Bound and Referential Pronouns and Ellipsis. Heim and Kratzer Chapter 9

Similar documents
Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 3: Covert Movement vs. Type Shifting 1

The compositional semantics of same

Movement and Binding

Handout #1: Mathematical Reasoning

What VP Ellipsis Can Do, and What it Can t, but not Why *

Syntactic and Semantic Differences between Nominal Relative Clauses and Dependent wh-interrogative Clauses

Cross-linguistic differences in the interpretation of sentences with more than one QP: German (Frey 1993) and Hungarian (É Kiss 1991)

Examining domain widening and NPI any 1 Ana Arregui University of Ottawa

Non-nominal Which-Relatives

bound Pronouns

Scope or Pseudoscope? Are there Wide-Scope Indefinites? 1

CONTEXT AND LOGICAL FORM

Introduction: Presuppositions in Context Theoretical Issues and Experimental Perspectives

2. SEMANTIC RELATIONS

3. Mathematical Induction

In Defense of Kantian Moral Theory Nader Shoaibi University of California, Berkeley

COMPARATIVES WITHOUT DEGREES: A NEW APPROACH. FRIEDERIKE MOLTMANN IHPST, Paris fmoltmann@univ-paris1.fr

THERE ARE SEVERAL KINDS OF PRONOUNS:

Phrase Structure Rules, Tree Rewriting, and other sources of Recursion Structure within the NP

P1. All of the students will understand validity P2. You are one of the students C. You will understand validity

Read this syllabus very carefully. If there are any reasons why you cannot comply with what I am requiring, then talk with me about this at once.

Constituency. The basic units of sentence structure

ELLIPSIS AND REPAIR EFFECTS * Seichi Sugawa Nanzan University and Nagoya Gakuin University

When the Present is all in the Past* Pranav Anand and Valentine Hacquard

A (Covert) Long Distance Anaphor in English

Quine on truth by convention

English auxiliary verbs

Arguments and Dialogues

Paraphrasing controlled English texts

UNBOUND ANAPHORIC PRONOUNS: E-TYPE, DYNAMIC, AND STRUCTURED-PROPOSITIONS APPROACHES

Syntax: Phrases. 1. The phrase

Constraints in Phrase Structure Grammar

Type-Ambiguous Names Anders J. Schoubye 1

Syntactic Theory. Background and Transformational Grammar. Dr. Dan Flickinger & PD Dr. Valia Kordoni

E-type pronouns: congressmen, sheep and paychecks

Discourse Markers in English Writing

SYNTAX: THE ANALYSIS OF SENTENCE STRUCTURE

Mathematical Induction

Degree Operators and Scope

The structure of the English Sentence

Invalidity in Predicate Logic

Noam Chomsky: Aspects of the Theory of Syntax notes

In Mr. Donnellan and Humpty Dumpty on Referring, Alfred MacKay

Kant s deontological ethics

Are There Tense Operators in English?

YOU DON T SAY? KENT BACH

The Refutation of Relativism

CS4025: Pragmatics. Resolving referring Expressions Interpreting intention in dialogue Conversational Implicature

Ellipsis and Anaphora

Introduction: Reading and writing; talking and thinking

Sentences, Statements and Arguments

Objective and subjective ought. Ralph Wedgwood

Is the Symmetry Problem Really a Problem?

GESE Initial steps. Guide for teachers, Grades 1 3. GESE Grade 1 Introduction

Understanding English Grammar: A Linguistic Introduction

The parts of speech: the basic labels

Cambridge English: Advanced Speaking Sample test with examiner s comments

Impossible Words? Jerry Fodor and Ernest Lepore

Actuality and fake tense in conditionals *

Predicate Logic Review

Structure of Clauses. March 9, 2004

Relative truth and the first person

Meaning and communication, swearing and silence

MINUTES. COMMISSION ON CONSTITUTIONAL MATTERS Telephone Conference Call, June 20, 2016

TERMS. Parts of Speech

Outline of today s lecture

Langue and Parole. John Phillips

Rethinking the relationship between transitive and intransitive verbs

On Shared Indefinite NPs in Coordinative Structures *

Basic Notions of Information Structure *

The Syntax of Predicate Logic

Descriptions as Variables

INTRUSION PREVENTION AND EXPERT SYSTEMS

19. Morphosyntax in L2A

Lecture 1: OT An Introduction

Quantifier Scope in Formal Linguistics

This handout will help you understand what relative clauses are and how they work, and will especially help you decide when to use that or which.

You will by now not be surprised that a version of the teleological argument can be found in the writings of Thomas Aquinas.

Reply to French and Genone Symposium on Naïve Realism and Illusion The Brains Blog, January Boyd Millar

Albert Pye and Ravensmere Schools Grammar Curriculum

Pronouns. Their different types and roles. Devised by Jo Killmister, Skills Enhancement Program, Newcastle Business School

Inductive Reasoning Page 1 of 7. Inductive Reasoning

Mind on Statistics. Chapter 12

LESSON TITLE: Jesus Heals Blind Bartimaeus

ON WHITCOMB S GROUNDING ARGUMENT FOR ATHEISM Joshua Rasmussen Andrew Cullison Daniel Howard-Snyder

MARY. V NP NP Subject Formation WANT BILL S

CHAPTER 2. Logic. 1. Logic Definitions. Notation: Variables are used to represent propositions. The most common variables used are p, q, and r.

Semantics versus Pragmatics

Refer to: Present & future If-clause Main clause. ZERO Present + Present. If you can meet me at the car, that s easiest for me.

English Appendix 2: Vocabulary, grammar and punctuation

Three Ways to Clarify Your Writing

ONLINE SAFETY TEACHER S GUIDE:

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products

How To Answer The Question Of If There Is A God Or Not In The World

L130: Chapter 5d. Dr. Shannon Bischoff. Dr. Shannon Bischoff () L130: Chapter 5d 1 / 25

Extraposition, the Right Roof Constraint, Result Clauses, Relative Clause Extraposition, and PP Extraposition

Adjective, Adverb, Noun Clauses. Gerund,Participial and Infinitive Phrases. English Department

KET for Schools Reading and Writing Part 9 teacher s notes

English Grammar Passive Voice and Other Items

Do we need Structured Question Meanings? Two Approaches to Questions

Transcription:

Bound and Referential Pronouns and Ellipsis Heim and Kratzer Chapter 9 1

9.1 Referential pronouns as free variables 2

9.1.1 Deictic versus anaphoric, referential versus bound-variable pronouns In traditional grammar, a pronoun is said to be used deictically when it receives its reference from the extra-linguistic context, and it is used anaphorically when it picks up its reference from another phrase in the surrounding text. Paradigm cases of the deictic use are demonstrative uses those accompanied by a pointing gesture, but even in the absence of pointing an extralinguistic referent that is sufficiently salient can suffice, as in (1): (1) I am glad he is gone. 3

9.1.1 Deictic versus anaphoric, referential versus bound-variable pronouns (cont.) It isn t clear whether the distinction between deictic and anaphoric uses has any role to play in linguistic theory. Anaphora may often be viewed as reference to a contextually salient individual as well. It seems to differ from deixis only insofar as the cause of the referent s salience is concerned. For instance when he in an utterance of (2) refers to Smith, this may be attributed to the fact that Smith has just been made salient by being referred to in the previous sentence. (2) I don t think anybody here is interested in Smith s work. He should not be invited. 4

9.1.1 Deictic versus anaphoric, referential versus bound-variable pronouns (cont.) In both anaphora and deixis, the pronoun refers to an individual, which, for whatever reason, is highly salient at the moment when the pronoun is processed, whether this is due to an act of pointing, to previous mention, or some other reason. Let us assume, then, that all deicitc and many anaphoric pronouns are interpreted by the same general strategy: listeners assign reference to the most salient individual that allows them to make sense of the utterance. If the most salient individual is not an appropriate referent, it will be passed over in favor of the next most salient individual until a plausible referent is found. How this is done is a matter for psycholinguistic research. As semanticists we abstract away from the strategies of reference resolution and the conditions they require to succeed. 5

9.1.1 Deictic versus anaphoric, referential versus bound-variable pronouns (cont.) Can all examples of anaphoric pronouns be subsumed under this characterization? No. Some pronouns don t refer to individuals at all, e.g. pronouns that occur in such that clauses or are bound by quantifiers, as (3): (3) Every man put a screen in front of him. This means that it is coindexed with QR trace of its antecedent and interpreted by the following rule: (4) Pronouns and Traces Rule If α is a pronoun or trace, i is an index, and g is a variable assignment whose domain includes i, then [[α]] g = g(i). 6

9.1.1 Deictic versus anaphoric, referential versus bound-variable pronouns (cont.) Would it be possible to treat all anaphoric pronouns as bound variables? For (2), we d have to raise the DP Smith high enough to c-command the entire two-sentence text. We assume such LFs can t be generated due to constraints on movement. Similarly, some intrasentential cases would involve moving out of islands, which is prohibited, as in (5). (5) Most accidents that Mary reported were caused by her cat. We conclude that at least some anaphoric pronouns are best analyzed as referring pronouns, just like deicitc pronouns. 7

9.1.1 Deictic versus anaphoric, referential versus bound-variable pronouns (cont.) We use the term co-reference in opposition to variable binding, and we always mean it in this technical sense. We will use the term anaphora (and antecedent ) as a general term to cover both cases. Two expressions (or occurrences of expressions) co-refer iff they refer to the same individual. If two expressions co-refer, then each of them refers to something. Bound variable pronouns cannot co-refer with any expression. Thus we distinguish two cases of pronoun uses: bound-variable uses and (co)-referring uses. We don t need a distinction between anaphora and deixis. 8

9.1.2 Utterance contexts and variable assignments To handle referring pronouns, the simplest assumption is that they are interpreted in the same way as bound pronouns. It is just that they are free variables. They will be interpreted by our existing Pronouns and Traces rule, and the assignment function. We will no longer assume that an LF whose truth value varies from one assignment to another is not a felicitous, complete utterance. We will think of assignments as representing the contribution of the utterance situation. If you utter (6), it has a representation such as (7). The utterance situation fixes a certain partial function from indices to individuals. In the case of (7), the variable assignment must include 1 and 2 in its domain. (6) She is taller than she. (7) She 1 is taller than she 2. 9

9.1.2 Utterance contexts and variable assignments (cont.) Let c stand for utterance situation or utterance context, and let g c stand for the variable assignment determined by c. We then formulate the following conditions for LFs with free pronouns: (8) Appropriateness Condition A context c is appropriate for an LF φ only if c determines a variable assignment g c whose domain includes every index which has a free occurrence in φ. (9) Truth and Falsity Conditions for Utterances if φ is uttered in c and c is appropriate for φ, then the utterance of φ in c is true if [[φ]] g c = 1 and false if [[φ]] g c = 0. 10

9.1.2 Utterance contexts and variable assignments (cont.) If (6) with LF (7) is uttered in a situation c 1, which furnishes the assignment g c1, then c 1 is appropriate for (7), and thus this is a true utterance if Kim is taller than Sally, and false if she isn t. g c1 = [ 1 Kim 2 Sandy ] What about gender, number and person features of referential pronouns? if Kim or Sandy is male, then the context c 1 is not appropriate. In section 5.5 we proposed a presuppositional account of gender features for bound pronouns. We can adopt that here. 11

9.1.2 Utterance contexts and variable assignments (cont.) Suppose that features are nodes of their own, adjoined to the DP. The lowest DP node is interpreted by the Pronouns and Traces rule and the higher nodes by FA. Each feature has a suitable lexical entry like(10). DP (third.person) DP (feminine) DP (singular) DP she 1 12

9.1.2 Utterance contexts and variable assignments (cont.) (10) [[feminine]] = λx : x is female. x So a feature denotes a partial identity function. If the feature gets a denotation at all, it will be the one of the lower DP. But if the lower DP s denotation fails to have the appropriate property, the one above gets no value. If c 2 maps index 1 to a man, the DP will fail to be in the domain of [[ ]] g c 2 due to (10). Likewise the whole sentence will fail to be in the domain of [[ ]] g c 2, and (7) would be neither true nor false. The result is a presupposition failure. If the discourse participants mistakenly believe a male referent to be female, or if they are willing to pretend that they do, then an occurrence of she can refer to a man, without any violation of principles of grammar. An analogous account can be given for person and number features. 13

9.2 Co-reference or binding? Anaphoric pronouns with quantifier antecedents are the paradigm cases of bound-variable pronouns, but they are by no means the only instances of bound-variable pronouns that we find in natural languages. It is easy to see that our theory predicts them to have a much wider distribution; and we will argue that this prediction is welcome and supported by empirical evidence. When the antecedent of a pronoun is in a separate sentence or deeply embedded in an island, we have to interpret the pronoun as co-referring with its antecedent. But this leaves us with many cases where anaphora to a referring antecedent can be analyzed as variable binding. Consider (1): (1) John hates his father. 14

9.2 Co-reference or binding? (cont.) Nothing prevents us from generating the following LF for (1). (2) is true iff John is a member of the set {x : x hates x s father}. (2) S DP John 1 S t 1 VP V DP hates the NP DP he 1 N father 15

9.2 Co-reference or binding? (cont.) It is just as easy to generate LFs in which the pronoun is free, either by not QR ing John at all, as in (3); or by giving its trace an index different from the pronoun s, as in (4). (3) S DP VP John V DP hates the NP DP he 1 N father 16

9.2 Co-reference or binding? (cont.) (4) S DP John 2 S t 2 VP V DP hates the NP DP he 1 N father 17

9.2 Co-reference or binding? (cont.) In (3) and (4), he 1 is free. By the Appropriateness Condition, these LFs thus require an utterance context which assigns a referent to index 1. Among the candidates are contexts like c 1 such that g c1 = [1 Fred], or c 2 such that g c2 = [1 Bill], or c 3 such that g c3 = [1 John]. If it is c 3 that prevails, then the utterance will be true if John hates John s father. We have shown that LF (3) or (4) uttered in context c 3 has precisely the same truth and falsity conditions as LF (2) (uttered in any context). 18

9.2 Co-reference or binding? (cont.) Our current theory thus predicts a lot of invisible ambiguity. We hypothesize that both analyses are indeed grammatical, but it seems to be impossible in principle to obtain empirical evidence for the hypothesis that we need both such derivations. However a number of authors (including Partee, Keenan, Lasnik, Sag, Williams, and Reinhart) have argued that there is truth-conditional evidence for this invisible ambiguity after all. But we must look to elliptical sentences to see this. 19

9.3 Pronouns in the theory of ellipsis 20

9.3.1 Background: the LF Identity Condition on ellipsis VP ellipsis: (1) He smokes. He shouldn t. (2) Laura took a nap, and Lena did too. Stripping or bare argument ellipsis : (3) Some people smoke, but not many. (4) Laura left Texas, and Lena as well. (5) Laura drank the milk last night, or perhaps the juice. In VP ellipsis, a VP is deleted on the way from SS to PF. In bare argument ellipsis, an S is deleted, and the remnant has been topicalized, adjoined to S before deletion. 21

9.3.1 Background: the LF Identity Condition on ellipsis (cont.) Since these sentences have the interpretation of complete sentences, they are intact at LF. The material that is deleted must be identical to material that is present overtly in the antecedent discourse. The relevant identity condition applies at the level of LF. Note that the deleted material must match the antecedent in scope: (7) Laura showed a drawing to every teacher, but Lena didn t. (8) LF Identity Condition on Ellipsis A constituent may be deleted at PF only if it is a copy of another constituent at LF. 22

Some sample derivations follow. The material to be deleted is shown in blue. (9) SS: S S Laura I PAST VP leave Texas but S Lena I didn t VP leave Texas 23

(10) SS for (5): S S Laura drank the milk or perhaps the juice S 1 S Laura drank t1 24

(11) LF for (5): S S the milk 1 S Laura drank t 1 or perhaps the juice S 1 S Laura drank t1 25

9.3.2 Referential pronouns and ellipsis (13) (On Roman s birthday), Philipp went to his office. Marcel didn t. If we understand the pronoun in the first sentence as referring to Roman, we also must understand the deleted pronoun as referring to Roman, no matter how salient another referent might be. (15) S S Philipp I Marcel I I VP I VP PAST go to his 1 office didn t go to his 1 office 26

9.3.2 Referential pronouns and ellipsis (cont.) (16) is ungrammatical, and the LF Identity condition excludes it. (16)* S S Philipp I Marcel I I VP I VP PAST go to his 1 office didn t go to his 2 office 27

9.3.2 Referential pronouns and ellipsis (cont.) Unfortunately, there is another LF, shown in (17), that is not excluded and which also expresses one of the unavailable readings. Here the first tree says that Philipp went to Roman s office, but the second tree says that Marcel went to Marcel s office. We need to close this loophole. The problem seems to be that the first pronoun is free, whereas the second variable is bound. Maybe we should rewrite the LF Identity Condition to be sensitive to this difference. Or we can add a general prohibition against LFs in which a given index has both bound and free occurrences. (18) No LF representation (for a sentence or multisentential text) can contain both bound occurrences and free occurrences of the same index. 28

(17) S Philipp I I VP S PAST go to his 1 office Marcel 1 S t 1 I I didn t go to VP his 1 office 29

9.3.2 Referential pronouns and ellipsis (cont.) We now predict that whenever a pronoun in the antecedent phrase refers to an individual x, then the pronoun s counterpart in the deleted phrase must refer to x as well. Referential pronouns keep their reference under ellipsis. 30

9.3.3 The sloppy identity puzzle and its solution (13) (On Roman s birthday,) Philipp went to his office. Marcel didn t. There is another interpretation of (13), the sloppy identity reading, whereby Philipp went to his own office (Philipp s), and Marcel went to his own office (Marcel s) Doesn t this constitute a blatant counterexample to the law we have just seen? This puzzle persists only as long as we take it for granted that the overt pronoun has to be referential. We can interpret this pronoun as a bound-variable pronoun. Here is an LF, where both pronouns are construed as bound-variable pronouns. The subjects in both cases were QR d and the same indices were chosen. 31

(19) S Philipp 1 S t 1 I I VP S PAST go to his 1 office Marcel 1 S t 1 I I didn t go to VP his 1 office 32

9.3.3 The sloppy identity puzzle and its solution (cont.) (19) meets the LF Identity Condition on ellipsis, since the two VPs are identical. And it is not in violation of sipulation (18), since all occurrences of index 1 are bound in the overall representation. We have solved the sloppy identity puzzle and vindicated our assumptions about ellipsis. in doing so, we have found an indirect, yet compelling, argument for the coexistence of bound-variable readings and referential readings in anaphoric pronouns with referring antecedents. We d want to explore further and make sure that our theory predicts the distribution of strict and sloppy readings in all sorts of examples. See text for some discussion. 33