IS THERE A DUTCH BOOK ARGUMENT FOR PROBABILITY KINEMATICS? *

Similar documents
When Betting Odds and Credences Come Apart: More Worries for Dutch Book Arguments

Lecture 8 The Subjective Theory of Betting on Theories

Review. Bayesianism and Reliability. Today s Class

1. Probabilities lie between 0 and 1 inclusive. 2. Certainty implies unity probability. 3. Probabilities of exclusive events add. 4. Bayes s rule.

Philosophy of Science Association

Interpretations of Probability

Pascal is here expressing a kind of skepticism about the ability of human reason to deliver an answer to this question.

The "Dutch Book" argument, tracing back to independent work by. F.Ramsey (1926) and B.deFinetti (1937), offers prudential grounds for

One natural response would be to cite evidence of past mornings, and give something like the following argument:

3. Mathematical Induction

P1. All of the students will understand validity P2. You are one of the students C. You will understand validity

Markov random fields and Gibbs measures

24. PARAPHRASING COMPLEX STATEMENTS

The Bayesian Approach to the Philosophy of Science

Philosophical Review.

Decision Making under Uncertainty

Two-State Options. John Norstad. January 12, 1999 Updated: November 3, 2011.

6/15/2005 7:54 PM. Affirmative Action s Affirmative Actions: A Reply to Sander

CONCEPTUAL CONTINGENCY AND ABSTRACT EXISTENCE

Probability in Philosophy

The Taxman Game. Robert K. Moniot September 5, 2003

Lecture 9 Maher on Inductive Probability

The Slate Is Not Empty: Descartes and Locke on Innate Ideas

Writing Thesis Defense Papers

Organizing an essay the basics 2. Cause and effect essay (shorter version) 3. Compare/contrast essay (shorter version) 4

E3: PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS lecture notes

arxiv: v1 [math.pr] 5 Dec 2011

Unit 4 The Bernoulli and Binomial Distributions

Self-locating belief and the Sleeping Beauty problem

8 Square matrices continued: Determinants

1.7 Graphs of Functions

INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2015

THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF ARBITRAGE PRICING

The Cable Guy Paradox

CONCLUSIVE arguments in philosophy are rare, so any such

Lecture Notes: Basic Concepts in Option Pricing - The Black and Scholes Model

Logic and Reasoning Practice Final Exam Spring Section Number

A Few Basics of Probability

Book Review of Rosenhouse, The Monty Hall Problem. Leslie Burkholder 1

Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?

Lecture 17 : Equivalence and Order Relations DRAFT

MTH6120 Further Topics in Mathematical Finance Lesson 2

DISTRIBUTION-BASED PRICING FORMULAS ARE NOT ARBITRAGE-FREE DAVID RUHM DISCUSSION BY MICHAEL G. WACEK. Abstract

1/9. Locke 1: Critique of Innate Ideas

The Term Structure of Interest Rates, Spot Rates, and Yield to Maturity

Am I Decisive? Handout for Government 317, Cornell University, Fall Walter Mebane

Quine on truth by convention

So let us begin our quest to find the holy grail of real analysis.

Sensitivity Analysis 3.1 AN EXAMPLE FOR ANALYSIS

Binomial lattice model for stock prices

Killing And Letting Die

Subjective Probability and Lower and Upper Prevision: a New Understanding

1 if 1 x 0 1 if 0 x 1

Question: What is the probability that a five-card poker hand contains a flush, that is, five cards of the same suit?

Notes. futures market does not by itself have any effect on the spot market. It affects current price only to the extent that

The Refutation of Relativism

No-Betting Pareto Dominance

6.4 Logarithmic Equations and Inequalities

One Period Binomial Model

The effect of exchange rates on (Statistical) decisions. Teddy Seidenfeld Mark J. Schervish Joseph B. (Jay) Kadane Carnegie Mellon University

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products

Session 7 Fractions and Decimals

FIRST YEAR CALCULUS. Chapter 7 CONTINUITY. It is a parabola, and we can draw this parabola without lifting our pencil from the paper.

HOW TO WRITE A CRITICAL ARGUMENTATIVE ESSAY. John Hubert School of Health Sciences Dalhousie University

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican, Hertford College. Lecture 3: Induction

Kant on Time. Diana Mertz Hsieh Kant (Phil 5010, Hanna) 28 September 2004

THE DIMENSION OF A VECTOR SPACE

1 Uncertainty and Preferences

Topic 8. Chi Square Tests

Common sense, and the model that we have used, suggest that an increase in p means a decrease in demand, but this is not the only possibility.

Overview of Violations of the Basic Assumptions in the Classical Normal Linear Regression Model

Read this syllabus very carefully. If there are any reasons why you cannot comply with what I am requiring, then talk with me about this at once.

Boonin on the Future-Like-Ours Argument against Abortion. Pedro Galvão Centro de Filosofia da Universidade de Lisboa

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces

Cartesian Products and Relations

The theory of the six stages of learning with integers (Published in Mathematics in Schools, Volume 29, Number 2, March 2000) Stage 1

Probabilities of Poker Hands with Variations

Linear Algebra. A vector space (over R) is an ordered quadruple. such that V is a set; 0 V ; and the following eight axioms hold:

A Failure of the No-Arbitrage Principle

Philosophical argument

The Role of Dispute Settlement Procedures in International Trade Agreements: Online Appendix

Difference tests (2): nonparametric

About the inverse football pool problem for 9 games 1

Quotient Rings and Field Extensions

Reality in the Eyes of Descartes and Berkeley. By: Nada Shokry 5/21/2013 AUC - Philosophy

Linear Programming. April 12, 2005

Solving Linear Systems, Continued and The Inverse of a Matrix

Lecture Note 1 Set and Probability Theory. MIT Spring 2006 Herman Bennett

Elasticity. I. What is Elasticity?

Copyrighted Material. Chapter 1 DEGREE OF A CURVE

Probability. a number between 0 and 1 that indicates how likely it is that a specific event or set of events will occur.

Reading 13 : Finite State Automata and Regular Expressions

Session IX: Lecturer: Dr. Jose Olmo. Module: Economics of Financial Markets. MSc. Financial Economics

How To Know If A Domain Is Unique In An Octempo (Euclidean) Or Not (Ecl)

Math 1526 Consumer and Producer Surplus

Sudoku puzzles and how to solve them

Linear Programming. March 14, 2014

Transcription:

IS THERE A DUTCH BOOK ARGUMENT FOR PROBABILITY KINEMATICS? * BRAD ARMENDT University of Illinois, Chicago Circle Dutch Book arguments have been presented for static belief systems and for belief change by conditionalization. An argument is given here that a rule for belief change which under certain conditions violates probability kinematics will leave the agent open to a Dutch Book. Paul Teller (1973) has reported David Lewis argument that under certain conditions an agent whose degrees of belief in some propositions are changed from less than 1 to 1 by his experience must change his other beliefs by simple conditionalization in order to avoid being the victim of a Dutch Book made by a bookie who knows no more than himself (the agent and the bookie know the agent s rule for changing his beliefs). The significance of Dutch Book arguments of any kind has been questioned and debated; I will not contribute to the debate here. I will examine the possibility of giving a Dutch Book argument for the generalization of simple conditionalization provided by Richard Jeffrey s probability kinematics. I will first show that certain gross violations of probability kinematics leave an agent open to a Dutch Book under assumptions little different from those of Lewis argument (section 2). I will then argue in sections 3 and 4 that for those beliefs which satisfy an additional independence condition, any departure from probability kinematics will leave the agent open to a Dutch Book by a bookie who knows the rule which leads to that departure. The statement and implementation of the additional condition involve the use of second order degrees of belief, and some readers may find this objectionable. However, they may still find the argument instructive. 1. It is important to recall that the formula for probability kinematics is equivalent to a condition stating that the agent does not change his conditional degrees of belief in certain propositions: Suppose an agent with a coherent system of beliefs prob has experience which directly affects his degrees of belief in propositions B1,, B n (his new system of beliefs will be written PROB), where for all i B, prob( Bi) > 0. Let {E 1,, E n 2 } be the set of propositions of the form C 1 & & C n, where each C j is j B or ~B j. Let S = {E 1,, E m } be the set whose elements are all the elements of the above set such that prob( E i ) > 0. By the probability axioms the following condition (1) ( E i S)( A)( prob( A / E i ) = PROB( A / E i ) ) is equivalent to Jeffrey s formula * Received December 1979. I am grateful to Brian Skyrms and Paul Teller for helpful suggestions and encouragement. Philosophy of Science, 47 (1980) pp. 583-588. Copyright 1980 by the Philosophy of Science Association.

BRAD ARMENDT (2) ( A)( PROB( A) = Σ m prob( A / E i ) PROB( E i ) ). So if (1) holds and (2) is violated, PROB will be incoherent and open to a Dutch Book of the standard kind. So if (2) is violated and PROB is coherent, (1) was also violated. 2. Now suppose the rule by which the agent moves from prob to PROB violates (1) and (2). That is, for the given changes of belief in the given B s, his rule is such that for some A s and some E i s, prob( A / E i ) PROB( A / E i ). Let be the set of A s for which (2) is violated. Suppose further that the agent s rule is such that for the particular set of B s, there exists an E i in S such that for some A in, PROB( A / E i ) < prob( A / E i ), no matter what the new degrees of belief PROB in the E j s may be. Then a bookie who knows the rule will be able to make a Dutch Book against the agent by buying bets on A / E i at the cheaper rate, selling them at the higher rate, and selling a side bet. The bookie will 1 if A & E i prob( A / E i ) if ~E i sell, and if not if E i for prob( AE i ) + prob( A / E i ) prob(~e i ) = prob(a / E i ) 1 if A & E i PROB( A / E i ) if ~E i and buy, and if not if E i for PROB( A / E i ). With these bets the bookie will come out ahead if E i (by prob( A / E i ) - PROB( A / E i ) ) and will tie if ~E i. To come out ahead in either event, he sells a side bet [ prob( A / E i ) - PROB( A / E i )] / 2 if E i if ~E i for ½ prob( E i ) [prob( A / E i ) - PROB( A / E i )]. For E i s such that the inequality goes in the other direction, PROB( A / E i ) > prob( A / E i ), the bookie will reverse the buying and selling of the first two pairs of bets and then sell a similar side bet.

DUTCH BOOK ARGUMENT FOR PROBABILITY KINEMATICS 3. In this section we will suppose the agent s rule leads to violations of Jeffrey s formula in a more complicated way. Suppose that for some A in, and for some E i in S, the new degree of belief PROB( A / E i ) is sometimes greater than, sometimes less than the old degree of belief prob( A / E i ), depending upon the value of the new degree of belief PROB( E i ). Note that here we suppose that the rule is such that only one value for PROB( A / E i ) is associated with each possible value of PROB( E i ). Let X i be the set of all possible values of PROB( E i ), and let X i,< be the subset of X i whose elements are such that PROB( A / E i ) is less than prob( A / E i ). Define X i,> similarly. If a bookie knows the agent s rule to the extent the he knows the contents of X i,< and X i,>, and if the following independence condition (C 3 in the second appendix to Skyrms (1979), interpreted as degree of belief prob of future degrees of belief PROB) holds for A and E i, (3) prob[ A / (E i & PROB( E i ) X i,< )] = prob( A / E i ) (similarly for X i,> ), where prob(prob( E i ) X i,< ) is assumed to be nonzero, then the bookie will be able to make a Dutch Book by doing the following: sell 1 if A & E i & PROB( E i ) X i,< if not and prob[ A / (E i & PROB( E i ) X i,< )] if ~( E i & PROB( E i ) X i,< ) if E i & PROB( E i ) X i,< for prob[ A / (E i & PROB( E i ) X i,< )]. Then if PROB( E i ) X i,<, 1 if A & E i PROB( A / E i ) if ~E i buy, and if not if E i for PROB( A / E i ). With these bets the bookie will come out ahead if E i & PROB( E i ) X i,< and will break even if not, since by equality (3) the price of the first pair of bets is prob( A / E i ), which is greater than the price of the second pair, PROB( A / E i ), if PROB( E i ) X i,<. His

BRAD ARMENDT guaranteed gain if E i & PROB( E i ) X i,< is given by prob( A / E i ) - α, where α = max[prob( A / E i ) given that the value of PROB( E i ) is in X i,< ]. 1 To be sure of winning in every case the bookie sells the side bet [ prob( A / E i ) - α] / 2 if E i & PROB( E i ) X i,< if not for [prob( A / E i ) - α] prob(e i & PROB( E i ) X i,< ) / 2. It is not necessary to construct the similar bets (with the buying and selling reversed) for X i,> unless the assumption that prob(prob( E i ) X i,< ) 0 fails, in which case the above bets would not have been made. 4. In this section we will first consider a generalization of the argument given in section 3. In that section it was assumed that the agent s rule is such that the values of PROB( A / E i ) vary as a function of the values of PROB( E i ). This need not be the case; for some possible values x of PROB( E i ), his rule may provide a set of possible values of PROB( A / E i ), depending on the values taken by PROB( E j ) for some or all of the E j s in S. We can deal with this in a straightforward way by considering the function f i mapping m- tuples (x 1,, x m ), where each x k is an element of X k, onto the set of possible values of PROB( A / E i ) in the obvious way: f i (x 1,, x m ) = y iff the agent s rule is such that if PROB( E 1 ) = x 1 & & PROB( E m ) = x m, then PROB( A / E i ) = y. Call the set of all the m-tuples Z and define Z i,< as the subset of Z such that if (x 1,, x m ) Z i,<, then f i (x 1,, x m ) = PROB( A / E i ) < prob( A / E i ), and similarly for Z i,>. Then if the following independence condition holds for A and E i, (3') prob[ A / (E i & (PROB( E 1 ),, PROB( E m )) Z i,< )] = prob( A / E i ) where prob[(prob( E 1 ),, PROB( E m )) Z i,< )] is assumed non-zero, a Dutch Book can be made like that described in section 3. (Substitute the statement (PROB( E 1 ),, PROB( E m )) Z i,< wherever PROB( E i ) X i,< occurs in the description of the bets.) Now it is conceivable that further generalization of the argument is called for. If the agent s rule is such that something in addition to all the new degrees of belief in the E i s helps determine the values of all the PROB( A / E i ) s which are different from prob( A / E i ) s (what could the extra factor plausibly be?), then the arguments above do not supply a Dutch Book against the rule. If the additional factor is such that (3') can be changed to 1 X i,< may be such that α does not exist. And perhaps values of PROB( A / E i ) are not bounded away from prob( A / E i ). If α does not exist take the least upper bound of the values of PROB( A / E i ); if the least α i,< upper bound is prob( A / E i ), a different set X can be chosen such that its members yield values for PROB( A / Ei) less than some α < prob( A / E i ). As long as prob(prob( E i ) X ) is nonzero, the above α i,< i,<. argument works when X is substituted for X α i,<

DUTCH BOOK ARGUMENT FOR PROBABILITY KINEMATICS apply to conditionalization upon statements about it (the factor), then suitable modification of the bets in section 3 will give a Dutch Book if kinematics is violated: (3'') prob[ A / (E i & the value of the factor is such that PROB( A / E i ) < prob( A / E i ))] = prob( A / E i ). If (3'') is not satisfied, then violations of kinematics by the imagined rule will not leave the agent open to a Dutch Book. Of course, without knowledge of the nature of the suggested factor, we cannot judge the propriety of the change of beliefs nor whether a Dutch Book should be available. 5. What do the above arguments and their assumptions tell us about violations of probability kinematics? Let us review the assumptions. First we have the usual assumptions about the agent s betting practices for example, that he is willing to accept any bet he regards as fair. These are of interest in assessing the significance of Dutch Book arguments in general, but they are not special assumptions of the kinematics Dutch Book argument. Next we have assumed (in sections 2, 3, and 4) that the agent and the bookie know where the change of belief will originate, that they know the identities of the B s. There are several things to say about this. The assumption is also made in Lewis argument for simple conditionalization, where it is imagined that a fully detailed partition describing the possible future experiences of the agent is available. The assumption need not be too strong the exact identities need not be known, just some set of B s which contains those where the change originates. But we cannot remove the assumptions by blowing up the set of B s to include everything: a) that set gives us our partition of E i s, and the larger the set of E i s is, the stronger the independence assumptions used in sections 3 and 4 become; and b) if the set of B s includes everything then probability kinematics is trivialized any A will be an element of the partition and (2) will be useless. In many practical situations, however, agent and bookie may have very good information about the origin of the agent s belief change (outcomes of experiments, elections, etc.). And if we see any significance in Dutch Book arguments generally, we may be willing to think that solid arguments for the desirability of a rule (in this case, kinematics) in ideal situations give us at least some reason to like the rule in other situations. What about conditions (3) and (3')? What sort of independence conditions are they? They assert that when information about the new degree of belief in E i (or in all the E i s) is combined with information about the truth of E i, only the latter and not the former influences the degree of belief in A. This is plausible, it seems, for most A s. For example, if in a series of coin tosses PROB is the agent s system of beliefs after the ninth toss, prob[heads on toss 10 / (coin is fair & PROB(coin is fair) (.2,.3) )] = prob(heads on toss 10 / coin is fair) = ½. But there are clear cases in which it should fail, cases in which A is not independent from the agent s beliefs in the E i s. A might, for example, be PROB( E i ) (.5,.6), or more generally, it might be a proposition about some part of the world which is correlated with features of that part of the world which includes the

BRAD ARMENDT agent s belief states. 2 In these cases, then, the failure of the equality in condition (1) may be accompanied by a failure of the new degree of belief in A, PROB(A), to satisfy (2), Jeffrey s formula for kinematics. So what we have shown is that rules containing violations of kinematics for independent A s lead to Dutch Books, while violations for correlated A s need not. REFERENCES Jeffrey, R. (1965), The Logic of Decision. New York: McGraw-Hill. Skyrms, B. (1979), Causal Necessity. New Haven: Yale University Press. Skyrms, B. (forthcoming), Higher Order Degrees of Belief. In Prospects for Pragmatism Essays in Honor of F. P. Ramsey, D. H. Mellor (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Teller, P. (1973), Conditionalization and Observation. Synthese 26: 218-258. 2 For further discussion of (3'), see Brian Skyrms (forthcoming) on his sufficiency condition where he notes that the condition guarantees that second order conditionalization is equivalent to first order probability kinematics. He discusses the condition s plausibility under various interpretations of the distribution PROB. The relevant point here is that in the application we are making, prob represents present degrees of belief about, among other things, future final degrees of belief PROB. The condition seems very plausible in many situations under this interpretation. It is implausible if PROB is given a propensity or an observational degree of belief interpretation.