (1 p)k Summing a weighted average of these inequalities yields (1 p)x 1 + px 2 (1 p)(m pk) + p(m L + (1 p)k) = M pl But note that this is exactly (20) Conversely, suppose that the consumer chooses (x 1, x 2) satisfying (20) and let us show that he can achieve this outcome with an appropriate choice of K Let K = M x 1, and check p that this choice of K works In case of no accident the consumer is left with M pk = M p M x 1 = x p 1, as desired In case of an accident he ends up with M L + (1 p)k = M L + (1 p) M x 1 He can thus consume x p 2 1M L 1 p p p x 1 But notice that the RHS of this inequality is at most x 2 since by assumption (x 1, x 2) satisfies (20) Since we have now shown that choosing K is equivalent to choosing x = (x 1, x 2 ) satisfying (20), this also means that the insurance problem can be stated as max x 0 u(x) such that (20) holds But notice that (20) can be written as px pe, where p = (1 p, p) and 14 We suppose here the accident probability given and, in particular, independent of the behavior of the insuree This circumvents the (important) topic of moral hazard 15

16 e = (M, M L) In other words, an equivalent formulation of the insurance problem is: max u(x) st px pe (21) x 0 The insurance problem can thus be framed as a standard consumer problem in which (i) the consumer s initial endowments are M in good times and M L in bad times and (ii) the consumer can trade consumption in good times for consumption in bad times at rate (1 p)/p 15 We conclude with the following useful definitions: Definition 12 An insurance policy is fair iff it entails a fair bet Definition 13 A consumer is said to be fully insured iff he bears no more risk, ie x i = x j for all i and j [Q15] Show that a risk-averse consumer always chooses full insurance whenever insurance is fair, ie whenever p = q Show moreover that the converse holds under the expected-utility assumption (ie the consumer does not choose full insurance if p q) [Q16] Consider an expected-utility maximizing risk-averse consumer with logarithmic ex-post utility function, and a risk-neutral insurance company Suppose the consumer s wealth is M but, with probability q he will lose L < M What is the set of pareto optimal contracts between consumer and insurer? Which of these are acceptable to both parties Which one of these entails a fair insurance policy? 223 Labour Supply [Q17] Suggest a way in which to approach labour supply using the general framework developed in section 21 Can you say anything concerning the effect of changing wages on labour supply? 15 ie give up p in good times and receive 1 p in bad times 16

17 3 The Producer We have in section 2 developed a theory of demand based on prices and consumers preferences This sections aims to outline the way in which a similar exercise can be carried out in view of developing a theory of supply based on prices and firms technological constraints One of the great qualities of the consumer model developed in these notes resides in the ease with which its formalism can be transferred over to production, thus yielding largely isomorphic approaches to consumption on the one hand and production on the other This section aims to elicit this isomorphism The starting point of a theory of production is the production function f such that to input vector z corresponds output y = f(z) It will once again prove useful to make certain assumptions concerning production functions We summarize these below: Assumption A1 : f is C Assumption A2 : i f > 0, i Assumption A3 : f is strictly concave The problem of profit maximization given output price p and input prices w is solves max py wz st f(z) y (22) (y,z) 0 Observe that a solution (y, z) to (22) is such that z minimizes the cost of producing y, ie min wz st f(z) y (23) z 0 But note that (23) is precisely the dual formulation of the consumer problem (7) in which x z, u() f(), p w, and u y Formally speaking the problem of the consumer and that of the producer are thus interchangeable Of course since in the case of the consumer it is the primal formulation which bears economic significance, while in the case of the producer it is the dual formulation, part of the analysis undertaken for the consumer looses relevance when carried over to the producer Consider Slutsky s equation for instance, eliciting changes in demand for a given level of expenditure Now, in the case of production, expenditure is a mere variable of the problem: Indeed firms care about profits, not costs So Slutsky s equation is of very little practical importance when discussing production 17

18 4 General Equilibrium I We developed in section 2 a theory of demand based on prices and consumers preferences, and in section 3 a theory of supply based on prices and firms technological constraints In both cases prices were taken as parameters of the problem under study In reality of course prices are endogenously determined, and the only parameters of the economy consist in consumers preferences and firms technological constraints General Equilibrium (GE) is the theory of prices It seeks to determine which prices will prevail in the economy and, as a consequence, which quantities of each goods will be produced and consumed It will be useful to think of an economy as a dynamical system A dynamical system (Ω, f) consists of a state space Ω and a process f describing the evolution of the system, such that if x t Ω denotes the state of the system in period t then x t+1 = f(x t ) (24) One of the most important concepts in the study of dynamical systems is that of an equilibrium An equilibrium of (Ω, f) is a state which, once reached, the system remains in indefinitely Observe from (24) that the set of equilibria thus coincides with the set of fixed points of the process f, ie the set of points such that f(x) = x It is very compelling to think of the economy as a dynamical system in which prices determine the state Somewhat peculiarly however, standard economic theory remains largely silent regarding the process describing the evolution of the system Instead, the theory characterizes equilibria at the outset, avoiding at that stage any reference to the underlying dynamic process It only later demonstrates as a consistency check, in a sense that the former equilibria in fact coincide with those of a well-defined dynamical process We will follow this practice here We will in these notes limit ourselves to the simplest form of GE models While supply in general results from production, we will take it to be fixed exogenously Such models are usually called pure exchange models A pure exchange model 16 begins with an endowment point E = ( A e, B e) At the outset, agent A (B) is endowed with goods-vector A e ( B e ) Such models have the great advantage of introducing supply and tying it up with consumers wealth in a very simple and convenient way Indeed, total supply is A e + B e, while the wealth of agent A (B) is given by p A e (p B e) 16 We limit ourselves here to two consumers in order to shorten and simplify the exposition 18

19 A market equilibrium is characterized by (i) prices p such that aggregate demand equals aggregate supply, and (ii) a consumption profile for each one of the consumers Formally: Definition 14 Let X = ( A x, B x) The pair (X, p) is a market equilibrium for the pure exchange economy with endowment E = ( A e, B e) if and only if A x + B x = A e + B e and each consumer s consumption profile maximizes his own utility function given prices p Let j x(p) denote the Marshallian demand of consumer j The vector j j x(p) j j e has an important economic interpretation It represents the aggregate excess demand vector given prices p We will use z(p) for a shorthand, so that z(p) = j x(p) j j j e (25) The following property is absolutely key It states that the value of the aggregate excess demand vector is always 0: z(p)p = 0 (26) [Q18] Prove (26) Observe, using (25), that a vector of prices p is an equilibrium price vector if and only if z(p) = 0 We will now show that the set of prices such that z(p) = 0 in fact corresponds to the equilibrium set of a well-defined dynamical system For technical reasons (that we will not dwell onto) we will, for the purposes of our next lemma, truncate the consumers Marshallian demands and set: j x i = j x i I { j x i j e i +ɛ} + ( j e i + ɛ)i { j x i > j e i +ɛ} (27) These truncated demands have the great advantage of being well-defined when prices are 0 It is moreover easy to show that a property corresponding to (26) holds, ie z(p)p = 0, for all p 17 Lastly, notice that p i = 0 implies z i > Each consumer must exhaust his budget constraint If he does not, this implies that we can find a good i such that p i > 0 and x i < e i But then, by (27), that consumer is not behaving optimally 18 If p i = 0 then by (27) each consumer demands strictly more of that good than he his endowed with There is thus strict excess demand for that good 19

20 Lemma 6 Let Σ denote the n-dimensional simplex, 19 and g : Σ Σ such that g i (p) = p i + max{0, z i (p)} j (p j + max{0, z j (p)}) (28) Then, g(p) = p if and only if z(p) = 0 Proof That z(p) = 0 implies g(p) = p is immediate We now show the converse Suppose, for a contradiction, that g(p) = p while z(p) 0 By (28), this implies that max{0, z i (p)} = kp i for some k 0, and all i In particular, one of the following must hold: 1 z i 0, i, with strict inequality for some i 2 z i > 0, i, and p i > 0, i 3 i such that z i 0 and p i = 0 We claim that none of the above can hold Suppose (1) holds Given zp = 0 this implies that there exists i such that z i < 0 while p i = 0 But this is impossible, by a former remark This also shows that (3) cannot hold Finally, (2) cannot hold since zp = 0 Lemma 6 is a central result It shows that a vector of prices p is a (market) equilibrium price vector if and only if it is an equilibrium state of the dynamical system (Σ, g) But given that Σ is a compact of R n, and g is continuous, we know that the dynamical system (Σ, g) has at least one equilibrium 20 It ensues that a market equilibrium does exist 21 [Q19] Let X = ( A x, B x), E = ( A e, B e), and p such that p i > 0 for all i Suppose A x ( B x) maximizes agent A s (B s) utility given prices p and wealth p A e (p B e) Suppose moreover that A x i + B x i = A e i + B e i in all but possibly one market Show that (X, p) is a market equilibrium for the pure exchange economy with endowment E [Q20] Consider a pure exchange economy, two consumers (A and B), two goods (1 and 2) Suppose consumer A has Cobb-Douglas utility function, while the two goods are perfect complements for consumer B Characterize market equilibrium if (i) A initially owns 10 units of 19 ie Σ = {x R n + i x i = 1} 20 This is a consequence of Brouwer s fixed point theorem 21 More precisely, lemma 6 shows that a market equilibrium exists given truncated demands a la (27) 20

21 good 1 and B 10 units of good 2 and (ii) A initially owns 10 units of good 2 and B 10 units of good 1 What is the set of pareto optimal allocations? Having formally defined market equilibria, we now aim to explore some of the properties these equilibria have The welfare theorems are the central results of GE Schematically, their message is the following Suppose S denotes the set of possible states of the economy, and P S the subset of states which are also pareto optimal Let s 0 S an arbitrary state, and s b the social planner s preferred state No matter how intricate the social planner s objective, the assumption that s b P is certainly compelling The First Welfare Theorem states that starting at s 0 and from there letting markets operate, the economy will eventually end in P 22 The Second Welfare Theorem states that if the social planner somehow manages to stir the economy to s b, he can then let markets operate and rest assured that the economy will remain in that state Somewhat ironically the welfare theorems are often perceived of as supporting arguments in favor of markets The First Welfare Theorem rests on the following observation: Prices fix the universal rate at which goods trade against one another and thereby also divide up the set of feasible allocations among consumers In equilibrium, each consumer chooses his preferred allocation within his subset Any improvement for one consumer must therefore lie in another consumer s subset and must, thereby, also be worse for that consumer owing to the fact that he chose to forego that allocation 23 The formal proof of the theorem requires some additional notation, which we now introduce Let F (E) denote the set of feasible consumption points 24 given endowment point E, ie F (E) = {X = ( A x, B x) : A x i + B x i = A e i + B e i, i} We call F (E) the Edgeworth box Let also A F (p, E) = {X F (E) : p A x p A e}, so that A F (p, E) is the subset of feasible consumption points affordable to consumer A under prices p Define B F (p, E) similarly Lemma 7 F (E) = A F (p, E) B F (p, E), for all p Proof Let X F (E) A F (p, E) Then 22 The Theorem remains silent however on how it will get from s 0 to P 23 By definition of a market equilibrium, each agent maximizes his own utility given prices There are thus no additional (mutual) gains from trade to be made at those prices The first welfare theorem notes that there are in fact no (mutual) gains from trade to be made at any prices 24 Strictly speaking, there are other feasible consumption points, namely those such that A x i + B x i < A e i + B e i for some i But these are not really interesting as they suppose that some resources go to waste In particular, it is cleat that none of these can be Pareto optimal 21

22 p B x = p( A e + B e A x) = p( A e A x) + p B e < p B e, ie X B F (p, E) Proposition 4 [First Welfare Theorem] A market equilibrium is pareto optimal Proof Let E the endowment point, p the equilibrium price vector, and X the equilibrium consumption point Suppose a feasible Y pareto dominates X, and suppose wlog that consumer A strictly prefers Y to X By definition of a market equilibrium Y / A F (p, E), and so by Lemma 7: Y B F (p, E) But this too is impossible, owing again to the definition of market equilibrium A last word of wisdom concerning the First Welfare Theorem Beware the following fallacious reasoning: in equilibrium each consumer maximizes his own utility so there are by definition no more gains from trade, and the First Welfare Theorem is a mere tautology The fault in this statement lies in the fact that there are by definition no more gains from trade at the equilibrium prices On the other hand what the First Welfare Theorem establishes is that there are in fact no more gains from trade at any prices [Q21] Argue that the reasoning used in the proof of the First Welfare Theorem collapses in the presence of externalities Proposition 5 [Second Welfare Theorem] Let X F (E) a pareto-optimal consumption point There exists p such that, in the pure exchange economy with endowment X, (X, p) is a market equilibrium Proof Let X = ( A x, B x) Let A L = {Y = ( A y, B y) F (E) : A u( A y) A u( A x)}, and B L = {Y = ( A y, B y) F (E) : B u( B y) B u( B x)} Note first that by quasi-concavity of utility functions both sets are convex We also have A L B L = {X} Indeed, if Y F (E) {X} belongs to A L B L, we can take a convex combination of X and Y and contradict the pareto-optimality of X So A L and B L are closed, convex sets with a singleton intersection The statement of the proposition is thus an immediate consequence of the Hyperplane Theorem 22

23 [Q22] Suppose (X, p) is a market equilibrium for the pure exchange economy with endowment E Can there exist an endowment point E and a price vector p p such that (X, p ) is a market equilibrium for the pure exchange economy with endowment E? What is the set of endowment points E such that (X, p) is a market equilibrium for the pure exchange economy with endowment E 5 Financial assets The analysis of general equilibrium developed in section 4 wholly disregards the issue of time In real life however, trade and consumption take place over time At any point in time therefore, individuals must decide whether to borrow or save all the while choosing what to consume at that point in time The key concept in this respect is that of a financial asset This section introduces financial assets, and sets the stage for section 6 in which we revisit GE with a view to incorporate temporal aspects We will throughout this section and the next consider T + 1 time periods, with t = 1 representing today and t > 1 representing future time periods We further suppose that for each t > 1 there are S possible contingencies, representing uncertainty about the future A pair (s, t) determines a state of the world Let W denote the set of all states of the world For expository purposes, it is useful to distinguish today s state of the world from future states We will let W 1 denote the set of all future states A financial asset is determined by a vector a R ST, specifying one payout for each possible future state of the world We suppose that the set of tradable assets is {a i } I i=1, so that I denotes the total number of tradable assets Let A denote the ST I matrix whose columns represent all tradable assets We refer to A as the asset structure We will henceforth make the assumption that I = ST 25 A portfolio ϕ R I is a combination of tradable assets, such that ϕ i indicates the quantity of asset i contained in the portfolio (note that we allow ϕ i < 0, i) The portfolio ϕ therefore induces payout vector Aϕ in future states We let q denote the price vector of the tradable assets at t = 1, so that, in particular, qϕ is the period 1 price of portfolio ϕ 25 The crucial assumption here is I ST If I < ST then rank(a) < ST, which most of the results derived in this section preclude The assumption that I actually equals ST is for simplification only 23

24 If the number of assets is large, different portfolios may induce identical payout vectors For a long time, one of financial traders main role was to seek out arbitrage opportunities between such portfolios Nowadays this is all computerized There are as a result, at any point in time, approximately no arbitrage opportunities remaining Formally: Definition 15 The no arbitrage condition states: Aϕ 1 = Aϕ 2 qϕ 1 = qϕ 2 (29) Intuitively, arbitrage creates a link between the prices of different assets We will now formalize this important idea Let ( e i) n i=1 denote the canonical basis in Rn If rank(a) = ST then for each i {1,, ST } we can find a portfolio v i such that Av i = e i (30) Definition 16 A family of portfolios ( v i) ST i=1 is a basis of elementary portfolios iff vi satisfies (30), for each i The following lemma provides a simple method which in practice allows us to find a basis of elementary portfolios Lemma 8 If rank(a) = ST and if moreover A is invertible then the column vectors of A 1 constitute a basis of elementary portfolios Proof Immediate from (30) Our next lemma summarizes the main practical consequence of the no arbitrage condition Lemma 9 Suppose the no arbitrage condition holds and rank(a) = ST Let ( v i) ST an i=1 arbitrary basis of elementary portfolios Then there exists π such that q i = πa i, i, or, in matrix form q = t Aπ (31) Moreover, π i = qv i, i (32) 24

25 Proof We have a i = j a i je j = j a i j(av j ) = A j a i jv j (33) On the other hand a i = Ae i (34) Hence, by no arbitrage q i = j a i jπ j = πa i (35) where π j = qv j (36) Naturally, any time the price of an elementary portfolio is lesser or equal than zero traders will demand an infinite amount of that portfolio, which in turn will push prices up We will thus henceforth assume π 0 [Q23] Let π 0 given by (31) Show that Aϕ 0 qϕ 0 Then show the converse, namely that Aϕ 0 qϕ 0 implies the existence of a vector π 0 such that q = t Aπ We next define an important class of portfolios Definition 17 Let τ {2,, T + 1} and b τ denote the portfolio paying out 1 if t = τ and 0 otherwise We call this portfolio a bond with maturity at date τ We define r τ such that 1 1+r τ indicates the price of this portfolio Notice that if ( v i) ST denotes a basis of elementary portfolios then: i=1 Ab τ = s Av sτ (37) By (31), we then have, using the no arbitrage condition: r τ = s π sτ (38) 25

26 In particular, we can define a probability distribution α τ such that, s {1,, S} π sτ = ατ s 1 + r τ (39) α τ s has a natural economic interpretation: we can view it as the probability which the market assigns to state of the world (s, τ) occurring 26 [Q24] Consider a world with two periods, today and tomorrow, and S states of the world Let A denote the asset structure of the economy, and q the asset price-vector Letting d = t (A 1 )q, show that r = 1 i d i i d i [Q25] A call option on a stock is a contract giving one the option to buy the stock at a specific price (the strike price) at a specified time in the future Consider a world with two future states (a good state and a bad state) and three financial assets There is first a bond, with interest rate r There is also a stock, whose price today is 1, and whose price tomorrow is u > 1 in the good state but d < 1 in the bad state There is finally a call option on the previous stock, with strike price K Assuming the no arbitrage condition holds, what is the price of the call option? (The formula you will obtain is a special case of the well-known Black-Scholes formula) What probability does the market assign to the good state occurring? In order to shed some light on financial assets role in the economy we will start with a simple model in which consumers only care about available wealth in each state of the world As usual, let u denote a utility function representing the consumer s preferences We suppose that the consumer receives income y w in each state of the world w W It will be useful to distinguish first-period income from later-periods income; we will write in this case y = (y 1, y 1 ) The consumer problem in this model is then: 27 max u(x) st ϕ,x 0 x1 y 1 qϕ ; x 1 y 1 + Aϕ (40) 26 To be more specific, suppose there exists a risk-neutral speculator who also happens to be fully unconstrained regarding his trading position If for some τ that speculator s beliefs do not coincide with α τ then he will take an infinite position 27 Notice that ϕ i in (40) may be positive or negative ϕ i < 0 is sometimes referred to as short-selling of asset i Finally, notice that the consumer is constrained in the speculative positions he may take Effectively, his income here plays the role of collateral 26

27 [Q26] Using the framework developed in the present section, re-formulate the intertemporal consumption problem as well as the insurance problem from sections 221 and 222, respectively In particular, specify A and q in each of these cases The purpose of the subsequent analysis is to show that (40) is in fact equivalent to (19), for an appropriate choice of p The idea is the following Consumers forego consumption today in order to buy assets which deliver future payouts; they then use these payouts to buy goods in the future Formally, we must therefore be able to by-pass financial assets Proposition 6 Suppose the no arbitrage condition holds and rank(a) = ST Let π 0 given by (31) and ξ = (1, π) Then x solves iff there exists ϕ such that (x, ϕ) solves (40) max u(x) st ξx ξy (41) x 0 Proof Note first that since (i) the objective functions are the same and (ii) all constraints are binding at any optimum of the two problems, it is enough to show that x Λ ϕ st (x, ϕ) Γ, where Γ = {(x, ϕ) : x 1 = y 1 qϕ ; x 1 = y 1 + Aϕ} ; Λ = {x : ξx = ξy} (42) We will first show that (x, ϕ) Γ x Λ We will then show that x Λ,! ϕ st (x, ϕ) Γ Let thus (x, ϕ) Γ Using (31) to substitute yields x 1 = y 1 πaϕ (43) We then have And, by definition of ξ x 1 = y 1 π ( x 1 y 1) (44) ξx = ξy (45) Conversely, let x Λ Since rank(a) = ST we can find a unique ϕ such that x 1 = 27

Walrasian Demand. u(x) where B(p, w) = {x R n + : p x w}.

Walrasian Demand. u(x) where B(p, w) = {x R n + : p x w}. Walrasian Demand Econ 2100 Fall 2015 Lecture 5, September 16 Outline 1 Walrasian Demand 2 Properties of Walrasian Demand 3 An Optimization Recipe 4 First and Second Order Conditions Definition Walrasian

More information

6. Budget Deficits and Fiscal Policy

6. Budget Deficits and Fiscal Policy Prof. Dr. Thomas Steger Advanced Macroeconomics II Lecture SS 2012 6. Budget Deficits and Fiscal Policy Introduction Ricardian equivalence Distorting taxes Debt crises Introduction (1) Ricardian equivalence

More information

4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS

4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS 4: SINGLE-PERIOD MARKET MODELS Ben Goldys and Marek Rutkowski School of Mathematics and Statistics University of Sydney Semester 2, 2015 B. Goldys and M. Rutkowski (USydney) Slides 4: Single-Period Market

More information

Constrained optimization.

Constrained optimization. ams/econ 11b supplementary notes ucsc Constrained optimization. c 2010, Yonatan Katznelson 1. Constraints In many of the optimization problems that arise in economics, there are restrictions on the values

More information

2. Information Economics

2. Information Economics 2. Information Economics In General Equilibrium Theory all agents had full information regarding any variable of interest (prices, commodities, state of nature, cost function, preferences, etc.) In many

More information

Multi-variable Calculus and Optimization

Multi-variable Calculus and Optimization Multi-variable Calculus and Optimization Dudley Cooke Trinity College Dublin Dudley Cooke (Trinity College Dublin) Multi-variable Calculus and Optimization 1 / 51 EC2040 Topic 3 - Multi-variable Calculus

More information

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Nathaniel Hendren January, 2014 Abstract Both Akerlof (1970) and Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976) show that

More information

Economics 2020a / HBS 4010 / HKS API-111 FALL 2010 Solutions to Practice Problems for Lectures 1 to 4

Economics 2020a / HBS 4010 / HKS API-111 FALL 2010 Solutions to Practice Problems for Lectures 1 to 4 Economics 00a / HBS 4010 / HKS API-111 FALL 010 Solutions to Practice Problems for Lectures 1 to 4 1.1. Quantity Discounts and the Budget Constraint (a) The only distinction between the budget line with

More information

U = x 1 2. 1 x 1 4. 2 x 1 4. What are the equilibrium relative prices of the three goods? traders has members who are best off?

U = x 1 2. 1 x 1 4. 2 x 1 4. What are the equilibrium relative prices of the three goods? traders has members who are best off? Chapter 7 General Equilibrium Exercise 7. Suppose there are 00 traders in a market all of whom behave as price takers. Suppose there are three goods and the traders own initially the following quantities:

More information

Schooling, Political Participation, and the Economy. (Online Supplementary Appendix: Not for Publication)

Schooling, Political Participation, and the Economy. (Online Supplementary Appendix: Not for Publication) Schooling, Political Participation, and the Economy Online Supplementary Appendix: Not for Publication) Filipe R. Campante Davin Chor July 200 Abstract In this online appendix, we present the proofs for

More information

Chapter 25: Exchange in Insurance Markets

Chapter 25: Exchange in Insurance Markets Chapter 25: Exchange in Insurance Markets 25.1: Introduction In this chapter we use the techniques that we have been developing in the previous 2 chapters to discuss the trade of risk. Insurance markets

More information

Economics of Insurance

Economics of Insurance Economics of Insurance In this last lecture, we cover most topics of Economics of Information within a single application. Through this, you will see how the differential informational assumptions allow

More information

Moral Hazard. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Moral Hazard. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Moral Hazard Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania 1 Principal-Agent Problem Basic problem in corporate finance: separation of ownership and control: o The owners of the firm are typically

More information

THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF ARBITRAGE PRICING

THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF ARBITRAGE PRICING THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF ARBITRAGE PRICING 1. Introduction The Black-Scholes theory, which is the main subject of this course and its sequel, is based on the Efficient Market Hypothesis, that arbitrages

More information

Example 1. Consider the following two portfolios: 2. Buy one c(s(t), 20, τ, r) and sell one c(s(t), 10, τ, r).

Example 1. Consider the following two portfolios: 2. Buy one c(s(t), 20, τ, r) and sell one c(s(t), 10, τ, r). Chapter 4 Put-Call Parity 1 Bull and Bear Financial analysts use words such as bull and bear to describe the trend in stock markets. Generally speaking, a bull market is characterized by rising prices.

More information

Envelope Theorem. Kevin Wainwright. Mar 22, 2004

Envelope Theorem. Kevin Wainwright. Mar 22, 2004 Envelope Theorem Kevin Wainwright Mar 22, 2004 1 Maximum Value Functions A maximum (or minimum) value function is an objective function where the choice variables have been assigned their optimal values.

More information

Intermediate Microeconomics (22014)

Intermediate Microeconomics (22014) Intermediate Microeconomics (22014) I. Consumer Instructor: Marc Teignier-Baqué First Semester, 2011 Outline Part I. Consumer 1. umer 1.1 Budget Constraints 1.2 Preferences 1.3 Utility Function 1.4 1.5

More information

ALMOST COMMON PRIORS 1. INTRODUCTION

ALMOST COMMON PRIORS 1. INTRODUCTION ALMOST COMMON PRIORS ZIV HELLMAN ABSTRACT. What happens when priors are not common? We introduce a measure for how far a type space is from having a common prior, which we term prior distance. If a type

More information

Lecture Notes on Elasticity of Substitution

Lecture Notes on Elasticity of Substitution Lecture Notes on Elasticity of Substitution Ted Bergstrom, UCSB Economics 210A March 3, 2011 Today s featured guest is the elasticity of substitution. Elasticity of a function of a single variable Before

More information

Mathematical finance and linear programming (optimization)

Mathematical finance and linear programming (optimization) Mathematical finance and linear programming (optimization) Geir Dahl September 15, 2009 1 Introduction The purpose of this short note is to explain how linear programming (LP) (=linear optimization) may

More information

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2011 Here are some remarks to help you with answering the questions.

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2011 Here are some remarks to help you with answering the questions. Name Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2011 Here are some remarks to help you with answering the questions. Question 1. A firm has a production function F (x 1, x 2 ) = ( x 1 + x 2 ) 2. It is a price

More information

Finite dimensional topological vector spaces

Finite dimensional topological vector spaces Chapter 3 Finite dimensional topological vector spaces 3.1 Finite dimensional Hausdorff t.v.s. Let X be a vector space over the field K of real or complex numbers. We know from linear algebra that the

More information

Choice under Uncertainty

Choice under Uncertainty Choice under Uncertainty Part 1: Expected Utility Function, Attitudes towards Risk, Demand for Insurance Slide 1 Choice under Uncertainty We ll analyze the underlying assumptions of expected utility theory

More information

The Graphical Method: An Example

The Graphical Method: An Example The Graphical Method: An Example Consider the following linear program: Maximize 4x 1 +3x 2 Subject to: 2x 1 +3x 2 6 (1) 3x 1 +2x 2 3 (2) 2x 2 5 (3) 2x 1 +x 2 4 (4) x 1, x 2 0, where, for ease of reference,

More information

Definition and Properties of the Production Function: Lecture

Definition and Properties of the Production Function: Lecture Definition and Properties of the Production Function: Lecture II August 25, 2011 Definition and : Lecture A Brief Brush with Duality Cobb-Douglas Cost Minimization Lagrangian for the Cobb-Douglas Solution

More information

Economics 326: Duality and the Slutsky Decomposition. Ethan Kaplan

Economics 326: Duality and the Slutsky Decomposition. Ethan Kaplan Economics 326: Duality and the Slutsky Decomposition Ethan Kaplan September 19, 2011 Outline 1. Convexity and Declining MRS 2. Duality and Hicksian Demand 3. Slutsky Decomposition 4. Net and Gross Substitutes

More information

Increasing for all. Convex for all. ( ) Increasing for all (remember that the log function is only defined for ). ( ) Concave for all.

Increasing for all. Convex for all. ( ) Increasing for all (remember that the log function is only defined for ). ( ) Concave for all. 1. Differentiation The first derivative of a function measures by how much changes in reaction to an infinitesimal shift in its argument. The largest the derivative (in absolute value), the faster is evolving.

More information

Lecture notes for Choice Under Uncertainty

Lecture notes for Choice Under Uncertainty Lecture notes for Choice Under Uncertainty 1. Introduction In this lecture we examine the theory of decision-making under uncertainty and its application to the demand for insurance. The undergraduate

More information

Lecture 2: Consumer Theory

Lecture 2: Consumer Theory Lecture 2: Consumer Theory Preferences and Utility Utility Maximization (the primal problem) Expenditure Minimization (the dual) First we explore how consumers preferences give rise to a utility fct which

More information

Lecture 3: Growth with Overlapping Generations (Acemoglu 2009, Chapter 9, adapted from Zilibotti)

Lecture 3: Growth with Overlapping Generations (Acemoglu 2009, Chapter 9, adapted from Zilibotti) Lecture 3: Growth with Overlapping Generations (Acemoglu 2009, Chapter 9, adapted from Zilibotti) Kjetil Storesletten September 10, 2013 Kjetil Storesletten () Lecture 3 September 10, 2013 1 / 44 Growth

More information

Economics 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics Problem Set 2 1/20/10

Economics 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics Problem Set 2 1/20/10 Dirk Bergemann Department of Economics Yale University s by Olga Timoshenko Economics 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics Problem Set 2 1/20/10 This problem set is due on Wednesday, 1/27/10. Preliminary

More information

Consumer Theory. The consumer s problem

Consumer Theory. The consumer s problem Consumer Theory The consumer s problem 1 The Marginal Rate of Substitution (MRS) We define the MRS(x,y) as the absolute value of the slope of the line tangent to the indifference curve at point point (x,y).

More information

No: 10 04. Bilkent University. Monotonic Extension. Farhad Husseinov. Discussion Papers. Department of Economics

No: 10 04. Bilkent University. Monotonic Extension. Farhad Husseinov. Discussion Papers. Department of Economics No: 10 04 Bilkent University Monotonic Extension Farhad Husseinov Discussion Papers Department of Economics The Discussion Papers of the Department of Economics are intended to make the initial results

More information

Web Appendix for Reference-Dependent Consumption Plans by Botond Kőszegi and Matthew Rabin

Web Appendix for Reference-Dependent Consumption Plans by Botond Kőszegi and Matthew Rabin Web Appendix for Reference-Dependent Consumption Plans by Botond Kőszegi and Matthew Rabin Appendix A: Modeling Rational Reference-Dependent Behavior Throughout the paper, we have used the PPE solution

More information

MATH10212 Linear Algebra. Systems of Linear Equations. Definition. An n-dimensional vector is a row or a column of n numbers (or letters): a 1.

MATH10212 Linear Algebra. Systems of Linear Equations. Definition. An n-dimensional vector is a row or a column of n numbers (or letters): a 1. MATH10212 Linear Algebra Textbook: D. Poole, Linear Algebra: A Modern Introduction. Thompson, 2006. ISBN 0-534-40596-7. Systems of Linear Equations Definition. An n-dimensional vector is a row or a column

More information

TOPIC 4: DERIVATIVES

TOPIC 4: DERIVATIVES TOPIC 4: DERIVATIVES 1. The derivative of a function. Differentiation rules 1.1. The slope of a curve. The slope of a curve at a point P is a measure of the steepness of the curve. If Q is a point on the

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 15: Repeated Games and Cooperation

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 15: Repeated Games and Cooperation 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 15: Repeated Games and Cooperation Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT November 2, 2009 1 Introduction Outline The problem of cooperation Finitely-repeated prisoner s dilemma

More information

Linear Programming Notes V Problem Transformations

Linear Programming Notes V Problem Transformations Linear Programming Notes V Problem Transformations 1 Introduction Any linear programming problem can be rewritten in either of two standard forms. In the first form, the objective is to maximize, the material

More information

Keynesian Macroeconomic Theory

Keynesian Macroeconomic Theory 2 Keynesian Macroeconomic Theory 2.1. The Keynesian Consumption Function 2.2. The Complete Keynesian Model 2.3. The Keynesian-Cross Model 2.4. The IS-LM Model 2.5. The Keynesian AD-AS Model 2.6. Conclusion

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 2: Strategic Form Games

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 2: Strategic Form Games 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 2: Strategic Form Games Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 4, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Decisions, utility maximization Strategic form games Best responses

More information

Fixed Point Theorems

Fixed Point Theorems Fixed Point Theorems Definition: Let X be a set and let T : X X be a function that maps X into itself. (Such a function is often called an operator, a transformation, or a transform on X, and the notation

More information

7: The CRR Market Model

7: The CRR Market Model Ben Goldys and Marek Rutkowski School of Mathematics and Statistics University of Sydney MATH3075/3975 Financial Mathematics Semester 2, 2015 Outline We will examine the following issues: 1 The Cox-Ross-Rubinstein

More information

Advanced Microeconomics

Advanced Microeconomics Advanced Microeconomics Ordinal preference theory Harald Wiese University of Leipzig Harald Wiese (University of Leipzig) Advanced Microeconomics 1 / 68 Part A. Basic decision and preference theory 1 Decisions

More information

Valuation of the Surrender Option Embedded in Equity-Linked Life Insurance. Brennan Schwartz (1976,1979) Brennan Schwartz

Valuation of the Surrender Option Embedded in Equity-Linked Life Insurance. Brennan Schwartz (1976,1979) Brennan Schwartz Valuation of the Surrender Option Embedded in Equity-Linked Life Insurance Brennan Schwartz (976,979) Brennan Schwartz 04 2005 6. Introduction Compared to traditional insurance products, one distinguishing

More information

REVIEW OF MICROECONOMICS

REVIEW OF MICROECONOMICS ECO 352 Spring 2010 Precepts Weeks 1, 2 Feb. 1, 8 REVIEW OF MICROECONOMICS Concepts to be reviewed Budget constraint: graphical and algebraic representation Preferences, indifference curves. Utility function

More information

1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set.

1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set. 1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set. Basic Topology Written by Men-Gen Tsai email: b89902089@ntu.edu.tw Proof: For any element x of the empty set, x is also an element of every set since

More information

Notes V General Equilibrium: Positive Theory. 1 Walrasian Equilibrium and Excess Demand

Notes V General Equilibrium: Positive Theory. 1 Walrasian Equilibrium and Excess Demand Notes V General Equilibrium: Positive Theory In this lecture we go on considering a general equilibrium model of a private ownership economy. In contrast to the Notes IV, we focus on positive issues such

More information

Chapter 7. Sealed-bid Auctions

Chapter 7. Sealed-bid Auctions Chapter 7 Sealed-bid Auctions An auction is a procedure used for selling and buying items by offering them up for bid. Auctions are often used to sell objects that have a variable price (for example oil)

More information

UCLA. Department of Economics Ph. D. Preliminary Exam Micro-Economic Theory

UCLA. Department of Economics Ph. D. Preliminary Exam Micro-Economic Theory UCLA Department of Economics Ph. D. Preliminary Exam Micro-Economic Theory (SPRING 2011) Instructions: You have 4 hours for the exam Answer any 5 out of the 6 questions. All questions are weighted equally.

More information

Chapter 21: The Discounted Utility Model

Chapter 21: The Discounted Utility Model Chapter 21: The Discounted Utility Model 21.1: Introduction This is an important chapter in that it introduces, and explores the implications of, an empirically relevant utility function representing intertemporal

More information

Moreover, under the risk neutral measure, it must be the case that (5) r t = µ t.

Moreover, under the risk neutral measure, it must be the case that (5) r t = µ t. LECTURE 7: BLACK SCHOLES THEORY 1. Introduction: The Black Scholes Model In 1973 Fisher Black and Myron Scholes ushered in the modern era of derivative securities with a seminal paper 1 on the pricing

More information

Mathematical Induction

Mathematical Induction Mathematical Induction In logic, we often want to prove that every member of an infinite set has some feature. E.g., we would like to show: N 1 : is a number 1 : has the feature Φ ( x)(n 1 x! 1 x) How

More information

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2015

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2015 ECON 459 Game Theory Lecture Notes Auctions Luca Anderlini Spring 2015 These notes have been used before. If you can still spot any errors or have any suggestions for improvement, please let me know. 1

More information

Chapter 4 Online Appendix: The Mathematics of Utility Functions

Chapter 4 Online Appendix: The Mathematics of Utility Functions Chapter 4 Online Appendix: The Mathematics of Utility Functions We saw in the text that utility functions and indifference curves are different ways to represent a consumer s preferences. Calculus can

More information

Prices versus Exams as Strategic Instruments for Competing Universities

Prices versus Exams as Strategic Instruments for Competing Universities Prices versus Exams as Strategic Instruments for Competing Universities Elena Del Rey and Laura Romero October 004 Abstract In this paper we investigate the optimal choice of prices and/or exams by universities

More information

Security Pools and Efficiency

Security Pools and Efficiency Security Pools and Efficiency John Geanakoplos Yale University William R. Zame UCLA Abstract Collateralized mortgage obligations, collateralized debt obligations and other bundles of securities that are

More information

The fundamental question in economics is 2. Consumer Preferences

The fundamental question in economics is 2. Consumer Preferences A Theory of Consumer Behavior Preliminaries 1. Introduction The fundamental question in economics is 2. Consumer Preferences Given limited resources, how are goods and service allocated? 1 3. Indifference

More information

Empirical Applying Of Mutual Funds

Empirical Applying Of Mutual Funds Internet Appendix for A Model of hadow Banking * At t = 0, a generic intermediary j solves the optimization problem: max ( D, I H, I L, H, L, TH, TL ) [R (I H + T H H ) + p H ( H T H )] + [E ω (π ω ) A

More information

Lectures, 2 ECONOMIES OF SCALE

Lectures, 2 ECONOMIES OF SCALE Lectures, 2 ECONOMIES OF SCALE I. Alternatives to Comparative Advantage Economies of Scale The fact that the largest share of world trade consists of the exchange of similar (manufactured) goods between

More information

Capital Structure. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Capital Structure. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Capital Structure Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania 1 Debt and Equity There are two main types of financing: debt and equity. Consider a two-period world with dates 0 and 1. At

More information

Working Paper Series

Working Paper Series RGEA Universidade de Vigo http://webs.uvigo.es/rgea Working Paper Series A Market Game Approach to Differential Information Economies Guadalupe Fugarolas, Carlos Hervés-Beloso, Emma Moreno- García and

More information

Linear Programming. March 14, 2014

Linear Programming. March 14, 2014 Linear Programming March 1, 01 Parts of this introduction to linear programming were adapted from Chapter 9 of Introduction to Algorithms, Second Edition, by Cormen, Leiserson, Rivest and Stein [1]. 1

More information

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces Dan Collins The textbook defines a subspace of a vector space in Chapter 4, but it avoids ever discussing the notion of a quotient space. This is understandable

More information

c 2008 Je rey A. Miron We have described the constraints that a consumer faces, i.e., discussed the budget constraint.

c 2008 Je rey A. Miron We have described the constraints that a consumer faces, i.e., discussed the budget constraint. Lecture 2b: Utility c 2008 Je rey A. Miron Outline: 1. Introduction 2. Utility: A De nition 3. Monotonic Transformations 4. Cardinal Utility 5. Constructing a Utility Function 6. Examples of Utility Functions

More information

Sensitivity Analysis 3.1 AN EXAMPLE FOR ANALYSIS

Sensitivity Analysis 3.1 AN EXAMPLE FOR ANALYSIS Sensitivity Analysis 3 We have already been introduced to sensitivity analysis in Chapter via the geometry of a simple example. We saw that the values of the decision variables and those of the slack and

More information

University of Oslo Department of Economics

University of Oslo Department of Economics University of Oslo Department of Economics Exam: ECON3200/4200 Microeconomics and game theory Date of exam: Tuesday, November 26, 2013 Grades are given: December 17, 2013 Duration: 14:30-17:30 The problem

More information

LECTURE 15: AMERICAN OPTIONS

LECTURE 15: AMERICAN OPTIONS LECTURE 15: AMERICAN OPTIONS 1. Introduction All of the options that we have considered thus far have been of the European variety: exercise is permitted only at the termination of the contract. These

More information

Common sense, and the model that we have used, suggest that an increase in p means a decrease in demand, but this is not the only possibility.

Common sense, and the model that we have used, suggest that an increase in p means a decrease in demand, but this is not the only possibility. Lecture 6: Income and Substitution E ects c 2009 Je rey A. Miron Outline 1. Introduction 2. The Substitution E ect 3. The Income E ect 4. The Sign of the Substitution E ect 5. The Total Change in Demand

More information

Several Views of Support Vector Machines

Several Views of Support Vector Machines Several Views of Support Vector Machines Ryan M. Rifkin Honda Research Institute USA, Inc. Human Intention Understanding Group 2007 Tikhonov Regularization We are considering algorithms of the form min

More information

CITY AND REGIONAL PLANNING 7230. Consumer Behavior. Philip A. Viton. March 4, 2015. 1 Introduction 2

CITY AND REGIONAL PLANNING 7230. Consumer Behavior. Philip A. Viton. March 4, 2015. 1 Introduction 2 CITY AND REGIONAL PLANNING 7230 Consumer Behavior Philip A. Viton March 4, 2015 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Foundations 2 2.1 Consumption bundles........................ 2 2.2 Preference relations.........................

More information

The Real Business Cycle model

The Real Business Cycle model The Real Business Cycle model Spring 2013 1 Historical introduction Modern business cycle theory really got started with Great Depression Keynes: The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money Keynesian

More information

Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zurich. Working Paper Series ISSN 1424-0459. Working Paper No. 229

Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zurich. Working Paper Series ISSN 1424-0459. Working Paper No. 229 Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zurich Working Paper Series ISSN 1424-0459 Working Paper No. 229 On the Notion of the First Best in Standard Hidden Action Problems Christian

More information

Numerical methods for American options

Numerical methods for American options Lecture 9 Numerical methods for American options Lecture Notes by Andrzej Palczewski Computational Finance p. 1 American options The holder of an American option has the right to exercise it at any moment

More information

Regret and Rejoicing Effects on Mixed Insurance *

Regret and Rejoicing Effects on Mixed Insurance * Regret and Rejoicing Effects on Mixed Insurance * Yoichiro Fujii, Osaka Sangyo University Mahito Okura, Doshisha Women s College of Liberal Arts Yusuke Osaki, Osaka Sangyo University + Abstract This papers

More information

Cost Minimization and the Cost Function

Cost Minimization and the Cost Function Cost Minimization and the Cost Function Juan Manuel Puerta October 5, 2009 So far we focused on profit maximization, we could look at a different problem, that is the cost minimization problem. This is

More information

Product Mix as a Framing Exercise: The Role of Cost Allocation. Anil Arya The Ohio State University. Jonathan Glover Carnegie Mellon University

Product Mix as a Framing Exercise: The Role of Cost Allocation. Anil Arya The Ohio State University. Jonathan Glover Carnegie Mellon University Product Mix as a Framing Exercise: The Role of Cost Allocation Anil Arya The Ohio State University Jonathan Glover Carnegie Mellon University Richard Young The Ohio State University December 1999 Product

More information

Lecture Note 7: Revealed Preference and Consumer Welfare

Lecture Note 7: Revealed Preference and Consumer Welfare Lecture Note 7: Revealed Preference and Consumer Welfare David Autor, Massachusetts Institute of Technology 14.03/14.003 Microeconomic Theory and Public Policy, Fall 2010 1 1 Revealed Preference and Consumer

More information

So let us begin our quest to find the holy grail of real analysis.

So let us begin our quest to find the holy grail of real analysis. 1 Section 5.2 The Complete Ordered Field: Purpose of Section We present an axiomatic description of the real numbers as a complete ordered field. The axioms which describe the arithmetic of the real numbers

More information

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 2

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 2 CS 70 Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 2 Proofs Intuitively, the concept of proof should already be familiar We all like to assert things, and few of us

More information

The Heat Equation. Lectures INF2320 p. 1/88

The Heat Equation. Lectures INF2320 p. 1/88 The Heat Equation Lectures INF232 p. 1/88 Lectures INF232 p. 2/88 The Heat Equation We study the heat equation: u t = u xx for x (,1), t >, (1) u(,t) = u(1,t) = for t >, (2) u(x,) = f(x) for x (,1), (3)

More information

On Lexicographic (Dictionary) Preference

On Lexicographic (Dictionary) Preference MICROECONOMICS LECTURE SUPPLEMENTS Hajime Miyazaki File Name: lexico95.usc/lexico99.dok DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY Fall 993/994/995 Miyazaki.@osu.edu On Lexicographic (Dictionary) Preference

More information

Economics 200B Part 1 UCSD Winter 2015 Prof. R. Starr, Mr. John Rehbeck Final Exam 1

Economics 200B Part 1 UCSD Winter 2015 Prof. R. Starr, Mr. John Rehbeck Final Exam 1 Economics 200B Part 1 UCSD Winter 2015 Prof. R. Starr, Mr. John Rehbeck Final Exam 1 Your Name: SUGGESTED ANSWERS Please answer all questions. Each of the six questions marked with a big number counts

More information

ASimpleMarketModel. 2.1 Model Assumptions. Assumption 2.1 (Two trading dates)

ASimpleMarketModel. 2.1 Model Assumptions. Assumption 2.1 (Two trading dates) 2 ASimpleMarketModel In the simplest possible market model there are two assets (one stock and one bond), one time step and just two possible future scenarios. Many of the basic ideas of mathematical finance

More information

No-Betting Pareto Dominance

No-Betting Pareto Dominance No-Betting Pareto Dominance Itzhak Gilboa, Larry Samuelson and David Schmeidler HEC Paris/Tel Aviv Yale Interdisciplinary Center Herzlyia/Tel Aviv/Ohio State May, 2014 I. Introduction I.1 Trade Suppose

More information

The Envelope Theorem 1

The Envelope Theorem 1 John Nachbar Washington University April 2, 2015 1 Introduction. The Envelope Theorem 1 The Envelope theorem is a corollary of the Karush-Kuhn-Tucker theorem (KKT) that characterizes changes in the value

More information

A Simple Model of Price Dispersion *

A Simple Model of Price Dispersion * Federal Reserve Bank of Dallas Globalization and Monetary Policy Institute Working Paper No. 112 http://www.dallasfed.org/assets/documents/institute/wpapers/2012/0112.pdf A Simple Model of Price Dispersion

More information

Continued Fractions and the Euclidean Algorithm

Continued Fractions and the Euclidean Algorithm Continued Fractions and the Euclidean Algorithm Lecture notes prepared for MATH 326, Spring 997 Department of Mathematics and Statistics University at Albany William F Hammond Table of Contents Introduction

More information

Adverse Selection and the Market for Health Insurance in the U.S. James Marton

Adverse Selection and the Market for Health Insurance in the U.S. James Marton Preliminary and Incomplete Please do not Quote Adverse Selection and the Market for Health Insurance in the U.S. James Marton Washington University, Department of Economics Date: 4/24/01 Abstract Several

More information

Separation Properties for Locally Convex Cones

Separation Properties for Locally Convex Cones Journal of Convex Analysis Volume 9 (2002), No. 1, 301 307 Separation Properties for Locally Convex Cones Walter Roth Department of Mathematics, Universiti Brunei Darussalam, Gadong BE1410, Brunei Darussalam

More information

BANACH AND HILBERT SPACE REVIEW

BANACH AND HILBERT SPACE REVIEW BANACH AND HILBET SPACE EVIEW CHISTOPHE HEIL These notes will briefly review some basic concepts related to the theory of Banach and Hilbert spaces. We are not trying to give a complete development, but

More information

2.3 Convex Constrained Optimization Problems

2.3 Convex Constrained Optimization Problems 42 CHAPTER 2. FUNDAMENTAL CONCEPTS IN CONVEX OPTIMIZATION Theorem 15 Let f : R n R and h : R R. Consider g(x) = h(f(x)) for all x R n. The function g is convex if either of the following two conditions

More information

Inflation. Chapter 8. 8.1 Money Supply and Demand

Inflation. Chapter 8. 8.1 Money Supply and Demand Chapter 8 Inflation This chapter examines the causes and consequences of inflation. Sections 8.1 and 8.2 relate inflation to money supply and demand. Although the presentation differs somewhat from that

More information

Saving and the Demand for Protection Against Risk

Saving and the Demand for Protection Against Risk Saving and the Demand for Protection Against Risk David Crainich 1, Richard Peter 2 Abstract: We study individual saving decisions in the presence of an endogenous future consumption risk. The endogeneity

More information

Review of Fundamental Mathematics

Review of Fundamental Mathematics Review of Fundamental Mathematics As explained in the Preface and in Chapter 1 of your textbook, managerial economics applies microeconomic theory to business decision making. The decision-making tools

More information

Duality of linear conic problems

Duality of linear conic problems Duality of linear conic problems Alexander Shapiro and Arkadi Nemirovski Abstract It is well known that the optimal values of a linear programming problem and its dual are equal to each other if at least

More information

Duality in Linear Programming

Duality in Linear Programming Duality in Linear Programming 4 In the preceding chapter on sensitivity analysis, we saw that the shadow-price interpretation of the optimal simplex multipliers is a very useful concept. First, these shadow

More information

Sensitivity analysis of utility based prices and risk-tolerance wealth processes

Sensitivity analysis of utility based prices and risk-tolerance wealth processes Sensitivity analysis of utility based prices and risk-tolerance wealth processes Dmitry Kramkov, Carnegie Mellon University Based on a paper with Mihai Sirbu from Columbia University Math Finance Seminar,

More information

Competitive Screening in Credit Markets with Adverse Selection: A Cover Version of Bester s Model

Competitive Screening in Credit Markets with Adverse Selection: A Cover Version of Bester s Model Competitive Screening in Credit Markets with Adverse Selection: A Cover Version of Bester s Model Ran Spiegler April 18, 2013 Abstract This note presents a simple model of competitive screening in a credit

More information

Game Theory: Supermodular Games 1

Game Theory: Supermodular Games 1 Game Theory: Supermodular Games 1 Christoph Schottmüller 1 License: CC Attribution ShareAlike 4.0 1 / 22 Outline 1 Introduction 2 Model 3 Revision questions and exercises 2 / 22 Motivation I several solution

More information

INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY

INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY MATH 410, CSUSM. SPRING 2008. PROFESSOR AITKEN This document covers the geometry that can be developed with just the axioms related to incidence and betweenness. The full

More information