Descriptive Set Theory

Similar documents
1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set.

MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 6.436J/15.085J Fall 2008 Lecture 5 9/17/2008 RANDOM VARIABLES

Extension of measure

Georg Cantor ( ):

There is no degree invariant half-jump

Full and Complete Binary Trees

CS 3719 (Theory of Computation and Algorithms) Lecture 4

INTRODUCTION TO DESCRIPTIVE SET THEORY

1 if 1 x 0 1 if 0 x 1

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 3. Spaces with special properties

o-minimality and Uniformity in n 1 Graphs

Basic Concepts of Point Set Topology Notes for OU course Math 4853 Spring 2011

SOLUTIONS TO ASSIGNMENT 1 MATH 576

CHAPTER 1 BASIC TOPOLOGY

INTRODUCTORY SET THEORY

E3: PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS lecture notes

An example of a computable

9 More on differentiation

INDISTINGUISHABILITY OF ABSOLUTELY CONTINUOUS AND SINGULAR DISTRIBUTIONS

Descriptive Set Theory

Metric Spaces Joseph Muscat 2003 (Last revised May 2009)

MA651 Topology. Lecture 6. Separation Axioms.

Math/Stats 425 Introduction to Probability. 1. Uncertainty and the axioms of probability

x < y iff x < y, or x and y are incomparable and x χ(x,y) < y χ(x,y).

How To Find Out How To Calculate A Premeasure On A Set Of Two-Dimensional Algebra

CHAPTER 7 GENERAL PROOF SYSTEMS

This asserts two sets are equal iff they have the same elements, that is, a set is determined by its elements.

God created the integers and the rest is the work of man. (Leopold Kronecker, in an after-dinner speech at a conference, Berlin, 1886)

THE DEGREES OF BI-HYPERHYPERIMMUNE SETS

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces

INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY

THE SEARCH FOR NATURAL DEFINABILITY IN THE TURING DEGREES

COFINAL MAXIMAL CHAINS IN THE TURING DEGREES

Lecture Notes on Measure Theory and Functional Analysis

Math 104: Introduction to Analysis

Introduction to Topology

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

GENTLY KILLING S SPACES TODD EISWORTH, PETER NYIKOS, AND SAHARON SHELAH

INTRODUCTION TO TOPOLOGY

Lecture 2: Universality

Undergraduate Notes in Mathematics. Arkansas Tech University Department of Mathematics

This chapter is all about cardinality of sets. At first this looks like a

Metric Spaces. Chapter 1

MODELS OF SET THEORY

TOPOLOGY: THE JOURNEY INTO SEPARATION AXIOMS

Lecture Notes on Topology for MAT3500/4500 following J. R. Munkres textbook. John Rognes

SET-THEORETIC CONSTRUCTIONS OF TWO-POINT SETS

Notes on descriptive set theory and applications to Banach spaces. Th. Schlumprecht

(IALC, Chapters 8 and 9) Introduction to Turing s life, Turing machines, universal machines, unsolvable problems.

3. Mathematical Induction

Mathematical Methods of Engineering Analysis

Set theory as a foundation for mathematics

SMALL SKEW FIELDS CÉDRIC MILLIET

Dedekind s forgotten axiom and why we should teach it (and why we shouldn t teach mathematical induction in our calculus classes)

MEASURE AND INTEGRATION. Dietmar A. Salamon ETH Zürich

Elements of probability theory

a 11 x 1 + a 12 x a 1n x n = b 1 a 21 x 1 + a 22 x a 2n x n = b 2.

CS 103X: Discrete Structures Homework Assignment 3 Solutions

The Ideal Class Group

The Markov-Zariski topology of an infinite group

Mathematical Induction

The Henstock-Kurzweil-Stieltjes type integral for real functions on a fractal subset of the real line

Omega Automata: Minimization and Learning 1

I. Pointwise convergence

CLASSES, STRONG MINIMAL COVERS AND HYPERIMMUNE-FREE DEGREES

Mathematics for Computer Science/Software Engineering. Notes for the course MSM1F3 Dr. R. A. Wilson

Lecture Note 1 Set and Probability Theory. MIT Spring 2006 Herman Bennett

arxiv:math/ v3 [math.gn] 31 Oct 2010

Mathematics for Econometrics, Fourth Edition

Notes on metric spaces

RANDOM INTERVAL HOMEOMORPHISMS. MICHA L MISIUREWICZ Indiana University Purdue University Indianapolis

8 Divisibility and prime numbers

The sample space for a pair of die rolls is the set. The sample space for a random number between 0 and 1 is the interval [0, 1].

On Integer Additive Set-Indexers of Graphs

Metric Spaces. Chapter Metrics

Basic Probability Concepts

ON THE COEFFICIENTS OF THE LINKING POLYNOMIAL

A Course in Discrete Structures. Rafael Pass Wei-Lung Dustin Tseng

Regular Languages and Finite Automata

PSEUDOARCS, PSEUDOCIRCLES, LAKES OF WADA AND GENERIC MAPS ON S 2

CODING TRUE ARITHMETIC IN THE MEDVEDEV AND MUCHNIK DEGREES

CHAPTER 1. Internal Set Theory

GENERIC COMPUTABILITY, TURING DEGREES, AND ASYMPTOTIC DENSITY

LEARNING OBJECTIVES FOR THIS CHAPTER

How many numbers there are?

Degrees that are not degrees of categoricity

Georg Cantor and Set Theory

FEGYVERNEKI SÁNDOR, PROBABILITY THEORY AND MATHEmATICAL

6.3 Conditional Probability and Independence

THE BANACH CONTRACTION PRINCIPLE. Contents

Some other convex-valued selection theorems 147 (2) Every lower semicontinuous mapping F : X! IR such that for every x 2 X, F (x) is either convex and

CSE 135: Introduction to Theory of Computation Decidability and Recognizability

DEGREES OF ORDERS ON TORSION-FREE ABELIAN GROUPS

So let us begin our quest to find the holy grail of real analysis.

P NP for the Reals with various Analytic Functions

1. (First passage/hitting times/gambler s ruin problem:) Suppose that X has a discrete state space and let i be a fixed state. Let

Lebesgue Measure on R n

Automata on Infinite Words and Trees

University of Miskolc

A BASIS THEOREM FOR Π 0 1 CLASSES OF POSITIVE MEASURE AND JUMP INVERSION FOR RANDOM REALS ROD DOWNEY AND JOSEPH S. MILLER

Transcription:

Martin Goldstern Institute of Discrete Mathematics and Geometry Vienna University of Technology Ljubljana, August 2011

Polish spaces Polish space = complete metric separable. Examples N = ω = {0, 1, 2,...}. R = real numbers. (E.g., Dedekind cuts) 2 ω = Cantor space = all infinite 01-sequences ω ω = Baire space = all infinite sequences of natural numbers. R n, R ω, (2 ω ) ω 2 ω.... many others

Polish spaces: convergence Polish space X = complete metric separable. To understand these spaces, we need to understand convergence in these spaces. a 1 = (5, 5, 5, 5, 5, 5...) a 2 = (3, 8, 0, 0, 0, 0,...) a 3 = (3, 6, 0, 5, 0, 0,...) a 3 = (3, 1, 4, 6, 0, 0,...) a 9 = (3, 1, 4, 1, 11, 1,...)... a ω = (3, 1, 4, 1, 5, 9, 2, 6,...). C X is closed, if convergent sequences in C have limit in C. U X is open iff X \ U is closed.

Continuum Hypothesis Cantor s Continuum Hypothesis (CH): Every infinite subset of the reals is either countable or equinumerous with R (or with 2 ω, i.e., contains a 1-1 copy of 2 ω ). (Hilbert s problem list, 1900: first problem.) The continuum hypothesis is neither provable nor refutable (from the usual axioms of set theory). (Cantor thought he had a proof.)

Perfect sets X=Polish, e.g. R or 2 ω. A nonempty set P X is perfect if P is closed P has no isolated points. (Every point in P is a limit of a sequence of distinct points in P.) Examples: [0, 1] R C [0, 1], the Cantor set. 2 ω C. Fact S X contains a perfect set iff S contains a Cantor set, i.e., iff there is a continuous injective map from 2 ω into S. Hence: If X contains a perfect set, then X is uncountable.

Fact S X contains a perfect set iff S contains a Cantor set, i.e., iff there is a continuous injective map from 2 ω into S. Corollary If X contains a nonempty perfect set, then X is uncountable. Question Is the converse true? Effective continuum hypothesis: Every infinite subset of the reals is either countable or contains a perfect set, i.e., contains a 1-1 continuous copy of 2 ω.

Effective Continuum Hypothesis Effective continuum hypothesis: Every infinite subset of the reals is either countable or contains a perfect set, i.e., contains a 1-1 continuous copy of 2 ω. The effective continuum hypothesis is (strictly speaking) false, but in practice often true. Refutable in ZFC. But the counterexample is complicated. Not refutable in ZF without the axiom of choice. (disclaimer... ) Provable for many definable sets in ZFC, even in ZF. Provable for most definable sets in ZFC+large cardinals. Thesis: Never claim that a set is merely uncountable when you can in fact show that it contains a perfect set.

Perfect set property A class C of subsets of X has the perfect set property if each uncountable set in C contains a perfect set. (I.e., if all sets in C satisfy the effective CH.) EXAMPLES: open sets closed sets Borel sets analytic sets Note: being countable is a positive property. Being uncountable is a negative property. But contains a perfect set is positive!

Borel sets. Π 0 ω Σ 0 ω 0 ω... G δ = Π 0 2 Σ 0 2 = F σ closed = Π 0 1 0 2 Σ 0 1 = open 0 1

Borel sets, examples We consider subsets of 2 ω. {x 2 ω : x(2) = 0 & x(3) = 1} is clopen, i.e., 0 1. The set of all eventually zero sequences is countable, hence F σ, i.e., Σ 0 2. The set U of all uniformly distributed sequences is Π 0 3 : n x U k m n m : i=0 x(i) 1 n 2 1 k U = 1 0 = Π 0 1 = Σ 0 2 = Π0 3 k ω m ω m n k ω m ω k ω

The perfect set property for closed sets Theorem (Cantor-Bendixson) Let X be a closed uncountable set. (Subset of R n, of 2 ω, etc.) Then there is a perfect set P such that C := X \ P is countable. Proof sketch. Let C 0 be the set of isolated points of X. C 0 must be countable, and X (1) := X \ C 0 is still closed uncountable. Continue for infinitely many steps: X X (1) X (2). Stop when C n = (then X (n) is perfect). If you are not done after ω steps, let X (ω) := X (n), and continue. This process (of taking Cantor-Bendixson derivatives ) must stop at a countable ordinal.

Analytic sets An analogy: Borel sets have a flavour that is similar to recursive (=decidable) subsets of the natural numbers. (E.g.: closed under complements.) Analytic sets correspond to r.e. sets (recursively enumerable, computably enumerable, semi-decidable). (Not closed under complements.) Another analogy: Borel sets have a flavour that is similar to sets in P = polynomially decidable sets. Analytic sets correspond to sets in NP.

Analytic sets, several definitions Let X be a Polish space (R n, ω ω, etc). Let S X be nonempty. Then the following are equivalent: 1. There is a continuous F : ω ω X with F [ω ω ] = S. 2. There is a continuous F : ω ω X and a closed set C ω ω with F [C] = S. 3. As above, but C may be a Borel set. 4. There is a closed (or Borel) subset of ω ω X whose projection to X is exactly S.

Analytic sets, THE definition Let X be a Polish space. S X is analytic if S = or there is a continuous map F : ω ω X with F [ω ω ] = S. (We should check X itself is analytic under this definition.) Rule of thumb: Anything involving only k ω, k ω, k ω, k ω is a Borel set. If you have to use y ω ω or r R, then analytic and usually not Borel. Example {x ω ω (n 1 < n 2 < ) : x n1 x n2 } is analytic, not Borel. {x ω ω (n 1 < n 2 < ) : x n1 = x n2 = } is Borel.

Closure properties The family of analytic sets contains all closed sets and is closed under countable unions (hence contains all closed sets), countable intersections (hence contains all Borel sets), continuous images (by definition), continuous preimages. But NOT under complement. Empirical fact: (100-ε)% of all sets considered in analysis are Borel sets. (100-ε)% of the remaining ε% are analytic (or co-analytic).

The perfect set property for analytic sets Let F : ω ω X be continuous, and assume that A := F [ω ω ] is uncountable. We claim that A contains a perfect set. More precisely: we will find a copy of 2 ω in ω ω on which F is 1-1. For s ω <ω, we write [s] for the {x : x ω ω, s x} (= all branches extending the node s.) For s ω <ω, we write F [s] for the set {f (x) : x ω ω, s x}. We will show our claim under the additional assumption that F [s] has more than one element, for each s. (This can easily be arranged: Iteratively remove those s for which this is not true; with each s we remove from ω ω all elements extending s, but all of them have the same image. Since only countably many s were removed, only countably many elements from A were removed.)

The perfect set property for analytic sets, part 2 Assumption: F : ω ω X is continuous, and for each s ω <ω the set F [s] := {f (x) : x ω ω, s f } has > 1 elements. (NOTE: for different s, the sets F [s] are not necessarily disjoint. If they were, everything would be trivial.) Construction: 1. Let t :=, the empty sequence. 2. We find two disjoint nonempty open sets U 0, U 1 in F[t]. 3. We find t 0, t 1 ω <ω, extending t, such that F [t l ] U l. (Use continuity of F.) 4. Continue by splitting t 0 to t 00 and t 01, and t 1 to t 10, t 11, using disjoint open sets U 00, U 01, U 10, U 11. 5. etc.

The perfect set property for analytic sets, part 3 What we have: For each finite 0, 1-sequence s we have found a finite sequence t s ω <ω such that: If s extends s, then t s extends t s If s and s are incompatible, then also t s and t s are incompatible, and moreover: F [t s ] and F[t s are disjoint. What we want: A continuous 1-1 map from 2 ω into F [ω ω ]. Easy: For each x 2 ω, say x = (a, b, c,...), let t x be the limit of t, t a, t ab, t abc. The map x F (t x ) is 1-1 and continuous.

Lebesgue measure Every open subset U of R is a union of (finitely or countably many) disjoint intervals. The measure µ(u) of U is the sum of the lengths of these intervals. The measure µ is defined on all Borel sets, and it is σ-additive. A set N R has measure zero if for all ε there exists an open set U of measure < ε with N U. A set S R is measurable iff there exists a Borel (or Σ 0 2 ) set B such that B S has measure 0. We set µ(s) := µ(b).

Measure, continued Theorem All analytic sets are measurable. Definition Let X, Y be measure spaces. A function g : X Y is measurable if g 1 (U) is measurable for all open sets U Y. Measurable functions from some unspecified space X into our space Y are called random variables in statistics.

Uniformisation Theorem (AC) Let S X Y, and assume πs = X, i.e., x X : S x := {y Y (x, y) S}. Then there is a function g : X Y whose graph is contained in S, i.e., g(x) S x for all x. (This theorem is equivalent to the axiom of choice.) Theorem ( Uniformisation theorem ) Assume that S from above is nice. Then we can find a nice g. (Usually without the axiom of choice.)

Jankov-von Neumann Theorem Let S X Y be analytic, πs = X. Then there is a measurable function g S. For the proof, we may assume that S is closed: Let S = F [ω ω ], and Ŝ := {(x, y, z) X Y ω ω (x, y) = F (z)} X (Y ω ω ) If we can find a function ĝ : X Y ω ω uniformizing Ŝ, then we get g uniformizing S by projection. (Details omitted.)

Closed subsets of ω ω Let C ω ω. The set T C := {c n : c C, n ω} ω <ω is a tree. (Downward closed set of finite sequences.) (Moreover, T C has no leaves = nodes without extensions.) We write [T C ] for the set of its branches: [T C ] := {x ω ω : n x n T C } C. It is easy to check that [T C ] = closure of C. Hence: Closed sets = trees without leaves.

Jankov-von Neumann for closed sets Theorem Let C ω ω ω ω be closed, πc = X. Then there is a nice (in fact: measurable) function g C. Proof sketch. For each x ω ω, the set C x := {y : (x, y) C} is closed, so C x = [T x ] for some tree T x. Let g(x) := the leftmost branch of [T x ]. This is a nicely defined function, hence measurable. (Need to check details.)

An application Fact Let (B n : n ω) be a family of sets of measure zero. Then n B n has measure zero. (Trivially.) But: There are families (B x : x ω ω ) of measure zero sets such that in x B x does not have measure zero. (Easy to find.) Theorem Let (B x : x ω ω ) be a nice family of sets Y with the following property: Whenever x 1 x 2, then B x1 B x2. Then the set x ω ω B x still has measure zero. ( nice means that the set {(x, y) : y B x } is a Borel (or analytic) set. By x 1 x 2 I means that x 1 (n) x 2 (n) for all n.)