EMOTIONAL SELF PREDICTION IN RISKY DECISION MAKING: THE ROLE OF NEGATIVE ASYMETRIES

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "EMOTIONAL SELF PREDICTION IN RISKY DECISION MAKING: THE ROLE OF NEGATIVE ASYMETRIES"

Transcription

1 EMOTIONAL SELF PREDICTION IN RISKY DECISION MAKING: THE ROLE OF NEGATIVE ASYMETRIES Autoria: Gazi Islam, Danny Pimentel Claro, Eduardo B. Andrade ABSTRACT Consumers often incorrectly predict psychological states and behaviors, failing to keep a planned course of action from their earlier predictions. This paper adddresses the extent to which individuals misestimate their own risk taking behavior, believing falsely that they will engage in risk averse behavior after losses. In a series of four experiments, we demonstrate that losses lead to higher than planned bets whereas bets are on average carried over after gains. This implies that participants are more successful at self-prediction after gains than after losses, increasing riskiness after the latter. Such assymetric dynamic inconsistencies emerge when (1) monetary and non-monetary incentivies are used, when participants face (2) fair and unfair gambles, and when the betting decision happens (3) individually and in groups. The reason for the assymetry lies in part on people s inability to predict how much the negative feelings generated by the loss will influence them to bet more than planned in an attempt to restablish a homeostatic state in the prospect of winning. These feelings affect post-planning behavior, while, we argue, they are inaccessible at the pre-decision planning phases. We discuss the implications of our results in terms of the cognition-emotion linkage, negative emotional asymetries and individual versus group decision making. INTRODUCTION Consumers often incorrectly predict psychological states and behaviors, failing to keep a planned course of action (e.g.van Boven & Kane, 2006; Van Boven, Loewenstein & Dunning, 2005). Although they plan to skip dessert, not drink a second glass of wine or not limit their buying behavior, they end up eating (Wardle and Beales, 1988), drinking (Allsop and Saunders 1989) and spending in a supermarket (Gilbert, Gill, and Wilson 2002, Nisbett and Kanouse 1968) more than they had initially planned. Anecdotal evidence suggests that this phenomenon might also be true in gambling environments. We have all overhead stories about those who have lost a blouse, a house, and, perhaps as a result, a spouse on the gambling table. Moreover, given the skyrocket growth of the gambling industry from casinos to internet gambling, the size and scope of the phenomenon may have increased markedly in the past decades. Las Vegas, for example, represents the top tourist destination in the US, with thirty nine million visitors in 2006 (American Gaming Association, 2006). Many of them gambled, and of those who did, most lost. In fact, the gross gaming revenue in Las Vegas mounted to 10.6 billion dollars in the same year, more than a quarter of the total visitor spending. Interestingly, if the anecdotes hold, a significant fraction of gamblers probably bet and eventually lost more than they had anticipated. However, empirical data to support the intuition that non-pathological gamblers (i.e., the great majority of consumers) are actually not good at keeping their plans in a gambling environment is still scant. Although prediction of future states of the self has been shown as problematic in the experimental social psychology literature (e.g. Loewenstein, Hsee, Weber & Welch, 2001), only recently have researchers paid systematic attention at what has been called the dynamic inconsistencies of gambling i.e., people s tendencies to bet differently from what they had originally planned to bet in anticipation of gains and losses. Moreover, as we will describe latter, the patterns of deviations as well as the explanations are not yet conclusive (e.g., Andrade and Iyer 2007, Barkan and Busemeyer 2003). The current paper attempts to fill this 1

2 lacuna in a series of four experiments, assessing the presence of dynamic inconsistencies in sequential gambling and provide further insights into the potential underlying processes. DYNAMIC INCONSISTENCIES IN GAMBLING That consumers deviate from their plans in a gambling scenario could be explained by non psychological factors, such as lack of experience or information about the environment. For instance, imagine Paul, a consumer who decides to go to Las Vegas for the first time and has put $300 aside to spend in the casinos. As the trip ends, Paul realizes he has spent twice as much and cannot quite figure out why. A simple explanation is that, as a naïve consumer, Paul did not know much about the city, the availability of the games (even at the airport!), the different types of games, the surrounding cues, the free drinks, etc. In other words, at the planning stage Paul did not have enough information about his decision making context. When additional pieces of information about the gambling environment were made available, he changed his initial plans. The rationale above would imply, however, that as information about the characteristics of the gambles and surroundings become available prior to a planning phase, dynamic inconsistencies should disappear. Recent experimental research has shown that this is not necessarily the case. Even in fully controlled environments (labs) where people have sufficient information about the gambles prior to the planning phase, they tend to deviate from the initial plan in sequential gambles (Andrade & Iyer, 2007). However, the pattern of deviations and the accounts provided to explain the inconsistencies have varied in the literature. Reversed Dynamic Inconsistencies and Changes in Reference Points Barkan and Busemeyer (2003) asked participants to plan and play several times a sequence of 2 gambles (the gambles varied in expected value). The first gamble was always mandatory. Participants had to indicate their preferences on whether or not to take the second gamble prior ( If I win the first gamble, I will take/reject the second gamble ) and after the outcome of gamble 1 ( I will take/reject the second gamble ). The authors found that losses and gains did not produce any differences in subsequent bets at the planning phase. In other words, participants seemed to treat the gambles independently at this stage. However, in practice, after gamble 1, participants were more likely to reject gamble 2 after a gain was observed and to take gamble 2 after a loss was experienced, showing reversed dynamic inconsistencies. This behavioral result seems consistent with a line of research in behavioral decision making showing that actors tend to become risk averse in the domain of gains, and risk seeking in the domain of losses (e.g. Khaneman & Tversky, 1979), but adds the important observation that people do not realize that this effect will happen prior to the risk taking episode. The authors argue that when planning a sequence of gambles individuals treat each gamble independently from one another, which leads to no change in reference points (i.e., when planning a second bet, people do not consider the impact of the outcome of the first planned bet). During the actual gambles, however, the previous outcome is integrated into the subsequent decision making process. As a result, shifts in reference points take place due to gains and losses, and deviations from initial plans follow the predictions of prospect theory (e.g. Khaneman & Tversky, 1979). Once losses are experienced in the first gamble individuals become more riskseeking i.e., positive deviations from the plan become more likely in a second gamble. Whereas when gains are experienced in the first gamble, individuals become more risk-averse i.e., negative deviations from the plan become more likely in a second gamble. Such rationale would explain (1) the null effect of a prior outcome on a future bet at the planning phase of the gamble as well as (2) the reversed dynamic inconsistencies at the actual phase of the gamble (see also Barkan et al. 2005). Recently, however, there has been evidence that the patterns of 2

3 planning and of deviations as well as the potential account for the phenomenon may differ from prior suggestions. Asymmetric Dynamic Inconsistencies and the Hot-Cold Empathy Gap Similar to Barkan and colleagues, Andrade and Iyer (2007) asked participants to plan and act on a sequence of 2 gambles. However, among other procedural differences from the earlier suty, participants were given a choice as to whether and how much to bet in each of the 2 gambles. The results show that within this paradigm two effects emerge. First, at the planning phase, the gambles are not necessarily assessed in isolation. In a series of four studies the authors showed that participants pre-committed to betting less in gamble 2 in anticipation of a loss and the same amount in anticipation of a gain relative to their chosen bet in gamble 1. In other words, while planning a sequence of 2 gambles and allowed to make contingent plans, participants not only took into account a previous outcome, but they actually behaved quite conservatively, planning to betting less when wealth was expected to decline (e.g., If I lose $X in gamble 1, I will bet $X - $Y in gamble 2 ). However, when a loss or a gain was actually experienced, asymmetric dynamic inconsistencies emerged. After a gain was realized, participants bet on average the same amount they had anticipated, whereas, after a loss was observed, they bet more than they had initially planned to bet in anticipation of such loss. Note that this effect emerged even in a scenario where participants had full information about the characteristics of the gamble, they were led to believe that the planned bets would have to be carried over (i.e., pre-commitment), the time delay between planning and actual betting was short, and people were reminded of their planned bet prior to actual betting decisions. The hot-cold empathy gap. To explain the asymmetric dynamic inconsistencies, the authors adopted a hot-cold empathy gap rationale. It has been shown that people in a cold (relatively neutral) state tend to underestimate how their own feelings will influence their future behavior when they experience a hot (strong visceral drive) state (Loewenstein, 1996; Loewenstein and Schkade 1999). Moreover, when deprived of a given resource, the aversive state that is experienced might lead people to react and usually overdo in an attempt to restore a homeostatic state. This would explain, for example, why hungry consumers buy more food than they ve initially planned (Gilbert, Gill, and Wilson 2002; Nisbett and Kanouse 1968), why curious individuals care more about the missing information than they had initially predicted (Loewenstein, Prelec, and Shatto 1996), and why drug users underestimate the impact of craving (Badger et al. 2007). Applied to gambling, it means that people at the planning phase might be underestimating the intensity and impact of post-outcome feelings on their subsequent bets. Precisely, when losses are felt in gamble 1 and participants become deprived of money, positive deviations take place in gamble 2. Since for gains, no sense of deprivation is experienced, no specific pattern of behavior is observed (i.e., both positive and negative deviations are likely). That would explain the asymmetric dynamic inconsistencies (i.e., people betting more than planned after losses, but on average not doing so after gains). Andrade and Iyer (2007) provided initial evidence consistent with this rationale. They showed that positive deviations from the plan after losses were associated a prior underestimation of negative affect (experiment 3). In other words, those who felt worse than they expected were the ones more likely to bet more than planned after a loss. Also, when a pleasant cooling off period was inserted between gambles, it mitigated participants tendency to bet more than planned in gamble 2 after losing gamble 1 (experiment 4). That is, when negative feelings associated with the loss were reduced by a distracting task, so 3

4 did the positive deviations. All these moderating factors suggest that the behavioral inconsistencies observed are, at least in part, affect driven. OVERVIEW In the current study, we build on Andrade and Iyer s (2007) initial findings to further investigate the presence and shape as well as the role of feelings in dynamic inconsistencies in gambling. Precisely, across four experiments where people are asked to plan and bet in a sequence of 2 gambles, we test (1) whether dynamic inconsistencies hold when a non-monetary incentive is used, (2) whether people can control for the impact of feelings, if any, on deviations from the plan, (3) whether the length of the pre-outcome period modify emotional states, and as result, change the pattern of the dynamic inconsistencies, (4) whether similar inconsistencies can be established at the group level of analysis, when groups instead of individuals are asked to make the decisions. Consequential Incentives. Andrade and Iyer (2007) showed that people reacted to a financial loss and bet more than planned when the loss was experienced. An open question is whether this pattern of results is contrived to monetary losses.(find cite!) Since negative emotions are critical to produce deviations from the plan after losses, we hypothesize that not only a monetary incentive, but other consequential incentives (i.e., incentives meaningful enough to trigger affective reactions) might generate the same pattern of inconsistencies. Experiment 1 addresses this issue. Affective Correction. If negative feelings instigate positive deviations from the plan, can people control for its impact when asked to do so? If the asymmetric dynamic inconsistencies result from the hot-cold empathy gap i.e., the underestimation of post-outcome feelings and the need to restore a homeostatic state (after losing gamble 1), participants might bet more than planned because of their lack of conscious awareness and control of their shift in emotional state. When explicitly instructed to control for the impact of feelings on subsequent behavior, the positive deviations after losses could be mitigated and the asymmetric dynamic inconsistency, consequently, disappear. It requires however, first, that people recognize that their negative feelings are actually leading them to bet more than planned after a loss, and second, that they are capable of controlling the urge to overreact. This proposition is tested in experiment 2. Pre-Outcome Period. In gambling environments, waiting is a common experience, particularly during the time delay between betting and outcome, the so-called the pre-outcome period of the gamble (Pope 1983). Pre-outcomes can take a few seconds (e.g., roulette), a few minutes (e.g., horse race), or a few hours (e.g., sports betting). Importantly, there is robust evidence that arousal builds up during this pre-outcome period (Dickerson and Adcock 1987; Dickerson et al. 1992; Wulfert et al. 2005). Moreover, within a certain range, longer time delays lead to more intensity levels of arousal (Nomikos et al. 1968). If longer time delays increase the intensity of pre-outcome feelings, and if pre-outcome feelings influence the intensity of postoutcome feelings, it is possible that people might feel worse when a longer (vs. shorter) preoutcome period precedes the loss. Moreover, since negative feelings instigate positive deviations from the plan, one would observe stronger (weaker) deviations when participants have experienced a longer (vs. shorter) pre-outcome period even tough the amount lost remains constant across groups. Experiment 3 addresses this issue. Consensual Decision Making. To date, the literature on pre-post planning discrepancies, and on asymmetries in risk taking more generally, has focused on the individual level of analysis (Hastie, 2001). However, an important question in group decision making is whether individual level models are isomorphic across levels, and whether group decision processes show similar 4

5 patterns to individual processes. Because consumers are also known to bet in groups (Pruitt and Teger 1969), buying lottery tickets together, meeting to bet on their favorite teams, and even playing together in casinos. The open question is whether the asymmetric dynamic inconsistencies will hold when groups must reach a consensus on the bets. Two potential hypotheses are contrasted. Since groups, in some contexts, tend to amplify the pre-existing attitudes of their members, as in the risky shift or group polarization literatures (Pruitt and Teger 1969; Myers, 1978, Myers & Lamm, 1976), and if contagious affect tends to aggregate and converge in group settings (George, 1990, Ilies, Wagner & Morgeson, 2007), the risky tendencies in individuals should also be isomorphic and observable at the group level. However, another possibility is that if risky behavior were over- amplified, then the risk taking tendencies of groups might lead to higher than planned bets for gains and losses alike, thereby eliminating the asymmetry. Experiment 4 addresses this issue. EXPERIMENT 1 In the first experiment we adopt a procedure similar to Andrade and Iyer s. Participants are asked to plan a sequence of bets contingent on winning/losing the previous gamble. Precisely, they plan a bet in gamble 1, and then are asked plan a bet in gamble 2 given either a win or a loss a loss in gamble 1. Within a certain budget, participants are free to decide on whether and how much to bet in each gamble. Then, during the gambles, they are unexpectedly given the opportunity to confirm or revise the planned bets. Contrary to Andrade and Iyer who used a monetary incentive, participants (here, undergraduate students) in this experiment bet course credits they received in exchange for their participation (i.e., a 10% increase in the final exam grade). We hypothesize that with a consequential yet non-monetary incentive the results will replicate Andrade and Iyer s findings and contradict Barkan and colleagues results. Precisely, we expect participants to behave conservatively at the planning phase, betting less in case wealth declines (i.e., after an anticipated loss). Moreover, when an opportunity to revise/confirm the plan is provided, asymmetric dynamic inconsistencies should emerge. That is, participants will bet on average the same planned amount after a gain is experienced but will bet more than planned after a loss is felt. Method Participants and design. Eighty one students participated in this experiment. They were given 1 course credit in exchange for their participation in the experiment. The experiment employed a two (bet 2: planned vs. actual; within) by two (outcome 1: gain vs. loss; between) mixed design. Procedure. The experiment was conducted in a computer-based environment. The cover story stated that the study was about gambling preferences, and that they would be playing a series of two identical and fair gambles. Each gamble offered a 50% chance of doubling the amount bet and had a 50% chance of losing the bet (EV = 0). Participants began the experiment with 1 course credit for their participation in the experiment (which corresponded to 5% increase in the final exam grade). At the beginning of the experiment, however, they were told that the experimenter had received authorization from the school to allow them to use this course credit in the subsequent gambles if they felt like. It was entirely up to them to decide on whether and how much to bet in the following gambles. The 1 course credit was then converted into 100 electronic chips, and participants were told that they could bet any amount from 0 to 50 chips (i.e., 0 to 2.5% increase in the final exam grade) in each 5

6 of the two gambles. Thus, over the two bets they could potentially increase their grade by up to 10%. The procedure followed three steps: trial, planning, and actual phase. In order to provide participants with information about the gamble, they were first asked to practice the gamble in a trial phase (no betting involved). Then, participants were told that the gamble comprised of two additional phases. During the planning phase, they would have to plan their bets in both gambles. Whatever decision made during the planning phase, they were told, would be carried over (no changes allowed). Participants then bet in gamble 1 and were given the opportunity to make bets in gamble 2 in anticipation of a gain and in anticipation of a loss in gamble 1. Then, the actual phase started. To avoid memory decay effects, they were reminded of the planned bet 1 and were unexpectedly informed that they could either confirm or revise the planned bet. They made the final bet in gamble 1 and then the gamble started. After 15 seconds of flashing in the gambling board the outcome was revealed (see below). They were then reminded of their planned bet in gamble 2 and were asked as in gamble 1 to confirm or revise it. Finally, after a few final questions participants were properly debriefed and thanked for their participation in the study. Gambles. The gambles had the following characteristics. A gambling board consisting of 20 red and 20 blue squares appeared on the screen. A X sign flashed randomly on the board every ½ sec for 15 sec. Each flash was independent of the previous one so that it could flash more than once in the same square. At the end of the fifteen second period, the flashing stopped. If the X sign landed on a blue square, the participant would double the amount bet; otherwise, s/he would lose the bet. The probabilities, payoffs, and the remaining time were displayed on top of the gambling board. To avoid potential objective mistakes, the board was constructed to present visual and easy-to-assess probabilities. Also, the winners were required to raise their hand so the experimenter could double-check each outcome. This procedure was added to simply allow all participants to observe the actual distribution of gains and losses in the room and avoid suspicion of outcome manipulation. Finally, to bring knowledge about this type of gambling to a common real-life baseline, participants also were told at the beginning of the experiment that the probabilities and payouts in the current gamble presented a slightly better deal compared to the black/red options in the American roulette (which offers a 47.4% of doubling the amount bet) (cite!). Results Planning phase. Participants planned the betting amount in gamble 1, and then, in gamble 2 in anticipation of a gain and in anticipation of a loss. The results showed that previous outcomes influenced subsequent planned bets (F(2, 79) = 4.08, p <.05). Planned bets in gamble 2 were lower in anticipation of a loss (vs. gain) in gamble 1 (M L = 24.9 vs. M G = 28.7; F(1, 80) = 3.96, p =.05). Moreover, compared to their planned bets in gamble 1 (M = 28.2), participants reported lower planned bets in gamble 2 after an anticipated loss in the previous gamble (F(1, 80) = 8.25, p <.01), but reported similar planned bets in gamble 2 after an anticipated gain in the previous gamble (F(1, 80) =.10, p >.10). In other words, at the planning phase, losses discouraged participants from betting in subsequent gambles, whereas gains had no effect on bets placed on subsequent gambles. Remember that in the planning stage participants were led to believe that the planned bets would be carried over. Therefore, these results do not represent instances of intentions, but actual forward looking behavior based on anticipated contingencies. Actual phase. In gamble 2, a significant interaction emerged between betting phase (planned vs. actual) and the outcome of gamble 1 (F(1, 79) = 4.85, p <.05). Participants who 6

7 won gamble 1, bet on average the same amount they had initially planned in anticipation of such gain (M p = 29.0 vs. M a = 28.7; F(1, 79) =.02, p >.10). Participants who lost gamble 1, however, bet on average more than they had initially planned to bet in anticipation of such loss (M p = 23.2 vs. M a = 30.2; F(1, 79) = 7.96, p <.01). Frequency of deviations. An open question is whether the results displayed above are a function of magnitude only (i.e., a few people bet a lot more after losing) or if the frequency of positive and negative deviations also changed as a function of outcome. Sixty percent of participants deviated from the plan. Within this group, preference for positive (61.5%) versus negative deviations did not differ from chance after a gain (z = 1.17, p >.10), whereas preference for positive deviations (78.3 %) was significantly greater than chance after a loss was experienced (z = 2.71, p <.005). The frequency of deviations in gamble 2, therefore, seemed contingent on the outcome of the gamble, although a Chi-square analysis did not reach significance (χ 2 (1; N=49) = 1.60, p =.20). Discussion Experiment 1 produced several initial findings. First, at the planning phase, individuals chose to bet less after an anticipated loss compared to an anticipated gain and compared to a previous bet. This effect shows that individuals do not necessarily disregard the previous outcome when planning the next gamble, but simply believe that losses will affect their behavior in a conservative manner i.e., spend less as wealth declines. Second, asymmetric dynamic inconsistencies emerged at gamble 2 when planned and actual bets are contrasted. For losses, participants bet on average more than they had initially planned, whereas, for gains, planned bets were on average carried over. This effect results from the fact that positive deviations became by far the dominating option after losses, whereas positive and negative deviations were as likely after gains. These findings, at least within this paradigm, are inconsistent with the rationale that in a sequence of gambles people make isolated planned bets, and integrated actual bets. Unlike in the work of Barkan and colleagues, at the planning phase previous outcomes did influence subsequent bets in our experiment. It is again worth noting, however, that in Barkan and Busemeyer s procedure participants (a) were forced to take gamble 1 and (b) had to decide on taking versus not taking gamble 2 (dichotomous variable). Our experiment used a more general procedure which allowed a full possible range of bet choices and no restrictions on whether or not to take the initial gamble. In other words, as in most real gambling scenarios, participants were free to decide on whether and how much they would want to bet in both gambles. Our results replicate Andrade and Iyer s findings with a non-monetary incentive. In other words, whether betting with money or course credit the pattern of results does not change. These findings are consistent with the logic that, ceteris paribus, as long as the incentives are consequential and therefore produce affective reactions, asymmetric dynamic inconsistencies might emerge. There are at least two major concerns. First, the gambles presented null expected values and a 50% chance of winning. Although it certainly facilitated participants straightforward assessment and computation of probabilities and payouts, such gamble structure seems at odds with what is observed in the real world. Would the same asymmetric effects be observed if the gamble displayed negative expected values and lower than 50% chance of winning? Since and Andrade and Iyer also restricted their studies to fair gambles, this question is yet to be addressed. Second, although evidence of asymmetric dynamic inconsistencies is consistent with a hot-cold empathy gap rationale, evidence for the impact feelings on betting decisions cannot be observed 7

8 from experiment 1. Also, if feelings do matter, we wonder whether people would be capable of correcting for their impact when explicitly asked to do so. Experiment 2 tackles these issues. EXPERIMENT 2 This experiment adopted a procedure similar to the one used in experiment 1, except for the following changes. First, each of the two gambles offered a 47.5% chance of doubling the amount bet (EV<0) and a 52.5% of losing the amount bet. Also, participants were allowed to use up to $10 out of the $15 participation fee i in the gambles if they felt like. Precisely, they could bet from $0 to $5 per gamble. As in experiment 1, the incentives were converted into 100 chips (from 0 to 50 chips per gamble). Second, an affect-based judgment correction (hereafter, affective correction) was implemented. Just before the actual bet in gamble 2, half of participants were instructed to make sure that potential feelings generated by the previous gamble, if any, would not influence the betting decision in gamble 2. Notice that this manipulation goes beyond simply highlighting the source of feelings (Schwarz and Clore 1983). Given that normative assessments about the role of feelings in gambling might differ, simply pointing out the presence of affect could produce varying effects. For instance, it is possible that some people, even while recognizing their negative emotions, might not feel it inappropriate to use such feelings to make decisions about subsequent bets. To avoid variance in normative judgments about the role of feelings in decision making, the affective correction manipulation was meant to assure that if feelings were playing a role in participants decisions, they should be corrected. Note that for a correction to take place participants must have a lay theory of about the direction of the effect, believe that it might be happening to them, and be able to control for its impact. Results Three participants bet more than the amount allowed per gamble and were deleted from the sample. Planning phase. Moreover, compared to their planned bets in gamble 1 (M = 23.8), participants reported lower planned bets in gamble 2 after an anticipated loss in the previous gamble (F(1, 178) = 15.87, p <.001), but reported similar planned bets in gamble 2 after an anticipated gain in the previous gamble (F(1, 178) =.02, p >.10). In short, the results replicate the findings in experiment 1 using gambles with negative expected value actual monetary incentives. When compared either to gains or to a previous bet, losses in the planning phase reduced betting amounts in subsequent gambles. Actual phase. To test the impact of feelings on dynamic inconsistencies, we assessed the interaction between betting phase (planned vs. actual) and previous outcomes (gain vs. loss) in gamble 2 when participants were either not provided with any additional instructions (control condition) or instructed to avoid using their feelings prior to bet 2 (affective correction condition). A significant interaction emerged in the control condition (F(1, 95) = 5.46, p <.05). For gains, there was no significant deviation from the plan. Participants who won gamble 1 bet on average the same amount they had previously planned to in anticipation of such gain (M p = 22.8 vs. M a = 21.5; F(1, 95) =.60, p >.10). However, there was a significant deviation from the plan for losses. Participants who lost gamble 1 bet on average more than they had previously planned to bet in anticipation of such loss (M p = 19.3 vs. M a = 23.3; F(1, 95) = 7.1, p <.01). Thus, in the control condition, the interaction replicates the findings of experiment 1 using unfair gambles, negative expected value, and actual monetary incentives. When participants were asked to correct for potential affect-based judgments just before actual bet 2, the interaction between betting phase and outcome disappeared (F(1, 80) =.12, p <.10). Consistent with the predictions, pairwise comparisons showed that the absence of the 8

9 interaction was driven mainly by a reduction in the deviations from the plan in the loss conditions. When participants were asked to avoid using their feelings at the actual phase in gamble 2, there was no difference between a bet in anticipation of a loss (M p = 18.8) and a bet after the loss was realized (M a = 19.9; F(1, 80) =.75, p >.10). Also important, the affective correction manipulation had no influence in participants betting patterns after a gain. Participants who won gamble 1 bet on average the same amount that they had initially planned to bet in anticipation of such gain (M p = 25.7 vs. M a = 26.2; F(1, 80) =.19, p >.10). This is important as it shows that the manipulation produced localized effects as a function of outcome in the first gamble, and not simply a general drop in betting patterns at gamble 2. A marginally significant three-way interaction emerged among betting phase (planned vs. actual), outcome 1 (gain vs. loss), and affective correction (yes vs. no) on betting patterns in gamble 2 (F(1, 175) = 2.74, p <.10). Frequency of deviations. Thirty-eight percent of participants deviated from the plan in gamble 2. An open question is whether, within the loss conditions, the affective correction manipulation reduced the magnitude and/or frequency of positive deviations from the plan. Within the control condition, a chi-square analysis was conducted to assess if the distribution of positive and negative deviations was contingent on the outcome of gamble 1. The results yield a significant interaction (χ 2 (1; N=37) = 6.13, p =.01). After a gain, positive (50%) and negative deviations were as likely (z = 0, p >.10), whereas after a loss preference for positive deviations (88.2%) was significantly greater than chance (z = 3.15, p <.001). Within the affective correction condition, the impact of previous outcome on type of deviation was mitigated (χ 2 (1; N=32) = 2.74, p =.10). However, the effect was not necessarily eliminated. After a loss, preference for positive deviations (75%) was still greater than chance (z = 1.73, p <.05), whereas after a gain, positive (55%) and negative deviations were again as frequent (z =.41, p >.10). Therefore, it seems that the affective correction did not necessarily eliminate the positive deviations after losses as much as it reduced its magnitude. Magnitude of deviations. To provide a clearer assessment of the impact of the affective correction manipulation on the magnitude of the deviations, we selected the 69 participants who deviated (positively or negatively) from the plan and conducted an analysis of variance with outcome 1 (gain vs. loss) and affective correction (yes vs. no) as the two factors and change at gamble 2 (i.e., actual bet 2 (-) planned bet 2) as the main dependent variable. The results yield a marginally significant interaction (F(1, 65) = 3.62, p =.06). Most importantly, the interaction was mainly driven by a clear reduction in the magnitude of positive deviations within the loss domain. When participants were not told to control their emotions during bet 2 (control condition), positive deviations averaged 12.9 chips. However, when asked to correct potential affect-based judgments prior to bet 2, positive deviations reduced to 3.2 chips (F(1, 65) = 3.17, p = 08). After a gain, the affective correction had no impact on the magnitude of the deviations (M control = -2.8 vs. M affective correction = 1.1; F(1, 65) =.69, p <.10). Similarly, within the control condition, there was a significant impact of outcome 1 on the magnitude of deviations in gamble 2 (F(1, 65) = 10.74, p <.01). This difference disappeared within the affective correction condition (F(1, 65) =.16, p >.10). Discussion This second experiment makes three additional contributions. First, it shows that the main findings of the previous experiment replicate in a scenario where the gambles are unfair, the EV is negative, and there are monetary consequences. Once again, at the planning phase, participants bets were lower after anticipated losses (vs. anticipated gains and vs. previous bets). 9

10 Also, at the actual phase in the control condition, participants bet on average more than they had initially planned to bet after a loss, but showed no differences after a gain. In other words, it seems that within this paradigm, as long as the gambles are consequential (monetary or not) and as a result trigger affective reactions, asymmetric dynamic consistencies emerge. Second, the affective correction manipulation mitigated the magnitude of deviations after an anticipated versus actual loss. This suggests, consistent with a hot-cold empathy gap account, that the attempt to reduce an aversive state contributed to over betting in gamble 2 after participants experienced a loss in gamble 1. Third???Also, there was no difference between planned and actual bets for gains, and the affective correction, as expected, did not produce any effects. This null effect is also an important demonstration that the manipulation did not reduce betting patterns in general. Instead, it produced localized effects based on the directional impact of feelings on betting after a loss. In other words, participants seem to (1) acknowledge and (2) be able to correct for the impact of negative feelings on betting after a loss by reducing the extent of positive deviations from the planned bet. Since positive feelings (i.e., after a gain) did not produce significant effects, the affective correction had no impact on the extent of the deviations. A potential criticism toward experiment 2 is the use of an exogenous and heavy-handed manipulation (i.e., affective correction). Moreover, the manipulation does not change people s current states as much as it controls for the impact of these states. In this third study, we address these concerns by focusing on an endogenous manipulation of affect. EXPERIMENT 3 The procedure followed similar to the one used in experiment 1, with two main exceptions. First, participants were asked to report their feelings on a 101 point scale ( Right now, I feel. [0=very bad; 50=neutral; 100=very good; any number from 0 to 100 is allowed] ). Precisely, they were asked to report (1) their current feelings just prior to the betting decision at gamble 1, (2) their expected feelings after winning and after losing their chosen bet, and (3) their actual feelings after the gain or loss was observed. Second, a pre-outcome time delay manipulation was introduced. The flashing period in the gambling board lasted either 3 seconds (short pre-outcome period) or 21 seconds (long pre-outcome period). Note that participants would be exposed to the same time delay on the trial (where information about the gamble is provided) and actual phases of the gamble. Thus, there would not be any information missing about the characteristics of the gamble across the two conditions. Results Planning phase. Participants planned the betting amount in gamble 1, and then, in gamble 2 in anticipation of a gain and in anticipation of a loss. The results showed that previous outcomes influenced subsequent planned bets (F(2, 114) = 4.80, p =.01). Planned bets in gamble 2 were lower in anticipation of a loss (M L = 33.6) and in anticipation of a gain (M G = 33.9) compared to their planned bets in gamble 1 (M = 36.8; F(1, 115) = 6.07, p <.05 and F(1, 115) = 5.03, p <.05, respectively). Planned bets in gamble 2 did not differ from one another when participants anticipated a gain versus a loss (F(1, 115) =.02, p >.10). In other words, at the planning phase, losses and gains discouraged participants from betting in subsequent gambles, showing very conservative planned behavior. Actual phase. First, the betting patterns in gamble 1 did not vary as a function of preoutcome period. Those in the short pre-outcome period condition bet, on average, the same amount (M = 38.6) as those in the long pre-outcome period condition (M = 34.7; F(1, 114) = 1.88, p >.10). This allowed us to compare across pre-outcome conditions. 10

11 In gamble 2, the results varied as a function of the length of the pre-outcome period. Within the long pre-outcome period condition, an interaction emerged between outcome and betting (F(1, 52) = 6.27, p <.05). Participants who won gamble 1, bet, on average, the same amount they had initially planned in anticipation of such gain (M p = 33.7 vs. M a = 31.4; F(1, 52) =.62, p >.10). Participants who lost gamble 1, however, bet more than they had previously planned in anticipation of such loss (M p = 33.0 vs. M a = 40.2; F(1, 52) = 8.55, p =.005). However, when the pre-outcome period was reduced to 3 seconds only, the interaction between outcome and betting phase disappeared (F(1, 60) =.01, p >.10). Participants who won gamble 1 bet on average the same amount they had initially planned in anticipation of such gain (M p = 32.5 vs. M a = 35.4; F(1, 60) = 1.78, p >.10). Moreover, participants who lost gamble 1 also bet on average the same amount they had previously planned to bet in anticipation of such loss (M p = 40.0 vs. M a = 43.4; F(1, 60) = 1.64, p >.10). A marginal three-way interaction emerged among betting phase (planned vs. actual), outcome of gamble 1 (gain vs. loss) and length of the preoutcome period (3 sec vs. 21 sec; F(1, 112) = 3.27, p =.07). Frequency of deviations. A similar analysis was conducted on the frequency of deviations. Thirty percent of participants deviated from the plan in the long pre-outcome period condition and the frequency of deviations in gamble 2 was contingent on the outcome of gamble 1 (χ 2 (1; N=16) = 4.75, p <.05). Within this group, positive (60%) and negative deviations were as frequent after a gain (z =.44, p >.10), whereas preference for positive deviations (91%) was significantly greater than chance after a loss was experienced (z = 2.71, p <.01). In the short preoutcome period condition, thirty one percent of participants deviated from the plan. However, within this condition, the frequency of deviations in gamble 2 was not contingent on the outcome of gamble 1(χ 2 (1; N=19) =.71, p >.10). (Mis)estimation of affect. The subsequent analyses are based on the difference between predicted affective changes and experienced affective changes. First, we hypothesized that after waiting a long (vs. short) period for the outcome to be revealed would influence the affective intensity. Indeed, in the long pre-outcome period condition, people not only felt worse than they have anticipated prior to the loss (M pc_long = vs. M ec_long = -38.7, F(1, 30) = 8.12, p <.01) but they also felt worse than those in the short pre-outcome period condition (M ec_short = -20.3, F(1, 55) = 10.01, p <.01). Interestingly, this pattern emerged despite the fact that, on average, participants in the long pre-outcome period condition lost in gamble 1 less (M = 35.5) than those in the short pre-outcome period condition (M = 42.9; F(1, 55) = 4.33, p <. 05). There was no significant difference between expected and experienced negative feelings in the short preoutcome period condition (M pc_short = F(1, 25) =.63, p >.10). After a gain, there was, on average, no evidence of misestimation of positive feeling in either the long (M pc_long = 30.6 vs. M ec_long = 29.2, F(1, 22) =.18, p >.10) or in the short (M pc_short = 17.1 vs. M ec_short = 21.5, F(1, 35) = 1.82, p >.10) pre-outcome period condition. Moreover, those who waited 3 seconds for the outcome to be revealed felt as happy as those who waited 21 seconds (F(1, 57) =.80, p >.10). On average, participants in the long pre-outcome period condition won in gamble 1 the same amount (M = 33.5) as those in the short pre-outcome period condition (M = 35.7; F(1, 57) =.21, p <.10). In short, participants who waited 21 seconds for the outcome to be revealed felt significantly worse than they had anticipated when a loss was eventually experienced. They also felt worse than those who waited only 3 seconds before the outcome was observed, despite the fact that those in the long per-outcome period condition lost fewer chips. For gains, participants did not on average misestimate their on feelings in either the short or long pre-outcome period 11

12 conditions. Moreover, winners in the long pre-outcome period condition also did not feel better than those in the short pre-outcome period condition. Positive deviations and (mis)estimations of affect. We argue, in line with a hot-cold empathy gap that positive deviations after losses might be due in part to people s tendency to underestimate of the intensity and impact of negative feelings on positive deviations from the plan. To assess this rationale, we tested a potential association between type of affect (mis)estimation (underestimation vs. accurate estimation vs. overestimation) and length of the pre-outcome period (short vs. long). Consistent with our intuitions, after losses, positive deviations were significantly more frequent in the long pre-outcome-underestimation of affect cell than in the other conditions (expected frequency = 16.6%; observed frequency = 50%; χ 2 (2; N=14) = 6.04, p <.05). Also, this association was contrived to the loss condition. Among those who won gamble 1, there was no association between type of affect (mis)estimation and length of the pre-outcome period on frequency of positive deviations (χ 2 (2; N=12) = 2.40, p >.10). In short, an experienced loss after a long pre-outcome period not only increased the frequency of underestimation of affect, but the underestimation of affect was also associated with more positive deviations from the plan. DISCUSSION Experiment 3 shows that the length of the pre-outcome period can modify people s negative feelings after the outcome. Within a certain range, a long (vs. short) time delay between bet and outcome led to stronger than expected negative feelings after the loss was realized. Also, participants felt worse when the loss was preceded by a long (vs. short) pre-outcome periods, despite the fact that those in the long pre-outcome period condition lost on average fewer chips compared to those in the short pre-outcome period condition. Moreover, consistent with a hotcold empathy gap reasoning, underestimation of affect after a loss was positively correlated with frequency of positive deviations from the plan. In other words, those who experienced strong and worse than expected negative feelings (i.e., the underestimation-long pre-outcome period cell) were the ones more likely to bet more than planned once a loss was felt. In the final experiment we further assess the robustness of asymmetric dynamic inconsistencies by testing the impact of consensual decision making. Since risk taking behavior is often done by groups as well as individuals, would the same pattern of results found in the three previous experiment replicate when a group consensus on the betting amount has to be reached beforehand? Experiment 4 addresses this topic. EXPERIMENT 4 Participants were randomly teamed up in groups of 3 and each group had access to one laptop only. The rules of the gamble as well as the trial, planning and actual phases were identical to the ones used in previous experiments. The major difference was that the betting decisions at the planning and actual phases had to be given by the group, and their impacts would be felt by each individual equally. In other words, each individual had his/her on budget (0 to 50 chips per gamble) but had to jointly decide as a group on the bets at the planning and actual phases. For example, if the group decided to bet 30 chips in gamble 1 and lost it, each member would lose 30 out of their own 50 chips. Individual reporting of feelings. Since the impact of gains and losses would be individually felt, it was also possible to assess affective forecasting. Thus, as in the previous experiment each member of the group was asked to report their current, anticipated, and postoutcome feelings. The same scale used in experiment 3 was used in this experiment. The individual affective forecasting would be then average to form the group affective forecasting. 12

13 Results Planning phase. The first question was whether group planning would be as conservative as the individual planning observed in the previous experiments. Participants planned the betting amount in gamble 1, and then, in gamble 2 in anticipation of a gain and in anticipation of a loss. The results showed that contrary to the preceding experiments, on average, the previous outcome did influence subsequent planned bets (F(2, 64) =.26, p >.10). In other words, groups were not behaving as conservatively as individuals did. Planned bets in gamble 2 were the same in anticipation of a loss (M L = 34.7) and in anticipation of a gain (M G = 34.5) compared to their planned bets in gamble 1 (M = 35.6; F(1, 65) =.21, p >.10 and F(1, 65) =.31, p >.10, respectively). Planned bets in gamble 2 did not differ from one another when participants anticipated a gain versus a loss (F(1, 65) =.01, p >.10). Actual phase. Interestingly enough, a different pattern of behavior at the planning phase did not interfere with the pattern of behavior in the actual phase of the gamble. Like in the previous experiments, in gamble 2 there was an interaction between outcome of gamble 1 and betting phase (F(1, 64) = 3.83, p =.05). Groups who won gamble 1, bet on average the same amount they had initially planned in anticipation of such gain (M p = 34.8 vs. M a = 35.9; F(1, 64) =.52, p >.10). Groups who lost gamble 1, however, bet on average more than they had previously planned to bet in anticipation of such loss (M p = 36.8 vs. M a = 42.3; F(1, 64) =.41, p =.001). Frequency of deviations. Twenty six percent of groups deviated from the plan. Within this sample, positive (67%) and negative deviations were as frequent after a gain (z =.83, p >.10), whereas preference for positive deviations (91%) was significantly greater than chance after a loss was experienced (z = 2.72, p <.01). The frequency of deviations in gamble 2, therefore, seemed contingent on the outcome of the gamble, although a chi-square analysis did not reach significance (χ 2 (1; N=17) =1.57, p =.21). Misestimation of affect. Group s feelings were obtained by averaging individuals feelings. The subsequent analyses are based on the difference between the group s predicted and experienced affective changes. Similar to experiment 3, the result show that whereas the groups accurately predicted their feelings after a gain (M pc = 22.9 vs. M ec 21.6, F(1, 64) =.16, p >.10) they felt significantly worse than they had anticipated to feel as a result of a loss (M pc = vs. M ec = -41.9, F(1, 64) = 7.80, p <.01). A marginal interaction between the outcome of the gamble and the affective measure (predicted vs. experienced) also emerged (F(1, 64) = 2.74, p =.10). Positive deviations and misestimations of affect. The open question is whether those groups who positively deviated from the plan after a loss were more likely to have underestimated their negative feelings in the first place. The results confirmed this intuition. Ten groups bet more than planned after a loss. Out of those, 80% had underestimated their negative feelings prior to the betting decision in gamble 2, a number significantly greater than chance (z = 1.90, p <.05). In line with our hypothesis, the number of groups who bet more than planned after a gain was quite small (N=4) and half of those had underestimated their positive feelings whereas the other half had actually overestimated them. Discussion This final experiment demonstrates that the assymetric dynamic inconsistencies apply to consensual decision making as well. When participants in groups of 3 were required to jointly decide on the amount bet, they bet more than planned after a loss and, on average, carry over the planned bets after a gain. Note that this pattern emerged despite the fact that the groups did not plan to behave conservatively (i.e., anticipate to bet less after a loss). In other words, the fact 13

14 people bet more than planned after a loss seems to not be confined to scenarios where in the planning phase they anticipate betting less after a loss. Furthermore, in groups as in individuals, the results suggest that this effect is linked to a misestimation of affect after a loss, with groups underestimating their own aggregate negative affect after losing a gamble.. Importantly, such underestimation of negative feelings was associated with positive deviations from the plan. The groups which felt worse than expected were the ones more likely to bet more than planned. No misestimation of positive feelings emerged. Moreover, there was no association between misestimations and type of deviations for those groups which won gamble 1. GENERAL DISCUSSION Consumers misestimate betting behavior. Even in a scenario where participants have full information about the characteristics of the gamble prior to a planning phase, losses lead to higher than planned bets whereas bets are on average carried over after gains. Our result substantiate Andrade and Iyer s initial findings and shed further light into the underlying processes and the impact of negative feelings. In a series of 4 experiment, we show that, within this paradigm, assymetric dynamic inconsistencies are particularly robust. They emerge when (1) monetary and non-monetary incentivies are used, when participants face (2) fair and unfair gambles, and when the betting decision happens (3) individually or in groups. The reason for the assymetry lies on people s inability to predict how much the negative feelings generated by the loss will influence them to bet more than planned in an attempt to restablish a homeostatic state in the prospect of winning. Since for gains, there is no sense of deprivation, no specific pattern of deviation becomes dominant. Consistent his this rationale, Experiment 2 shows that when partiticipants are asked to correct for the impact of feelings on subsequent bets, the asymmetry dissipates. Experiment 3 demonstrates that a very short pre-outcome period alleviates the negativity associated with the loss, and hence, reduces people s decision to bet more than planned after a loss is felt. In short, it seems that negative feelings attached the losses are critical to trigger overreactions in an attempt to elimate the unpleasant feeling. Our results are also in line with recent propositions that loss aversion is in fact a negative emotion (e.g., fear), which might explain why people tend to overreact to it (Camerer 2005). LIMITATIONS AND FUTURE RESEARCH However, a few lmitations and open questions remain. One might argue that our results emerge because our sample (undergrad students) is relatively naïve. More experienced gamblers would not make the same mistake. Indeed, it is an interesting question whether learning can help mitigate the asymmetric dynamic inconsistencies. In other words, can someone overtime learn when to stop after a loss is experienced? Our experiment 2 shows that people are capable of recognizing the impact of negative feelings on future bets and are able to correct for it. Thus, on the one hand, one might speculate that learning will reduce dynamic inconsistencies as long as people realize during the process that they are underestimating the intensity and impact of their negative feelings on future betting decisions. On the other hand, the fact that people have in general a limited capacity of anticiapting actual feelings, might make it difficult to learn about its future impact. This is certainly an important question to be addressed in the literature. Another potential criticism to our gambling paradigm, and to most lab experiments, is the lack of external validity. We suspect, however, that the effects we observed in the lab actually be conservative relative to what might be seen in the real world. A clear implication of our findigns is that endogenous and exogenous manipulation of feelings influence betting patterns indenpendently of actual changes in probabilities and pay outs. In our third experiment, 14

15 we have showed this by varying the amount of time people waited for the outcome to be revealed. Longer (vs. shorter) time delay produced stronger affective reactions, and more deviations from the plan after losses. Multiple other cues might and have been used in the gaming environments. From noisy machines to free drinks, Casinos adopt several tactics to instigate people s feelings during the games. Therefore, it is not unreasonable to suggest that in actual gambling environments the gap between cold (netural feelings at planning) and hot states (actual feelings when losses are felt) might be even wider than in our labs. As a result, stronger deviations from the plan could materialize. According to the american gaming association, consumer spending in commercial casinos alone went from $17.10 billion in 1996 to $32.42 billion in How much of this amount represents deviations from the plan is far from clear. However, if our results can at least in part be extrapolated, it seems that a signficant proportion of consumer spending in casinos may actually represent unplanned (uncontrolled?) behavior. To the extent that the unplanned expenditures capture a significant chunck of one s discretionary income, our research also raises public policy questions about potential negative impact of gaming even among non-pathological gamblers (i.e., the vast majority of consumers). Future research should further address this issue. REFERENCES Allsop, S. and B. Saunders (1989), Relapse and Alcohol Problems. In Relapse and Addictive Behaviour. Ed. M. Gossop (pp ). New York: Tavistokc/Routledge. Andrade, Eduardo B. & Ganesh Iyer (2007), Dynamic Inconsistencies in Gambling and the Role of Feelings, Working Paper. University of California, Berkeley. Badger, Gary J., Warren K. Bickel, Louis A. Giordano, Eric A. Jacobs, George Loewenstein, and Lisa Marsch (2007). Altered States: The Impact of Immediate Craving on the Valuation of Current and Future Opioids. Journal of Health Economics, 26 (September), Barkan, Rachel and Jerome R. Busemeyer (2003), Modeling Dynamic Inconsistency with a Changing Reference Point, Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 16 (May), Barkan, Rachel, Shai Danzinger, Guy Ben-Bashat, and Jemore R. Busemeyer (2005), Framing Reference Points: The Effect of Integration and Segregation on Dynamic Inconsistency, Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 18, Camerer, Colin (2005). Three Cheers Psychological, Theoretical, Empirical for Loss Aversion, Journal of Marketing Research, XLII (May), Dickerson, Mark, John Hinchy, Stephanie L. England, John Fabre, and Ross Cunningham (1992), On the determinants of persistent gambling behaviour. I. High-frequency poker machine players, British Journal of Psychology, 83 (May), Elfenbein, H. A., Marsh, A., & Ambady, N. (2002). Emotional intelligence and the recognition of emotion from the face. In L. F. Barrett & P. Salovey (Eds.), The wisdom of feelings: Processes underlying emotional intelligence (pp ). New York: Guilford. Gilbert, Daniel T., Michael J. Gill, and Timothy D. Wilson (2002), The Future is Now: Temporal Correction in Affective Forecasting, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 88 (May), Hackman JR, ed Groups That Work andthose That Don t. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass Hatfield, E., Cacioppo, J. T., & Rapson, R. L. (1994). Emotional contagion.new York: Cambridge University Press. Hess, U., Banse, R., & Kappas, A. (1995). The intensity of facial expression is determined by underlying affective state and social situation.journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 69,

16 Kahneman, Daniel and Amos Tversky (1979), Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision Under Risk, Econometrica, 47(2), Loewenstein, George (1996), Out of Control: Visceral Influences on Behavior, Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 65(3), (2000), Emotions in Economic Theory and Economic Behavior, American Economic Review: Papers and Proceedings, 90, Loewenstein, George and Daniel Adler (1995), A Bias in the Prediction of Tastes, The Economic Journal, 105 (July), Loewenstein, George, Drazen Prelec, and C. Shatto (1996), Hot/cold intrapersonal empathy gaps and the prediction of curiosity, Working Paper, Pittsburgh: Carnegie-Mellon University. Loewenstein, George, Ted O Donoghue and Matthew Rabin (2003), Projection Bias in Predicting Future Utility, The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 118 (November), Loewenstein, G.F., Hsee, C.K., Weber, E.U., & Welch, N. (2001). Risk as feelings. Psychological Bulletin: 127 (2), Myers, D. G. (1978). Polarizing effects of social comparison. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 14, Myers, D. G., & Lamm, H. (1976). The group polarization phenomenon. Psychological Bulletin, 83, Nisbett, Richard E. and David E. Kanouse (1968), Obesity, Hunger, and Supermarket Shopping Behavior, Proceedings of the Annual Convention of the American Psychological Association, 3, Ostroff, Cheri (1992). The relationship between satisfaction, attitudes, and performance: An organizational level analysis. Journal of Applied Psychology, 77, Ostroff, Cheri (1993) Comparing correlations based on individual-level and aggregated data. Journal of Applied Psychology, 78, 4, Pope, Robin (1983), The Pre-Outcome period and the Utility of Gambling, In Foundations of Utility and Risk Theory with Applications, ed. Bernt P. Stigum and Fred Wenstøp, Dordrecht (Holland): Reidel, Pruitt, Dean G. and Alan I. Teger (1969), The risky shift in group betting. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 5 (April), Schwarz, Norbert and Gerald L. Clore (1983), Mood, Misattribution, and Judgment of Well- Being: Informative and Directive Functions of Affective States, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 45 (September), Van Boven, L., Loewenstein, G., & Dunning, D. (2005). The illusion of courage in social predictions: Underestimating the impact of fear of embarrassment on other people. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 96, Wardle, Jane and Sally Beales (1988), Control and Loss of Control Over Eating: An Experimental Investigation, Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 97 (1), Wulfert, Edelgard, Brian D. Roland, Julie Hartley, Naitian Wang, Christine Franco (2005). Heart Rate, Arousal, and Excitement in Gambling: Winners versus Losers, Psychology of Addictive Behaviors. 19,

ASSOCIATION FOR CONSUMER RESEARCH

ASSOCIATION FOR CONSUMER RESEARCH ASSOCIATION FOR CONSUMER RESEARCH Labovitz School of Business & Economics, University of Minnesota Duluth, 11 E. Superior Street, Suite 210, Duluth, MN 55802 The Unexpected Enjoyment of Expected Events:

More information

Banking on a Bad Bet: Probability Matching in Risky Choice Is Linked to Expectation Generation

Banking on a Bad Bet: Probability Matching in Risky Choice Is Linked to Expectation Generation Research Report Banking on a Bad Bet: Probability Matching in Risky Choice Is Linked to Expectation Generation Psychological Science 22(6) 77 711 The Author(s) 11 Reprints and permission: sagepub.com/journalspermissions.nav

More information

Prospect Theory Ayelet Gneezy & Nicholas Epley

Prospect Theory Ayelet Gneezy & Nicholas Epley Prospect Theory Ayelet Gneezy & Nicholas Epley Word Count: 2,486 Definition Prospect Theory is a psychological account that describes how people make decisions under conditions of uncertainty. These may

More information

We never talked directly about the next two questions, but THINK about them they are related to everything we ve talked about during the past week:

We never talked directly about the next two questions, but THINK about them they are related to everything we ve talked about during the past week: ECO 220 Intermediate Microeconomics Professor Mike Rizzo Third COLLECTED Problem Set SOLUTIONS This is an assignment that WILL be collected and graded. Please feel free to talk about the assignment with

More information

A Statistical Analysis of Popular Lottery Winning Strategies

A Statistical Analysis of Popular Lottery Winning Strategies CS-BIGS 4(1): 66-72 2010 CS-BIGS http://www.bentley.edu/csbigs/vol4-1/chen.pdf A Statistical Analysis of Popular Lottery Winning Strategies Albert C. Chen Torrey Pines High School, USA Y. Helio Yang San

More information

Compass Interdisciplinary Virtual Conference 19-30 Oct 2009

Compass Interdisciplinary Virtual Conference 19-30 Oct 2009 Compass Interdisciplinary Virtual Conference 19-30 Oct 2009 10 Things New Scholars should do to get published Duane Wegener Professor of Social Psychology, Purdue University Hello, I hope you re having

More information

Expected Value and the Game of Craps

Expected Value and the Game of Craps Expected Value and the Game of Craps Blake Thornton Craps is a gambling game found in most casinos based on rolling two six sided dice. Most players who walk into a casino and try to play craps for the

More information

! Insurance and Gambling

! Insurance and Gambling 2009-8-18 0 Insurance and Gambling Eric Hehner Gambling works as follows. You pay some money to the house. Then a random event is observed; it may be the roll of some dice, the draw of some cards, or the

More information

From Loss Aversion to Loss Acceptance: How Casino Contexts Can Undermine Loss Aversion. Working Paper. October 13, 2008

From Loss Aversion to Loss Acceptance: How Casino Contexts Can Undermine Loss Aversion. Working Paper. October 13, 2008 1 From Loss Aversion to Loss Acceptance: How Casino Contexts Can Undermine Loss Aversion Joseph P. Simmons Nathan Novemsky* Working Paper October 13, 2008 Please do not cite without permission. * Joseph

More information

1 Uncertainty and Preferences

1 Uncertainty and Preferences In this chapter, we present the theory of consumer preferences on risky outcomes. The theory is then applied to study the demand for insurance. Consider the following story. John wants to mail a package

More information

A Loss-Sensitivity Explanation of Integration of Prior Outcomes in Risky Decisions

A Loss-Sensitivity Explanation of Integration of Prior Outcomes in Risky Decisions A Loss-Sensitivity Explanation of Integration of Prior Outcomes in Risky Decisions J. Romanus, L. Hassing, and T. Gärling Department of Psychology Göteborg University Romanus, J., Hassing, L., & Gärling,

More information

Beating Roulette? An analysis with probability and statistics.

Beating Roulette? An analysis with probability and statistics. The Mathematician s Wastebasket Volume 1, Issue 4 Stephen Devereaux April 28, 2013 Beating Roulette? An analysis with probability and statistics. Every time I watch the film 21, I feel like I ve made the

More information

Choice Under Uncertainty

Choice Under Uncertainty Decision Making Under Uncertainty Choice Under Uncertainty Econ 422: Investment, Capital & Finance University of ashington Summer 2006 August 15, 2006 Course Chronology: 1. Intertemporal Choice: Exchange

More information

Betting on Excel to enliven the teaching of probability

Betting on Excel to enliven the teaching of probability Betting on Excel to enliven the teaching of probability Stephen R. Clarke School of Mathematical Sciences Swinburne University of Technology Abstract The study of probability has its roots in gambling

More information

MA 1125 Lecture 14 - Expected Values. Friday, February 28, 2014. Objectives: Introduce expected values.

MA 1125 Lecture 14 - Expected Values. Friday, February 28, 2014. Objectives: Introduce expected values. MA 5 Lecture 4 - Expected Values Friday, February 2, 24. Objectives: Introduce expected values.. Means, Variances, and Standard Deviations of Probability Distributions Two classes ago, we computed the

More information

TABLE OF CONTENTS. ROULETTE FREE System #1 ------------------------- 2 ROULETTE FREE System #2 ------------------------- 4 ------------------------- 5

TABLE OF CONTENTS. ROULETTE FREE System #1 ------------------------- 2 ROULETTE FREE System #2 ------------------------- 4 ------------------------- 5 IMPORTANT: This document contains 100% FREE gambling systems designed specifically for ROULETTE, and any casino game that involves even money bets such as BLACKJACK, CRAPS & POKER. Please note although

More information

Market efficiency in greyhound racing: empirical evidence of absence of favorite-longshot bias

Market efficiency in greyhound racing: empirical evidence of absence of favorite-longshot bias Market efficiency in greyhound racing: empirical evidence of absence of favorite-longshot bias Anil Gulati, Western New England College, agulati@wnec.edu Shekar Shetty, Western New England College, sshetty@wnec.edu

More information

Many recent studies of Internet gambling particularly

Many recent studies of Internet gambling particularly GLRE-2012-1655-ver9-Auer_1P.3d 04/09/12 2:46pm Page 1 GAMING LAW REVIEW AND ECONOMICS Volume 16, Number 5, 2012 Ó Mary Ann Liebert, Inc. DOI: 10.1089/glre.2012.1655 GLRE-2012-1655-ver9-Auer_1P Type: research-article

More information

Section 7C: The Law of Large Numbers

Section 7C: The Law of Large Numbers Section 7C: The Law of Large Numbers Example. You flip a coin 00 times. Suppose the coin is fair. How many times would you expect to get heads? tails? One would expect a fair coin to come up heads half

More information

IS MORE INFORMATION BETTER? THE EFFECT OF TRADERS IRRATIONAL BEHAVIOR ON AN ARTIFICIAL STOCK MARKET

IS MORE INFORMATION BETTER? THE EFFECT OF TRADERS IRRATIONAL BEHAVIOR ON AN ARTIFICIAL STOCK MARKET IS MORE INFORMATION BETTER? THE EFFECT OF TRADERS IRRATIONAL BEHAVIOR ON AN ARTIFICIAL STOCK MARKET Wei T. Yue Alok R. Chaturvedi Shailendra Mehta Krannert Graduate School of Management Purdue University

More information

A THEORETICAL ANALYSIS OF THE MECHANISMS OF COMPETITION IN THE GAMBLING MARKET

A THEORETICAL ANALYSIS OF THE MECHANISMS OF COMPETITION IN THE GAMBLING MARKET A THEORETICAL ANALYSIS OF THE MECHANISMS OF COMPETITION IN THE GAMBLING MARKET RORY MCSTAY Senior Freshman In this essay, Rory McStay describes the the effects of information asymmetries in the gambling

More information

Using Retrocausal Practice Effects to Predict On-Line Roulette Spins. Michael S. Franklin & Jonathan Schooler UCSB, Department of Psychology.

Using Retrocausal Practice Effects to Predict On-Line Roulette Spins. Michael S. Franklin & Jonathan Schooler UCSB, Department of Psychology. Using Retrocausal Practice Effects to Predict On-Line Roulette Spins Michael S. Franklin & Jonathan Schooler UCSB, Department of Psychology Summary Modern physics suggest that time may be symmetric, thus

More information

Market Efficiency and Behavioral Finance. Chapter 12

Market Efficiency and Behavioral Finance. Chapter 12 Market Efficiency and Behavioral Finance Chapter 12 Market Efficiency if stock prices reflect firm performance, should we be able to predict them? if prices were to be predictable, that would create the

More information

How To Check For Differences In The One Way Anova

How To Check For Differences In The One Way Anova MINITAB ASSISTANT WHITE PAPER This paper explains the research conducted by Minitab statisticians to develop the methods and data checks used in the Assistant in Minitab 17 Statistical Software. One-Way

More information

REVERSALS OF PREFERENCE BETWEEN BIDS AND CHOICES IN GAMBLING DECISIONS 1

REVERSALS OF PREFERENCE BETWEEN BIDS AND CHOICES IN GAMBLING DECISIONS 1 Journal o/ Experimental Psychology 97, Vol. 89, No., 46-55 REVERSALS OF PREFERENCE BETWEEN BIDS AND CHOICES IN GAMBLING DECISIONS SARAH LICHTENSTEIN AND PAUL SLOVIC 2 Oregon Research Institute, Eugene

More information

Ignoring base rates. Ignoring base rates (cont.) Improving our judgments. Base Rate Neglect. When Base Rate Matters. Probabilities vs.

Ignoring base rates. Ignoring base rates (cont.) Improving our judgments. Base Rate Neglect. When Base Rate Matters. Probabilities vs. Ignoring base rates People were told that they would be reading descriptions of a group that had 30 engineers and 70 lawyers. People had to judge whether each description was of an engineer or a lawyer.

More information

(SEE IF YOU KNOW THE TRUTH ABOUT GAMBLING)

(SEE IF YOU KNOW THE TRUTH ABOUT GAMBLING) (SEE IF YOU KNOW THE TRUTH ABOUT GAMBLING) Casinos loosen the slot machines at the entrance to attract players. FACT: This is an urban myth. All modern slot machines are state-of-the-art and controlled

More information

This Method will show you exactly how you can profit from this specific online casino and beat them at their own game.

This Method will show you exactly how you can profit from this specific online casino and beat them at their own game. This Method will show you exactly how you can profit from this specific online casino and beat them at their own game. It s NOT complicated, and you DON T need a degree in mathematics or statistics to

More information

Understanding pricing anomalies in prediction and betting markets with informed traders

Understanding pricing anomalies in prediction and betting markets with informed traders Understanding pricing anomalies in prediction and betting markets with informed traders Peter Norman Sørensen Økonomi, KU GetFIT, February 2012 Peter Norman Sørensen (Økonomi, KU) Prediction Markets GetFIT,

More information

Introduction to the Rebate on Loss Analyzer Contact: JimKilby@usa.net 702-436-7954

Introduction to the Rebate on Loss Analyzer Contact: JimKilby@usa.net 702-436-7954 Introduction to the Rebate on Loss Analyzer Contact: JimKilby@usa.net 702-436-7954 One of the hottest marketing tools used to attract the premium table game customer is the "Rebate on Loss." The rebate

More information

.4 120 +.1 80 +.5 100 = 48 + 8 + 50 = 106.

.4 120 +.1 80 +.5 100 = 48 + 8 + 50 = 106. Chapter 16. Risk and Uncertainty Part A 2009, Kwan Choi Expected Value X i = outcome i, p i = probability of X i EV = pix For instance, suppose a person has an idle fund, $100, for one month, and is considering

More information

Fixed Odds Betting Terminals and the Code of Practice. A report for the Association of British Bookmakers Limited SUMMARY ONLY

Fixed Odds Betting Terminals and the Code of Practice. A report for the Association of British Bookmakers Limited SUMMARY ONLY Fixed Odds Betting Terminals and the Code of Practice A report for the Association of British Bookmakers Limited SUMMARY ONLY Europe Economics Chancery House 53-64 Chancery Lane London WC2A 1QU Tel: (+44)

More information

A Hands-On Exercise Improves Understanding of the Standard Error. of the Mean. Robert S. Ryan. Kutztown University

A Hands-On Exercise Improves Understanding of the Standard Error. of the Mean. Robert S. Ryan. Kutztown University A Hands-On Exercise 1 Running head: UNDERSTANDING THE STANDARD ERROR A Hands-On Exercise Improves Understanding of the Standard Error of the Mean Robert S. Ryan Kutztown University A Hands-On Exercise

More information

Elementary Statistics and Inference. Elementary Statistics and Inference. 16 The Law of Averages (cont.) 22S:025 or 7P:025.

Elementary Statistics and Inference. Elementary Statistics and Inference. 16 The Law of Averages (cont.) 22S:025 or 7P:025. Elementary Statistics and Inference 22S:025 or 7P:025 Lecture 20 1 Elementary Statistics and Inference 22S:025 or 7P:025 Chapter 16 (cont.) 2 D. Making a Box Model Key Questions regarding box What numbers

More information

MANIPULATING SLOT MACHINE PREFERENCE IN PROBLEM GAMBLERS THROUGH CONTEXTUAL CONTROL BECKY L. NASTALLY, MARK R. DIXON, AND JAMES W.

MANIPULATING SLOT MACHINE PREFERENCE IN PROBLEM GAMBLERS THROUGH CONTEXTUAL CONTROL BECKY L. NASTALLY, MARK R. DIXON, AND JAMES W. JOURNAL OF APPLIED BEHAVIOR ANALYSIS 2010, 43, 125 129 NUMBER 1(SPRING 2010) MANIPULATING SLOT MACHINE PREFERENCE IN PROBLEM GAMBLERS THROUGH CONTEXTUAL CONTROL BECKY L. NASTALLY, MARK R. DIXON, AND JAMES

More information

Social Facilitation in Online and Offline Gambling: A Pilot Study

Social Facilitation in Online and Offline Gambling: A Pilot Study DOI 10.1007/s11469-010-9281-6 Social Facilitation in Online and Offline Gambling: A Pilot Study Tom Cole & Douglas J. K. Barrett & Mark D. Griffiths # Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2010 Abstract

More information

2 What is Rational: Normative. 4 Lottery & Gambling

2 What is Rational: Normative. 4 Lottery & Gambling 1 Decision Making 2 What is Rational: Normative Key Question: Are you Rational? Deviations from rationality: Value is subjective (utility, and more..). Value is multidimensional (multiple budgets, not

More information

The NCAA Basketball Betting Market: Tests of the Balanced Book and Levitt Hypotheses

The NCAA Basketball Betting Market: Tests of the Balanced Book and Levitt Hypotheses The NCAA Basketball Betting Market: Tests of the Balanced Book and Levitt Hypotheses Rodney J. Paul, St. Bonaventure University Andrew P. Weinbach, Coastal Carolina University Kristin K. Paul, St. Bonaventure

More information

Standard 12: The student will explain and evaluate the financial impact and consequences of gambling.

Standard 12: The student will explain and evaluate the financial impact and consequences of gambling. STUDENT MODULE 12.1 GAMBLING PAGE 1 Standard 12: The student will explain and evaluate the financial impact and consequences of gambling. Risky Business Simone, Paula, and Randy meet in the library every

More information

Sleeping Beauty, as described on wikipedia, citing Arnold

Sleeping Beauty, as described on wikipedia, citing Arnold Sleeping Beauty Sleeping Beauty, as described on wikipedia, citing Arnold Zuboff Sleeping Beauty volunteers to undergo the following experiment. On Sunday she is given a drug that sends her to sleep. A

More information

AMS 5 CHANCE VARIABILITY

AMS 5 CHANCE VARIABILITY AMS 5 CHANCE VARIABILITY The Law of Averages When tossing a fair coin the chances of tails and heads are the same: 50% and 50%. So if the coin is tossed a large number of times, the number of heads and

More information

Introduction to. Hypothesis Testing CHAPTER LEARNING OBJECTIVES. 1 Identify the four steps of hypothesis testing.

Introduction to. Hypothesis Testing CHAPTER LEARNING OBJECTIVES. 1 Identify the four steps of hypothesis testing. Introduction to Hypothesis Testing CHAPTER 8 LEARNING OBJECTIVES After reading this chapter, you should be able to: 1 Identify the four steps of hypothesis testing. 2 Define null hypothesis, alternative

More information

Demand for Health Insurance

Demand for Health Insurance Demand for Health Insurance Demand for Health Insurance is principally derived from the uncertainty or randomness with which illnesses befall individuals. Consequently, the derived demand for health insurance

More information

If You Think Investing is Gambling, You re Doing it Wrong!

If You Think Investing is Gambling, You re Doing it Wrong! If You Think Investing is Gambling, You re Doing it Wrong! Warren Buffet Jennifer Arthur, M.Sc. PhD Candidate, University of Adelaide Supervisor: Dr. Paul Delfabbro 10th European Conference on Gambling

More information

How to Win the Stock Market Game

How to Win the Stock Market Game How to Win the Stock Market Game 1 Developing Short-Term Stock Trading Strategies by Vladimir Daragan PART 1 Table of Contents 1. Introduction 2. Comparison of trading strategies 3. Return per trade 4.

More information

HONORS STATISTICS. Mrs. Garrett Block 2 & 3

HONORS STATISTICS. Mrs. Garrett Block 2 & 3 HONORS STATISTICS Mrs. Garrett Block 2 & 3 Tuesday December 4, 2012 1 Daily Agenda 1. Welcome to class 2. Please find folder and take your seat. 3. Review OTL C7#1 4. Notes and practice 7.2 day 1 5. Folders

More information

The Very Best Way We Know to Play the Trifecta

The Very Best Way We Know to Play the Trifecta Frandsen Publishing Presents Favorite ALL-Ways TM Newsletter Articles The Very Best Way We Know to Play the Trifecta When approached properly, the Trifecta is not only a fun wager, but it can be wonderfully

More information

Ad-Hoc Committee on Academic Integrity. Survey Summary Report

Ad-Hoc Committee on Academic Integrity. Survey Summary Report Ad-Hoc Committee on Academic Integrity Survey Summary Report Presented at the UAA Faculty Senate Retreat 24 August 2011 CONTENTS I. Methodology II. Perceptions of Academically Dishonest Behaviors Table

More information

American Economic Association

American Economic Association American Economic Association Does the Basketball Market Believe in the `Hot Hand,'? Author(s): Colin F. Camerer Source: The American Economic Review, Vol. 79, No. 5 (Dec., 1989), pp. 1257-1261 Published

More information

Why is Insurance Good? An Example Jon Bakija, Williams College (Revised October 2013)

Why is Insurance Good? An Example Jon Bakija, Williams College (Revised October 2013) Why is Insurance Good? An Example Jon Bakija, Williams College (Revised October 2013) Introduction The United States government is, to a rough approximation, an insurance company with an army. 1 That is

More information

HIGH-RISK STOCK TRADING: INVESTMENT OR GAMBLING?

HIGH-RISK STOCK TRADING: INVESTMENT OR GAMBLING? HIGH-RISK STOCK TRADING: INVESTMENT OR GAMBLING? Jennifer Arthur, M.Sc. PhD Candidate, University of Adelaide Co-Authors: Dr. Paul Delfabbro & Dr. Robert Williams 14 th Annual Alberta Research Gambling

More information

Mental-accounting portfolio

Mental-accounting portfolio Portfolios for Investors Who Want to Reach Their Goals While Staying on the Mean Variance Efficient Frontier SANJIV DAS is a professor of finance at the Leavey School of Business, Santa Clara University,

More information

THE DETERMINANTS OF SCORING IN NFL GAMES AND BEATING THE SPREAD

THE DETERMINANTS OF SCORING IN NFL GAMES AND BEATING THE SPREAD THE DETERMINANTS OF SCORING IN NFL GAMES AND BEATING THE SPREAD C. Barry Pfitzner, Department of Economics/Business, Randolph-Macon College, Ashland, VA 23005, bpfitzne@rmc.edu, 804-752-7307 Steven D.

More information

Wald s Identity. by Jeffery Hein. Dartmouth College, Math 100

Wald s Identity. by Jeffery Hein. Dartmouth College, Math 100 Wald s Identity by Jeffery Hein Dartmouth College, Math 100 1. Introduction Given random variables X 1, X 2, X 3,... with common finite mean and a stopping rule τ which may depend upon the given sequence,

More information

$2 4 40 + ( $1) = 40

$2 4 40 + ( $1) = 40 THE EXPECTED VALUE FOR THE SUM OF THE DRAWS In the game of Keno there are 80 balls, numbered 1 through 80. On each play, the casino chooses 20 balls at random without replacement. Suppose you bet on the

More information

Eliminating Over-Confidence in Software Development Effort Estimates

Eliminating Over-Confidence in Software Development Effort Estimates Eliminating Over-Confidence in Software Development Effort Estimates Magne Jørgensen 1 and Kjetil Moløkken 1,2 1 Simula Research Laboratory, P.O.Box 134, 1325 Lysaker, Norway {magne.jorgensen, kjetilmo}@simula.no

More information

Applied Economics For Managers Recitation 5 Tuesday July 6th 2004

Applied Economics For Managers Recitation 5 Tuesday July 6th 2004 Applied Economics For Managers Recitation 5 Tuesday July 6th 2004 Outline 1 Uncertainty and asset prices 2 Informational efficiency - rational expectations, random walks 3 Asymmetric information - lemons,

More information

Leaving Money on the Table

Leaving Money on the Table Student Aid Policy Analysis Leaving Money on the Table www.edvisors.com/ask/student aid policy/leaving money on the table/ Mark Kantrowitz Senior Vice President and Publisher January 12, 2015 Edvisors

More information

Statistics in Medicine Research Lecture Series CSMC Fall 2014

Statistics in Medicine Research Lecture Series CSMC Fall 2014 Catherine Bresee, MS Senior Biostatistician Biostatistics & Bioinformatics Research Institute Statistics in Medicine Research Lecture Series CSMC Fall 2014 Overview Review concept of statistical power

More information

CHAPTER 1: INTRODUCTION, BACKGROUND, AND MOTIVATION. Over the last decades, risk analysis and corporate risk management activities have

CHAPTER 1: INTRODUCTION, BACKGROUND, AND MOTIVATION. Over the last decades, risk analysis and corporate risk management activities have Chapter 1 INTRODUCTION, BACKGROUND, AND MOTIVATION 1.1 INTRODUCTION Over the last decades, risk analysis and corporate risk management activities have become very important elements for both financial

More information

MONEY MANAGEMENT. Guy Bower delves into a topic every trader should endeavour to master - money management.

MONEY MANAGEMENT. Guy Bower delves into a topic every trader should endeavour to master - money management. MONEY MANAGEMENT Guy Bower delves into a topic every trader should endeavour to master - money management. Many of us have read Jack Schwager s Market Wizards books at least once. As you may recall it

More information

Using Behavioral Economics to Improve Diversification in 401(k) Plans: Solving the Company Stock Problem

Using Behavioral Economics to Improve Diversification in 401(k) Plans: Solving the Company Stock Problem Using Behavioral Economics to Improve Diversification in 401(k) Plans: Solving the Company Stock Problem Shlomo Benartzi The Anderson School at UCLA Richard H. Thaler The University of Chicago Investors

More information

Herd Behavior and Underdogs in the NFL

Herd Behavior and Underdogs in the NFL Herd Behavior and Underdogs in the NFL Sean Wever 1 David Aadland February 2010 Abstract. Previous research has failed to draw any clear conclusions about the efficiency of the billion-dollar gambling

More information

The Mathematics of Alcoholics Anonymous

The Mathematics of Alcoholics Anonymous The Mathematics of Alcoholics Anonymous "As a celebrated American statesman put it, 'Let's look at the record. Bill Wilson, Alcoholics Anonymous, page 50, A.A.W.S. Inc., 2001. Part 2: A.A. membership surveys

More information

THE WINNING ROULETTE SYSTEM by http://www.webgoldminer.com/

THE WINNING ROULETTE SYSTEM by http://www.webgoldminer.com/ THE WINNING ROULETTE SYSTEM by http://www.webgoldminer.com/ Is it possible to earn money from online gambling? Are there any 100% sure winning roulette systems? Are there actually people who make a living

More information

"SEO vs. PPC The Final Round"

SEO vs. PPC The Final Round "SEO vs. PPC The Final Round" A Research Study by Engine Ready, Inc. Examining The Role Traffic Source Plays in Visitor Purchase Behavior January 2008 Table of Contents Introduction 3 Definitions 4 Methodology

More information

Are Longshots Only for Losers? A New Look at the Last Race Effect

Are Longshots Only for Losers? A New Look at the Last Race Effect Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, J. Behav. Dec. Making (2015) Published online in Wiley Online Library (wileyonlinelibrary.com).1873 Are Longshots Only for Losers? A New Look at the Last Race Effect

More information

Low-Volatility Investing: Expect the Unexpected

Low-Volatility Investing: Expect the Unexpected WHITE PAPER October 2014 For professional investors Low-Volatility Investing: Expect the Unexpected David Blitz, PhD Pim van Vliet, PhD Low-Volatility Investing: Expect the Unexpected 1 Expect the unexpected

More information

Executive summary. Participation in gambling activities (Chapter 2)

Executive summary. Participation in gambling activities (Chapter 2) Executive summary This report presents results from the British Gambling Prevalence Survey (BGPS) 2010. This is the third nationally representative survey of its kind; previous studies were conducted in

More information

The Independence Referendum: Predicting the Outcome 1. David N.F. Bell

The Independence Referendum: Predicting the Outcome 1. David N.F. Bell The Independence Referendum: Predicting the Outcome 1 David N.F. Bell Division of Economics Stirling Management School, University of Stirling, IZA, Bonn and ESRC Centre for Population Change 1 Thanks

More information

Lecture 15. Ranking Payoff Distributions: Stochastic Dominance. First-Order Stochastic Dominance: higher distribution

Lecture 15. Ranking Payoff Distributions: Stochastic Dominance. First-Order Stochastic Dominance: higher distribution Lecture 15 Ranking Payoff Distributions: Stochastic Dominance First-Order Stochastic Dominance: higher distribution Definition 6.D.1: The distribution F( ) first-order stochastically dominates G( ) if

More information

The Rational Gambler

The Rational Gambler The Rational Gambler Sahand Rabbani Introduction In the United States alone, the gaming industry generates some tens of billions of dollars of gross gambling revenue per year. 1 This money is at the expense

More information

We show that prospect theory offers a rich theory of casino gambling, one that captures several features

We show that prospect theory offers a rich theory of casino gambling, one that captures several features MANAGEMENT SCIENCE Vol. 58, No. 1, January 2012, pp. 35 51 ISSN 0025-1909 (print) ISSN 1526-5501 (online) http://dx.doi.org/10.1287/mnsc.1110.1435 2012 INFORMS A Model of Casino Gambling Nicholas Barberis

More information

Decision Theory. 36.1 Rational prospecting

Decision Theory. 36.1 Rational prospecting 36 Decision Theory Decision theory is trivial, apart from computational details (just like playing chess!). You have a choice of various actions, a. The world may be in one of many states x; which one

More information

VISUAL GUIDE to. RX Scripting. for Roulette Xtreme - System Designer 2.0

VISUAL GUIDE to. RX Scripting. for Roulette Xtreme - System Designer 2.0 VISUAL GUIDE to RX Scripting for Roulette Xtreme - System Designer 2.0 UX Software - 2009 TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION... ii What is this book about?... iii How to use this book... iii Time to start...

More information

Week 5: Expected value and Betting systems

Week 5: Expected value and Betting systems Week 5: Expected value and Betting systems Random variable A random variable represents a measurement in a random experiment. We usually denote random variable with capital letter X, Y,. If S is the sample

More information

Elementary Statistics and Inference. Elementary Statistics and Inference. 17 Expected Value and Standard Error. 22S:025 or 7P:025.

Elementary Statistics and Inference. Elementary Statistics and Inference. 17 Expected Value and Standard Error. 22S:025 or 7P:025. Elementary Statistics and Inference S:05 or 7P:05 Lecture Elementary Statistics and Inference S:05 or 7P:05 Chapter 7 A. The Expected Value In a chance process (probability experiment) the outcomes of

More information

Expected Value. 24 February 2014. Expected Value 24 February 2014 1/19

Expected Value. 24 February 2014. Expected Value 24 February 2014 1/19 Expected Value 24 February 2014 Expected Value 24 February 2014 1/19 This week we discuss the notion of expected value and how it applies to probability situations, including the various New Mexico Lottery

More information

Betting with the Kelly Criterion

Betting with the Kelly Criterion Betting with the Kelly Criterion Jane June 2, 2010 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Kelly Criterion 2 3 The Stock Market 3 4 Simulations 5 5 Conclusion 8 1 Page 2 of 9 1 Introduction Gambling in all forms,

More information

CROSS EXAMINATION OF AN EXPERT WITNESS IN A CHILD SEXUAL ABUSE CASE. Mark Montgomery

CROSS EXAMINATION OF AN EXPERT WITNESS IN A CHILD SEXUAL ABUSE CASE. Mark Montgomery CROSS EXAMINATION OF AN EXPERT WITNESS IN A CHILD SEXUAL ABUSE CASE Mark Montgomery Post Office Box 161 Durham, NC 27702 (919) 680-6249 mark.montgomery@mindspring.com Opinion Testimony by a Pediatrician/Nurse/Counselor/Social

More information

Probability and Expected Value

Probability and Expected Value Probability and Expected Value This handout provides an introduction to probability and expected value. Some of you may already be familiar with some of these topics. Probability and expected value are

More information

Choice under Uncertainty

Choice under Uncertainty Choice under Uncertainty Part 1: Expected Utility Function, Attitudes towards Risk, Demand for Insurance Slide 1 Choice under Uncertainty We ll analyze the underlying assumptions of expected utility theory

More information

Evaluating Trading Systems By John Ehlers and Ric Way

Evaluating Trading Systems By John Ehlers and Ric Way Evaluating Trading Systems By John Ehlers and Ric Way INTRODUCTION What is the best way to evaluate the performance of a trading system? Conventional wisdom holds that the best way is to examine the system

More information

Betfair According To Wikipedia

Betfair According To Wikipedia betfair GREEN calculator 2009 Hello, My name is Derek Johnstone and I am the developer of the betfair GREEN calculator 2009, The calculator was created in March 2009 to aid my trading calculations on the

More information

Artificial Intelligence Beating Human Opponents in Poker

Artificial Intelligence Beating Human Opponents in Poker Artificial Intelligence Beating Human Opponents in Poker Stephen Bozak University of Rochester Independent Research Project May 8, 26 Abstract In the popular Poker game, Texas Hold Em, there are never

More information

Decision & Risk Analysis Lecture 6. Risk and Utility

Decision & Risk Analysis Lecture 6. Risk and Utility Risk and Utility Risk - Introduction Payoff Game 1 $14.50 0.5 0.5 $30 - $1 EMV 30*0.5+(-1)*0.5= 14.5 Game 2 Which game will you play? Which game is risky? $50.00 Figure 13.1 0.5 0.5 $2,000 - $1,900 EMV

More information

SOME ASPECTS OF GAMBLING WITH THE KELLY CRITERION. School of Mathematical Sciences. Monash University, Clayton, Victoria, Australia 3168

SOME ASPECTS OF GAMBLING WITH THE KELLY CRITERION. School of Mathematical Sciences. Monash University, Clayton, Victoria, Australia 3168 SOME ASPECTS OF GAMBLING WITH THE KELLY CRITERION Ravi PHATARFOD School of Mathematical Sciences Monash University, Clayton, Victoria, Australia 3168 In this paper we consider the problem of gambling with

More information

Do testosterone levels in females have influence on the distrust game, the beauty contest game, and risk-aversion?

Do testosterone levels in females have influence on the distrust game, the beauty contest game, and risk-aversion? Do testosterone levels in females have influence on the distrust game, the beauty contest game, and risk-aversion? Takafumi MATSUBA, Jun SATO and Kenya KURA Abstract One of the famous neuroscientific studies

More information

EFFICIENCY IN BETTING MARKETS: EVIDENCE FROM ENGLISH FOOTBALL

EFFICIENCY IN BETTING MARKETS: EVIDENCE FROM ENGLISH FOOTBALL The Journal of Prediction Markets (2007) 1, 61 73 EFFICIENCY IN BETTING MARKETS: EVIDENCE FROM ENGLISH FOOTBALL Bruno Deschamps and Olivier Gergaud University of Bath University of Reims We analyze the

More information

Marketing Automation And the Buyers Journey

Marketing Automation And the Buyers Journey Marketing Automation And the Buyers Journey A StrategyMix White Paper By Jonathan Calver, Managing Director, StrategyMix About this Paper This paper will first introduce you to the principles and concepts

More information

Testing Efficiency in the Major League of Baseball Sports Betting Market.

Testing Efficiency in the Major League of Baseball Sports Betting Market. Testing Efficiency in the Major League of Baseball Sports Betting Market. Jelle Lock 328626, Erasmus University July 1, 2013 Abstract This paper describes how for a range of betting tactics the sports

More information

PAYMENT PROTECTION INSURANCE RESEARCH

PAYMENT PROTECTION INSURANCE RESEARCH PAYMENT PROTECTION INSURANCE RESEARCH ANALYTICAL REPORT NOVEMBER 2015 ABOUT COMRES ComRes provides specialist research and insight into reputation, public policy and communications. It is a founding member

More information

During the last several years, poker has grown in popularity. Best Hand Wins: How Poker Is Governed by Chance. Method

During the last several years, poker has grown in popularity. Best Hand Wins: How Poker Is Governed by Chance. Method Best Hand Wins: How Poker Is Governed by Chance Vincent Berthet During the last several years, poker has grown in popularity so much that some might even say it s become a social phenomenon. Whereas poker

More information

The power of money management

The power of money management The power of money management One trader lost ($3000) during the course of a year trading one contract of system A. Another trader makes $25,000 trading the same system that year. One trader makes $24,000

More information

Problem Gambling. Over the last decade, legalized gambling in Canada has grown - rapidly! So has problem gambling!

Problem Gambling. Over the last decade, legalized gambling in Canada has grown - rapidly! So has problem gambling! Problem Gambling Introduction Over the last decade, legalized gambling in Canada has grown - rapidly! So has problem gambling! Should people with mood disorders be especially concerned? Probably yes! There

More information

Game Theory and Poker

Game Theory and Poker Game Theory and Poker Jason Swanson April, 2005 Abstract An extremely simplified version of poker is completely solved from a game theoretic standpoint. The actual properties of the optimal solution are

More information

Solutions: Problems for Chapter 3. Solutions: Problems for Chapter 3

Solutions: Problems for Chapter 3. Solutions: Problems for Chapter 3 Problem A: You are dealt five cards from a standard deck. Are you more likely to be dealt two pairs or three of a kind? experiment: choose 5 cards at random from a standard deck Ω = {5-combinations of

More information

Gambling, Leisure and Pleasure: Exploring Psychosocial Need Satisfaction in Gambling

Gambling, Leisure and Pleasure: Exploring Psychosocial Need Satisfaction in Gambling Gambling, Leisure and Pleasure: Exploring Psychosocial Need Satisfaction in Gambling Dr. Jonathan Parke, Sophro, U.K. Dr. Robert Williams, University of Lethbridge, Canada Context questions for the audience

More information

Basic Concepts in Research and Data Analysis

Basic Concepts in Research and Data Analysis Basic Concepts in Research and Data Analysis Introduction: A Common Language for Researchers...2 Steps to Follow When Conducting Research...3 The Research Question... 3 The Hypothesis... 4 Defining the

More information