3. Evaluating Arguments: When Is an Argument a Good One?

Similar documents
Philosophical argument

A Few Basics of Probability

1/9. Locke 1: Critique of Innate Ideas

8. Inductive Arguments

2. Argument Structure & Standardization

DEDUCTIVE & INDUCTIVE REASONING

PHI 201, Introductory Logic p. 1/16

Inductive Reasoning Page 1 of 7. Inductive Reasoning

You will by now not be surprised that a version of the teleological argument can be found in the writings of Thomas Aquinas.

Cosmological Arguments for the Existence of God S. Clarke

CHAPTER 3. Methods of Proofs. 1. Logical Arguments and Formal Proofs

Read this syllabus very carefully. If there are any reasons why you cannot comply with what I am requiring, then talk with me about this at once.

Building a Better Argument

Likewise, we have contradictions: formulas that can only be false, e.g. (p p).

Cultural Relativism. 1. What is Cultural Relativism? 2. Is Cultural Relativism true? 3. What can we learn from Cultural Relativism?

3. Mathematical Induction

Science and Scientific Reasoning. Critical Thinking

Invalidity in Predicate Logic

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 2

Scientific Reasoning: A Solution to the Problem of Induction

Writing Thesis Defense Papers

Argument Mapping 2: Claims and Reasons

Five High Order Thinking Skills

Draft Copy: Do Not Cite Without Author s Permission

DEVELOPING HYPOTHESIS AND

Plato gives another argument for this claiming, relating to the nature of knowledge, which we will return to in the next section.

3. Logical Reasoning in Mathematics

Kant s deontological ethics

Divine command theory

MILL. The principle of utility determines the rightness of acts (or rules of action?) by their effect on the total happiness.

Manufacturers versus Component Part and Raw Material Suppliers: How to Prevent Liability By Kenneth Ross *

Introduction to Hypothesis Testing

Quine on truth by convention

What Is Circular Reasoning?

Deductive reasoning is the application of a general statement to a specific instance.

P1. All of the students will understand validity P2. You are one of the students C. You will understand validity

Handout #1: Mathematical Reasoning

Harvard College Program in General Education Faculty of Arts and Sciences Harvard University. A Guide to Writing in Ethical Reasoning 15

One natural response would be to cite evidence of past mornings, and give something like the following argument:

A Short Course in Logic Zeno s Paradox

Introduction to Hypothesis Testing OPRE 6301

Philosophy 104. Chapter 8.1 Notes

Mathematical Induction

Hypothesis testing. c 2014, Jeffrey S. Simonoff 1

Experimental Analysis

Module Five Critical Thinking

STEPS IN SCIENTIFIC RESEARCH:

Boonin on the Future-Like-Ours Argument against Abortion. Pedro Galvão Centro de Filosofia da Universidade de Lisboa

Publishing papers in international journals

The College Standard

A. What is Virtue Ethics?

Locke s psychological theory of personal identity

Program Level Learning Outcomes for the Department of Philosophy Page 1

Last time we had arrived at the following provisional interpretation of Aquinas second way:

Arguments and Dialogues

Logic and Reasoning Practice Final Exam Spring Section Number

Honours programme in Philosophy

How does the problem of relativity relate to Thomas Kuhn s concept of paradigm?

Components of a Reading Workshop Mini-Lesson

Intending, Intention, Intent, Intentional Action, and Acting Intentionally: Comments on Knobe and Burra

CONCEPTUAL CONTINGENCY AND ABSTRACT EXISTENCE

Full details of the course syllabus, support and examination arrangements are provided below.

How To Decide A Case In The Uk

Slippery Slopes and Vagueness


Guide to Powers of Attorney. For more information or to speak to one of our trained advisers please telephone our team on

EVALUATION OF IMPORTANCE FOR RESEARCH IN EDUCATION

Structuring and Analyzing Arguments: The Classical, Rogerian, and Toulmin Models. Junior AP English

1.2 Forms and Validity

A Short Course in Logic Example 8

Practical Research. Paul D. Leedy Jeanne Ellis Ormrod. Planning and Design. Tenth Edition

Basic Proof Techniques

Practical Jealousy Management

Why are thesis proposals necessary? The Purpose of having thesis proposals is threefold. First, it is to ensure that you are prepared to undertake the

CHAPTER 2. Logic. 1. Logic Definitions. Notation: Variables are used to represent propositions. The most common variables used are p, q, and r.

Review. Bayesianism and Reliability. Today s Class

Chapter 5: Fallacies. 23 February 2015

To Kill a Mockingbird Journal Prompts

Background Biology and Biochemistry Notes A

Modern Science vs. Ancient Philosophy. Daniel Gilbert s theory of happiness as presented in his book, Stumbling on Happiness,

Lecture 9 Maher on Inductive Probability

Why I Wrote this Packet

CONSTRUCTING A LOGICAL ARGUMENT

Independent samples t-test. Dr. Tom Pierce Radford University

Lecture 2. What is the Normative Role of Logic?

Neil Murray University of South Australia April 2011

Methodology in Social Psychology. Logics of inquiry

Goals AND Objectives should be student-centered rather than course-centered Goals AND Objectives should reflect successful student performance

Theories of Personality Psyc , Fall 2014

The Problem of Evil not If God exists, she'd be OOG. If an OOG being exists, there would be no evil. God exists.

Neutrality s Much Needed Place In Dewey s Two-Part Criterion For Democratic Education

FOR MORE, go to Problem Behavior in My Classroom?

Subject area: Ethics. Injustice causes revolt. Discuss.

WRITING PROOFS. Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology

Mathematical Induction

A. Arguments are made up of statements, which can be either true or false. Which of the following are statements?

Goal Setting. Your role as the coach is to develop and maintain an effective coaching plan with the client. You are there to

Descartes Meditations. ? God exists I exist (as a thinking thing)

LESSON TITLE: Taming the Tongue. THEME: God wants us to watch what we say. SCRIPTURE: James 3:1-12 CHILDREN S DEVOTIONS FOR THE WEEK OF:

If you opt to have an appraiser come to view the coach you will have to have the following ready or available:

Transcription:

3. Evaluating Arguments: When Is an Argument a Good One? 1 Two Aspects of Evaluation 1. Evaluation of premises 2. Evaluation or reasoning from premises to conclusion 2 1

Cogency An argument that has both satisfactory premises (i.e., true or plausible premises) and a structure that provides rational support for its conclusion may termed a good, strong, convincing or sound argument. For arguments in natural languages Govier suggests that we use the word cogent as our basic evaluative term 3 ARG Conditions This is Govier s shorthand acronym for the basic elements of a cogent argument: Acceptable premises Relevant premises Adequate Grounds for the conclusion 4 2

Acceptable Premises As a first approximation, we can say that a premise is acceptable if it is reasonable for those to whom the argument is addressed to believe (i.e., to accept) that premise. A bit more precisely: A premise is acceptable if there is some reason to believe that that premise is true and no (known) good reason to believe that it is false. (More about acceptability later, in Ch. 5) 5 Relevance of Premises Premises are relevant to a conclusion if they state evidence or offers reasons that (actually) support the conclusion or can be arranged into a proof from which the conclusion can be derived. (This latter idea of arranging into proof will be considered more extensively in connection with the idea of validity in propositional logic, Ch. 8). 6 3

Adequate Grounds Premises provide adequate grounds for a conclusion when, considered together, the premises provide sufficient reason to accept that conclusion. Notice: Relevance is not the same as sufficiency. One person s personal experience may be relevant to some general claim, yet not be sufficient to support it 7 The Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council is obviously corrupt. Every time I apply for a grant, they give me the run-around about forms and paperwork, and they always seem to find some reason to reject my grant application. The fact that one person has had bad, frustrating experiences with SSHRC is certainly relevant to the claim that the organization is corrupt. But without some additional information about how others are treated, and perhaps some information about how the person offering the argument compares with other applicants, this is clearly not sufficient to establish the conclusion. 8 4

Cogency, Soundness, Validity In formal logic, a sound argument can be defined as an argument in which all the premises are true and which has a structure such that the premises deductively entail the conclusion. Deductive entailment is a very strong logical relation in which it is logically impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. 9 An Example (Govier s) 1. Either interest rates will go down, or they will go up. 2. Interest rates will not go down. Therefore, 3. Interest rates will go up. Notice that the conclusion follows not because of anything you may happen to know about interest rates, but, given that the premises are true, simply by virtue of the form of the argument. 10 5

Another Example 1. If Saskatoon is the capital of Saskatchewan, then Saskatoon is in Saskatchewan 2. Saskatoon is the capital of Saskatchewan Therefore, 3. Saskatoon is in Saskatchewan This argument is deductively valid: The truth of its premises guarantees the truth of its conclusion. But is it sound? 11 Yet another 1. If Saskatoon is in Ontario, then Saskatoon is south of Whitehorse. 2. Saskatoon is south of Whitehorse Therefore, 3. Saskatoon is in Ontario Notice that both premises are true. Their truth does not deductively entail the truth of the conclusion, however, since this is an invalid argument form. 12 6

Cogency vs. Soundness Generally speaking any argument that is sound (all true premises + valid form) is also cogent (satisfies ARG conditions). But not all arguments that are cogent are sound: Premises may be rationally acceptable even if they are not known with certainty to be true. Not all arguments are deductive. Premises may support the conclusion in other ways besides deductive entailment. 13 Cogent Arguments Sound Arguments Arguments that are both Cogent and Sound 14 7

A Small Step Backwards: Relevance & Grounds So far we have been using these words in a rather vague sense. One way of getting at a clearer account of relevance and grounds (R and G conditions), is to consider the various ways in which the premises of an argument can be said to support its conclusion. This involves looking at various different types of arguments/reasoning 15 Four Types of Argument/Reasoning 1. Deductive entailment (deductive reasoning) 2. Inductive support (inductive reasoning) 3. Analogy (analogical reasoning) 4. Conductive support Each of these are ways in which premises may be properly connected to conclusions. What counts are relevance and adequacy of grounds is somewhat different for each type, however 16 8

Deductive Entailment In a deductive inference, the conclusion follows just by virtue of the truth of the premises, given a valid argument form. Famous example: All men are mortal. Socrates is a man. Therefore, Socrates is mortal 17 In the case of a deductive argument that is valid (i.e., of a known-to-be valid form), the R condition is always satisfied and, if the premises of that argument are all true, the G condition is also automatically satisfied. Evaluating such an argument (determining whether or not it is cogent), then, involves determining whether or not the A condition is satisfied i.e., whether its premises are true. 18 9

Govier s example: 1. A mathematical proof is an intellectual exercise. 2. Some computers can do mathematical proofs. Therefore, 3. Some computers can do an intellectual exercise. 19 Notice that deductive entailment is always an instance of linked support: 1 + 2 3 20 10

Inductive Support Inductive reasoning is a basic technique in science reasoning from particular cases to general conclusions. Generalized example: t1 sample of X glowed orange when Y present t2 sample of X glowed orange when Y present t3 sample of X glowed orange when Y present tn So, probably, X glows orange when Y is present 21 Obviously, in inductive reasoning, the number of observations contributes to the adequacy of the probable conclusion. (This is what statisticians and research scientists are ultimately referring to when they speak of sample size.) 22 11

Govier s Example 1. All the students I have met who graduated from school X got good grades in mathematics. So, probably, 2. All students who have graduated from school X got good grades in mathematics. The inference here is a generalization from a sample to a larger group. 23 Some Incidentals About Induction I Inductive inference assumes that unobserved cases will resemble observed ones. That is, it assumes that there are regularities in the world and our experience of it. (Some philosophers would note as well: inductive inference depends on these regularities, but these regularities are not themselves observable.) 24 12

Some Incidentals About Induction II When inductive reasoning is in question, it is common to speak of evidence rather than reasons. Also, as we have noted, an inductive argument can supply only probable (as opposed to certain) support for its conclusion (i.e., its inductive generalization) 25 For a valid deductive argument, it is logically impossible that the conclusion does not follow from the premises if those premises are true. But it is not logically impossible that, say, the next student to graduate from school X will turn out not to be good at mathematics. Inductive inference assumes that there are regularities in the world, but sometimes the world is irregular or surprising. 26 13

Inference to the Best Explanation 1. These eighty students who graduated from school X all have good marks in mathematics 2. The best and most natural explanation for that is that mathematics is well taught at school X Therefore, probably, 3. Mathematics is well taught at school x. Premise 2 offers an hypothesis that purports to explain the empirical observation in premise 1. 27 In assessing arguments that make use of hypotheses, we need to determine whether the hypothesis is actually acceptable (A condition), that is, whether it really is the best available explanation. If you create arguments that use inference to the best explanation, ideally you should be prepared to offer a sub-argument supporting the hypothesis. 28 14

Analogy Another basic form of reasoning commonly used in science (and in law, public administration, and ethics). E.g., in assessing the safety of some drug Y for humans, researchers may perform studies on rats, on the assumption that rat physiology is analogous to (i.e., relevantly similar to) human physiology. 29 Conductive Support Not really a separate type of inference, I d say, but Govier believes it is useful to assign it special name and special significance. In conductive arguments, the support offered by the premises is always convergent 30 15

Convergent Support 1 2 3 4 31 An Example As Govier notes, legal reasoning is often conductive (i.e., strictly convergent) in nature: The accused 1. Has no alibi 2. Has a motive 3. Had a an opportunity to commit the crime 4. Was seen at the scene of the crime Any one of these factors might be successfully disputed by a defense attorney, yet a Crown prosecutor need not withdraw charges unless and until all of them have been successfully disputed. Each, after all, independently supports a guilty verdict. 32 16

Counterarguments In evaluating conductive arguments is often useful to think up counterarguments factors or reasons that would count against the conclusion. E.g.: The accused was seen at the scene of the crime, but he was also seen somewhere else at the same time; The accused has a motive, but so do many other people 33 Using ARG Conditions to Evaluate Arguments If we know what conditions an argument needs to satisfy in order to be a cogent argument, then we can evaluate the cogency of any argument by inspecting it to see if it satisfies those conditions 34 17

Govier Suggests 1. Start with the (A) condition. Are the premises acceptable? If they are, why? If not, why not? 2. Then move on to the (R) condition. Are the premises relevant to the conclusion? Do the premises deductively entail the conclusion? Do they provide inductive support for it? Etc. If (R) is to be satisfied, it must be possible to interpret the premises such that they offer some support for the conclusion. Otherwise, they are irrelevant. 35 3. If (A) and (R) are satisfied, then move on to (G). That is, assess whether the premises provide sufficient or adequate grounds for the conclusion. An argument is cogent, you ll recall, if, but only if, all three conditions are satisfied. 36 18

Some Examples 1. Debbi is either in La Ronge or she is in Saskatoon. 2. Debbi is not in La Ronge. Therefore, 3. Debbi is in Saskatoon 37 Example 2 1. Animals are not human beings. 2. Animals do not speak language as human beings do. 3. Animals do not have the same advanced cultures and technologies as human beings Therefore, 4. Animals do not have any moral rights. (1, 2, p. 77) 38 19

Example 3 We both own IBM ThinkPad notebook computers. We ve both owned our computers for about three years. We both use our computers for about the same length of time each day. The hard drive on my computer just crashed. So, it s likely that your hard disk will crash too. 39 Example 4 My truck won t start. It could be that I m out of gas. It could be that the starter motor is pooched. But I think it s the battery, since that would also explain why the lights and the CD player don t work either. 40 20

Example 6 1. Students in my political studies class have not been working as hard as students in my political studies class last year. Therefore, 2. Students at the University of Saskatchewan in general are not working as hard this year as they have in the past. And, 3. I think this is caused by affluence and low standards in high schools which produce poor work habits in students. (based on 1, 8, p. 78) 41 The Challenge of Argument This is Govier s term for the, sometimes difficult, task of addressing an argument as an argument, rather than simply disagreeing with it conclusion. Recall the Principle of (Modest) Charity : When someone offers us an argument, we assume she has reasons that justify her conclusion. It would be a failure of charity (and a show of disrespect) to simply reject her conclusion without considering her reasons. 42 21