On the Nature of Measurement in Quantum Mechanics. Abstract. Text



Similar documents
Does Quantum Mechanics Make Sense? Size

Superposition & the paradoxes of quantum mechanics

"in recognition of the services he rendered to the advancement of Physics by his discovery of energy quanta". h is the Planck constant he called it

Quantum Phenomena and the Theory of Quantum Mechanics

Theory of electrons and positrons

DO PHYSICS ONLINE FROM QUANTA TO QUARKS QUANTUM (WAVE) MECHANICS

Physics 9e/Cutnell. correlated to the. College Board AP Physics 1 Course Objectives

How do the Students Describe the Quantum Mechanics and Classical Mechanics?

DO WE REALLY UNDERSTAND QUANTUM MECHANICS?

Fernanda Ostermann Institute of Physics, Department of Physics, Federal University of Rio Grande do Sul, Brazil.

TIME, SYMMETRY OF. Although everyday experience leads us to believe that time "flows" in one direction, the

Unamended Quantum Mechanics Rigorously Implies Awareness Is Not Based in the Physical Brain

The quantum understanding of pre-university physics students

Atomic Structure Ron Robertson

CHAPTER - 1. Chapter ONE: WAVES CHAPTER - 2. Chapter TWO: RAY OPTICS AND OPTICAL INSTRUMENTS. CHAPTER - 3 Chapter THREE: WAVE OPTICS PERIODS PERIODS

HUNTER COLLEGE READING/WRITING CENTER THE WRITING PROCESS Invention: Annotating a Text

1 Now, Why do we want to learn Quantum Mechanics

PHY1020 BASIC CONCEPTS IN PHYSICS I

There is a physics joke about the stages of learning quantum mechanics:

PHYS 1624 University Physics I. PHYS 2644 University Physics II

Richard Feynman, Curious Character

Chapter 18: The Structure of the Atom

3-9 EPR and Bell s theorem. EPR Bohm s version. S x S y S z V H 45

Solid-State Physics: The Theory of Semiconductors (Ch ) SteveSekula, 30 March 2010 (created 29 March 2010)

Quantum control of individual electron and nuclear spins in diamond lattice

Vector or Pseudovector?

13- What is the maximum number of electrons that can occupy the subshell 3d? a) 1 b) 3 c) 5 d) 2

MASTER OF SCIENCE IN PHYSICS MASTER OF SCIENCES IN PHYSICS (MS PHYS) (LIST OF COURSES BY SEMESTER, THESIS OPTION)

THE STATISTICAL TREATMENT OF EXPERIMENTAL DATA 1

History of the Atom & Atomic Theory

Name Date Class ELECTRONS IN ATOMS. Standard Curriculum Core content Extension topics

Till now, almost all attention has been focussed on discussing the state of a quantum system.

A Modest View of Bell s Theorem. Steve Boughn, Princeton University and Haverford College

The structure of accounting systems: how to store accounts Lincoln Stoller, Ph.D.

Quantum Systems for Information Technology

Prerequisite: High School Chemistry.

Application of Nuclear Magnetic Resonance in Petroleum Exploration

Time dependence in quantum mechanics Notes on Quantum Mechanics

F en = mω 0 2 x. We should regard this as a model of the response of an atom, rather than a classical model of the atom itself.

Time and Causation in Gödel s Universe.

Atomic structure. Resources and methods for learning about these subjects (list a few here, in preparation for your research):

It has been contended that it would be possible for a socialist economy to solve

Generally Covariant Quantum Mechanics

What does Quantum Mechanics tell us about the universe?

ELECTRON SPIN RESONANCE Last Revised: July 2007

Nanoelectronics. Chapter 2 Classical Particles, Classical Waves, and Quantum Particles. Q.Li@Physics.WHU@2015.3

It has long been a goal to achieve higher spatial resolution in optical imaging and

Introduction to Quantum Computing

Physics 10. Lecture 29A. "There are two ways of spreading light: to be the candle or the mirror that reflects it." --Edith Wharton

The Hydrogen Atom Is a Magnet.

- particle with kinetic energy E strikes a barrier with height U 0 > E and width L. - classically the particle cannot overcome the barrier

Origin of quantum-mechanical complementarity probed by a `which-way' experiment in an atom interferometer

PUMPED Nd:YAG LASER. Last Revision: August 21, 2007

UNIT I: INTRFERENCE & DIFFRACTION Div. B Div. D Div. F INTRFERENCE

Three Pictures of Quantum Mechanics. Thomas R. Shafer April 17, 2009

Lecture 6 Scanning Tunneling Microscopy (STM) General components of STM; Tunneling current; Feedback system; Tip --- the probe.

Appendix A: Science Practices for AP Physics 1 and 2

Solar Energy Production

Solutions to Problems in Goldstein, Classical Mechanics, Second Edition. Chapter 7

Atomic Structure: Chapter Problems

AP Physics B Ch. 23 and Ch. 24 Geometric Optics and Wave Nature of Light

School of Physics and Astronomy FACULTY OF MATHEMATICS AND PHYSICAL SCIENCES. MSc in Quantum Technologies

Project Management Simple Answers to Simple Questions

Introduction to acoustic imaging

Figure 1. A typical Laboratory Thermometer graduated in C.

Intro to Data Analysis, Economic Statistics and Econometrics

PHYS 39a Lab 3: Microscope Optics

A Guide to Acousto-Optic Modulators

Lecture PowerPoints. Chapter 7 Physics: Principles with Applications, 6 th edition Giancoli

Physical Principle of Formation and Essence of Radio Waves

Hydrogen Bonds The electrostatic nature of hydrogen bonds

NMR - Basic principles

Nanoscience Course Descriptions

Bergen Community College School of Mathematics, Science and Technology Department of Physical Sciences. Course Syllabus PHY 291 Physics III

The Phenomenon of Photoelectric Emission:

Heating & Cooling in Molecular Clouds

Adequate Theory of Oscillator: A Prelude to Verification of Classical Mechanics Part 2

Structure Factors

Light as a Wave. The Nature of Light. EM Radiation Spectrum. EM Radiation Spectrum. Electromagnetic Radiation

limit.) Every group so defined would be still further sub-divided if we Thus a heterogeneous substance such as a mixture of ice and water naturally

Level 3 Achievement Scale

PHYSICS TEST PRACTICE BOOK. Graduate Record Examinations. This practice book contains. Become familiar with. Visit GRE Online at

Basic Electrical Technology Dr. L. Umanand Department of Electrical Engineering Indian Institute of Science, Bangalore. Lecture phase System 4

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 22 Apr 2004

Lecture: 33. Solidification of Weld Metal

The dream for a better life has made man look for gold coins from the World War II (1940) which were lost in various parts of Greece.

Indiana's Academic Standards 2010 ICP Indiana's Academic Standards 2016 ICP. map) that describe the relationship acceleration, velocity and distance.

SIZE. Energy. Non-Mechanical Energy. Mechanical Energy. Part II. Examples of Non-Mechanical Energy. Examples of Mechanical Energy.

The Existence of a Neutron

EDUCATION CURRENT TITLE PROFESSIONAL EXPERIENCE: Ph.D, Theoretical Solid State Physics Louisiana State University, Baton Rouge, LA, 1970

QUANTUM ENIGMA Summer 2014 Ted McIrvine

- thus, the total number of atoms per second that absorb a photon is

Project Management Methodologies By Jason Charvat, published by Wiley, NJ, 2003 (A book review by R. Max Wideman)

Experiment 5. Lasers and laser mode structure

9 th Grade Physical Science Springfield Local Schools Common Course Syllabi. Course Description

4.1 Studying Atom. Early evidence used to develop models of atoms.

chapter >> Externalities Section 2: Policies Toward Pollution

1. Basics of LASER Physics

The Importance of Independent Testing

DISTANCE DEGREE PROGRAM CURRICULUM NOTE:

Transcription:

of Measurement in Quantum Mechanics DOUGLAS M. SNYDER LOS ANGELES, CALIFORNIA Abstract A number of issues related to measurement show that self-consistency is lacking in quantum mechanics as this theory has been generally understood. Each issue is presented as a point in this paper. Each point can be resolved by incorporating a cognitive component in quantum mechanics. Measurement in quantum mechanics involves the meaning of the physical circumstances of the experiment. This meaning is in part independent of what traditionally are considered purely physical considerations. Text The following five points concern issues in quantum mechanics that indicate that experimenter variables play a role in this theory. Each point is followed by a brief discussion. POINT ONE 1. An experimenter oftentimes may consider a physical interaction either as a measurement involving a macroscopic measuring instrument interacting with an observable or in terms of a set of microscopic systems, including the observable, functioning lawfully in accordance with the Schršdinger equation. The question arises: On the microscopic level, does the abrupt change in the wave function associated with the observable that often occurs in a measurement occur when the observable and the macroscopic apparatus are considered as a set of microscopic physical systems interacting with each other? According to Bohr, the answer apparently is, ÒNo.Ó Bohr emphasized that it was the macroscopic nature of the measuring apparatus that was responsible for a measurement. According to Bohr (1935), there was some loss of control due to the macroscopic character of the physical apparatus used to make a measurement. This lack of control resulted in the limitation on knowledge described by the uncertainty principle. Thus if the macroscopic system is considered in terms of its microscopic components, a measurement should not - 1 -

occur. There should not be an abrupt change in the wave function associated with the observable. wrote: Here is how Bohr considered measurement in quantum mechanics. He It is imperative to realize that in every account of physical experience one must describe both experimental conditions and observations by the same means of communication as one used in classical physics. In the analysis of single atomic particles [in quantum mechanics], this is made possible by irreversible amplification effects [emphasis added]ðsuch as a spot on a photographic plate left by the impact of an electron, or an electric discharge created in a counter deviceðand the observations concern only where and when the particle is registered on the plate or its energy on arrival at the counter. (Bohr, 1955/1958b, p. 88) Bohr (1955/1958a) essentially defined the phenomenon in quantum mechanics as the entire experimental context, specifically the experiment that is conducted on an observable. Bohr maintained that the experiment conducted was described in terms of the physical apparatus used and the observable measured and that the physical world in quantum mechanics could only be understood in terms of the phenomenon. On the lines of objective description, it is indeed more appropriate to use the word phenomenon to refer only to observations obtained under circumstances whose description includes an account of the whole experimental arrangement. In such terminology, the observational problem in quantum physics is deprived of any special intricacy and we are, moreover, directly reminded that every atomic phenomenon is closed in the sense that its observation is based on registrations obtained by means of suitable amplification devices with irreversible functioning such as, for example, permanent marks on a photographic plate, caused by the penetration of electrons into the emulsion. (Bohr, 1955/1958a, p. 73) 1 1 Citing Bohr, Wheeler (1981/1983) wrote: ÒA phenomenon is not yet a phenomenon until it has been brought to a close by an irreversible act of amplification such as the blackening of a grain of silver bromide emulsion or the triggering of a photodetector...we are dealing with an - 2 -

An experiment discussed by Feynman, Leighton, and Sands (1965) that will be discussed shortly indicates that the destruction of interference often associated with a measurement in quantum mechanics does not depend on a macroscopic measuring instrument. POINTS TWO AND THREE 2. A measurement can occur on a microscopic level without depending on a macroscopic measuring instrument. 3. The presence or absence of interference may depend on a comparison of different observables in an experiment, even if the observables cannot actually be observed by the experimenter. The Importance of Comparison In demonstrating the point that measurement does not rely on a macroscopic physical apparatus acting as a measuring instrument interacting with the observable measured, Feynman et al. considered the destruction of interference on the atomic level in the case of neutron scattering by a crystal. This destruction of interference depends on a change in the nucleus in the crystal that interacts with the impacting neutron allowing the experimenter to Òin principle, find out which nucleus had done the scattering, since it would be the only one with spin turned overó (Feynman et al., 1965, chap. 3, p. 8). Initially, all the nuclei in the crystal have their spin components along a specific spatial axis set in one direction. It is a change in the spin component along a spatial axis for a nucleus in the crystal impacted by a neutron that distinguishes this nucleus from other nuclei for which the spin component along this same axis has not changed and which thus all remain in the original direction. Note that the destruction in interference depends on the nuclei that are not impacted by the neutron all having spin components that are opposite in orientation to the nucleus that is impacted by the incoming neutron. It is not the physical interaction between a nucleus in the crystal and the neutron that alone is responsible for the destruction of interference. If, in the interaction, the spin component for the nucleus does not flip and the spin component for the neutron therefore does not flip, interference is not destroyed. In the experiment, destruction of the interference depends on a microscopic event, a spin component flip on the part of the neutron that distinguishes the path of the event that makes itself known by an irreversible act of amplification, by an indelible record, an act of registration.ó (pp. 184-185, 196) - 3 -

impacting neutron from alternative paths. The different spin components cannot, of course, be observed by the experimenter. It is the information conveyed to the observer that determines whether or not interference is destroyed. The physical interaction alone does not account for the different physical results. Feynman et al. (1965) had a different view: Well, if we can tell which atom [nucleus] did the scattering, what have the other atoms [nuclei] to do with it? Nothing of course. The scattering is exactly the same as that from a single atom. (chap. 3, p. 8) When Feynman et al. wrote: ÒNothing of course,ó their own description of the experiment indicates their statement is incorrect. Perhaps, they could argue that on a physical level alone the other nuclei are not involved in the scattering, or that if considered in isolation the impacted nucleus would not show interference. Their own description of the destruction of interference, though, in the crystal depends on the difference between the spin component orientations of the impacted nucleus and the other nuclei. In other words, the experimental circumstance involving numerous nuclei is not the same as one involving only one nucleus. POINT FOUR 4. A measurement needs to make which-way information only in principle available to destroy interference. In different works on quantum theory, Feynman distinguished those circumstances in which wave amplitudes associated with an observable are first added and the absolute value of the sum is squared to derive the probability of an event, as opposed to taking the absolute square of each of the wave amplitudes and taking their sum to determine the probability of the same event. Feynman et al. (1965) wrote concerning quantum mechanics: [1] The probability of an event in an ideal experiment is given by the square of the absolute value of a complex number f which is called the probability amplitude... [2] When an event can occur in several alternative ways, the probability amplitude for the event is the sum of the probability amplitudes for each way considered separately... - 4 -

[3] If an experiment is performed which is capable of determining whether one or another alternative is actually taken, the probability of the event is the sum of the probabilities for each alternative. (chap. 3, p. 10) In their experiment discussed above, Feynman et al. (1965) wrote that the distinction between the different paths need not actually be known to an observer. 2 All that is necessary is that their distinction is in principle possible in the experimental circumstances. If you could, in principle, distinguish the alternative final states [of the observables] (even though you do not bother to do so), the total, final probability is obtained by calculating the probability for each state (not the amplitude) and then adding them together. If you cannot distinguish the final states even in principle, then the probability amplitudes must be summed before taking the absolute square to find the actual probability. (Feynman et al., 1965, chap. 3, p. 9) Point four might appear to indicate that the observer is not central to measurement in quantum mechanics. It is important to note that distinguishing final paths constitutes a measurement. Remember, oftentimes, the physical interaction occasioning a measurement can be a macroscopic apparatus interacting with a microscopic observable or it can be an interaction among microscopic observables alone (Point one). Because of these different views one can take of an interaction, the in principle possibility of distinguishing paths supports a cognitive component to measurement in quantum mechanics. In this context, it is important to note negative observation. In a negative observation, a measurement does not involve a physical interaction at all (Bergquist, Hulet, Itano, & Wineland, 1986; Cook, 1990; Epstein, 1945; Nagourney, Sandberg, & Dehmelt, 1986; Renninger, 1960; Sauter, Neuhauser, Blatt, & Toschek, 1986; Snyder, 1996, 1997). A negative observation occurs where an observation is made by deducing that a particular physical event must have occurred because another physical event did not occur 2 In QED: The Strange Theory of Light and Matter, Feynman (1985) maintained the same principles hold in quantum electrodynamics. In sum, where one can distinguish between the possible routes, or developmental sequence, for an observable, interference between the component wave amplitudes characterizing the existent is destroyed. - 5 -

with subsequent consequences for the functioning of the physical world stemming from the change in knowledge. POINT FIVE 5. Macroscopic devices may either : 1) interact with an observable acting as a measuring instrument where coherence is destroyed and there is an abrupt change in the wave function associated with the observable, or 2) act as a device in the service of separating a wave function into coherent components or recombining coherent component wave functions so that interference is expressed. There is nothing in the nature of a macroscopic device itself that necessarily signals a measurement. An example is a double-hole diaphragm that is rigidly attached to a support through which electrons pass on their way to a screen that they impact and that records their position (Bohr, 1949/1969). Coherent component wave functions are developed as a result of the electron passing through the diaphragm, resulting in interference which is detectable when the electrons impact the screen. A macroscopic apparatus in this case does not result in a measurement when it interacts with a microscopic observable. Something else is needed to distinguish whether a measurement is made. If, instead of being fixed, the diaphragm was movable due to momentum transfer between the electron and the diaphragm, a position measurement would occur. Which hole an electron went through on its way to the screen could be determined by how the diaphragm moved as the electron passed through (Bohr, 1949/1969). What is it about allowing the diaphragm to move that changes its function so dramatically? The answer lies in the destruction of interference, and interference in quantum mechanics depends on coherent waves that are mathematically complex and do not have a physical existence. One can in fact piece together coherent component wave functions associated with an observable using a macroscopic physical apparatus. For example, one may use a one-half silvered mirror to recombine coherent component wave functions associated with a photon that had originally been separated earlier by another one-half silvered mirror. The macroscopic apparatus used to combine the component wave functions does not destroy interference. It actually implements interference using the coherent wave functions. - 6 -

CONCLUSION Following is a summary of the points made in this paper. 1. In many experimental circumstances, a macroscopic apparatus appears to be responsible for the occurrence of measurements in quantum mechanics. 2. Feynman et al.õs experiment works as they discussed, and their position that a macroscopic physical apparatus is not always necessary for a measurement is sound. 3. The occurrence of a measurement may depend on a comparison of observables, even if these observables cannot be observed but can only be thought about. 4. A physical interaction that is considered a measurement, accompanied by an abrupt change of the wave function associated with the observable measured, does not necessarily have to be considered as such. The collapse of the wave function need not occur in another view of the same interaction that focuses on the interacting systems microscopically. 5. A measurement can be said to occur when in principle it is possible to distinguish possible measurement outcomes, even if these outcomes are not actually measured. 6. Negative observations are possible in quantum mechanics. 7. A macroscopic physical apparatus is not necessary for a measurement, and indeed it can be used to develop interference. Notice the use of the terms view, comparison, and in principle. The inconsistencies noted in this paper indicate that quantum mechanics is not concerned exclusively with the physical. A measurement affecting an observable can be made without a physical interaction. Quantum mechanics, though, always does depend on the mathematically complex waves associated with observables, and interference itself combines these complex waves. Anything that can be known about an observable is derived from these waves. Ascribing a cognitive component to quantum mechanics accounts for the terms indicating cognition that are noted above as well as the result stemming - 7 -

from BohrÕs concept of measurement that depending on oneõs view there may or not be an abrupt change of the wave function associated with an observable when a physical interaction occurs. One can summarize the points in this paper by characterizing measurement in quantum mechanics as involving the meaning of the physical circumstances of the experiment. This meaning is in part independent of what traditionally are considered purely physical considerations. REFERENCES Bergquist, J. C., Hulet, R. G., Itano, W. M., and Wineland, D. J. (1986). Observation of quantum jumps in a single atom. Physical Review Letters, 57, 1699-1702. Bohr, N. (1935). Can quantum-mechanical description of nature be considered complete? Physical Review, 49, 1804-1807. Bohr, N. (1969). Discussion with Einstein on epistemological problems in atomic physics. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), Albert Einstein: Philosopherscientist (Vol. 1) (pp. 199-241). La Salle, Illinois: Open Court. (Original work published 1949) Bohr, N. (1958a) Atoms and human knowledge. In N. Bohr, Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge (pp. 67-82). New York: John Wiley & Sons. (Original work published 1955) Bohr, N. (1958b) Unity of knowledge. In N. Bohr, Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge (pp. 83-93). New York: John Wiley & Sons. (Original work published 1955) Cook, R. J. (1990). Quantum jumps. In E. Wolf (Ed.), Progress in Optics (Vol. 28) (pp. 361-416). Amsterdam: North-Holland. Epstein, P. (1945). The reality problem in quantum mechanics. American Journal of Physics, 13, 127-136. Feynman, R. P., Leighton, R. B., &, and Sands, M. (1965). The Feynman Lectures on Physics: Quantum Mechanics (Vol. 3). Reading, Massachusetts: Addison-Wesley. Feynman, R. P. (1985). QED: The Strange Theory of Light and Matter. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. Nagourney, W., Sandberg, J., and Dehmelt, H. (1986). Shelved optical electron amplifier: observation of quantum jumps. Physical Review Letters, 56, 2797-2799. - 8 -

Renninger, M. (1960). Messungen ohne Stšrung des Me objekts [Observations without disturbing the object]. Zeitschrift fÿr Physik, 158, 417-421. Sauter, T., Neuhauser, W., Blatt, R. and Toschek, P. E. (1986). Observation of quantum jumps. Physical Review Letters, 57, 1696-1698. Snyder, D. M. (1996). On the Nature of the Change in the Wave Function in a Measurement in Quantum Mechanics. Los Alamos National Laboratory E- Print Physics Archive (WWW address: http://xxx.lanl.gov/abs/quantph/9601006). Snyder, D. M. (1997). Negative Observations in Quantum Mechanics. APS E- print Server (WWW address: http://publish.aps.org/eprint/gateway/ eplist/aps1997jun24_006) and Cogprints Electronic Archive (WWW address: http://cogprints.soton.ac.uk/abs/psyc/199806017). Wheeler, J. A. (1983). Law without law. In J. A. Wheeler & W. H. Zurek (Eds.) Quantum Theory and Measurement (pp. 182-213). Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. (Original work published 1981) - 9 -