Kant: Here, Now, and How



Similar documents
Services supply chain management and organisational performance

1/9. Locke 1: Critique of Innate Ideas

Proceedings of the 8 th Euro-Asia Conference on Environment and CSR: Tourism, MICE, Hospitality Management and Education Session (Part II)

ON EXTERNAL OBJECTS By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

Global Trade Law. von Ulrich Magnus. 1. Auflage. Global Trade Law Magnus schnell und portofrei erhältlich bei beck-shop.de DIE FACHBUCHHANDLUNG

Partners. In collaboration with: With the financial support of: European Union ESCEM

The Slate Is Not Empty: Descartes and Locke on Innate Ideas

Reality in the Eyes of Descartes and Berkeley. By: Nada Shokry 5/21/2013 AUC - Philosophy

Andreas Cseh. Quantum Fading. Strategies for Leveraged & Inverse ETFs. Anchor Academic Publishing. disseminate knowledge

How to start up a software business within a cloud computing environment

Bank- und finanzwirtschaftliche Forschungen Band 395

Proceedings of the 7 th Euro-Asia Conference on Environment and CSR: Tourism, MICE, Hospitality Management and Education Session (Part I)

Kant on Time. Diana Mertz Hsieh Kant (Phil 5010, Hanna) 28 September 2004

Inner sense and time

HWZ Schriftenreihe für Betriebs- und Bildungsökonomie. Herausgegeben von HWZ Hochschule für Wirtschaft Zürich. Band 9

Medical Care in Germany

Erich R. Utz. Modelling and Measurement Methods of Operational Risk in Banking. Herbert Utz Verlag München

Permanent Establishments in International Tax Law

Globalization, Technologies and Legal Revolution

The basic principle is that one should not think of the properties of the process by means of the properties of the product

limo B. Poser The Impact of Corporate Venture Capital

Metaphysics and the Question of Being

Partners. In Collaboration with:

Term: Fall 2015 Course Title: Plato Course Number: Philosophy 6704 Section Times/Days: Monday 4:00-6:30 Instructor: Dr. Eric Perl

Phil 420: Metaphysics Spring [Handout 4] Hilary Putnam: Why There Isn t A Ready-Made World

The Logical Way to Teach Introduction to Philosophy. Gabriel R. Camacho El Paso Community College, Transmountain Campus

Financial Markets and Public Finance

Yearbook of Private International Law

Classica et Orientalia

Program Level Learning Outcomes for the Department of Philosophy Page 1

PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES

WRITING A CRITICAL ARTICLE REVIEW

E-LOGOS/2006 ISSN

Legal Aspects of an E-Commerce Transaction

Writing Thesis Defense Papers

#HUMN-104 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

P R I M A R Y A N D S E C O N D A R Y Q U A L I T I E S

Divine command theory

Plato gives another argument for this claiming, relating to the nature of knowledge, which we will return to in the next section.

Psychology has been considered to have an autonomy from the other sciences (especially

How does the problem of relativity relate to Thomas Kuhn s concept of paradigm?

Gödel s Ontological Proof of the Existence of God

Partners. In Collaboration with:

In Defense of Kantian Moral Theory Nader Shoaibi University of California, Berkeley

Positive Philosophy by August Comte

Phenomenological Research Methods

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican, Hertford College. Lecture 3: Induction

Volker Flogel. The Microstructure of European Bond Markets

Skepticism about the external world & the problem of other minds

Kant on Geometry and Spatial Intuition

How should we think about the testimony of others? Is it reducible to other kinds of evidence?

Locke s psychological theory of personal identity

Some key arguments from Meditations III-V

Honours programme in Philosophy

Existence Is Not a Predicate by Immanuel Kant

KARL MARX. For Germany the critique of religion has been successful, and the critique of religion is the basis of all other criticism...

Leitlinien- Clearingbericht "Depression

Killing And Letting Die

Arguments and Dialogues

Traveling in A- and B- Time

Argument for a Distinction Between the Mind/Soul and the Body. This is a prose summary of the diagrammed argument on the previous page:

Technische Berichte Nr. 11 des Hasso-Plattner-Instituts für Softwaresystemtechnik an der Universität Potsdam

They Say, I Say: The Moves That Matter in Academic Writing

HOW TO WRITE A CRITICAL ARGUMENTATIVE ESSAY. John Hubert School of Health Sciences Dalhousie University

Philosophy 175: Theory of Knowledge, Section 003 Loyola University Chicago Ben Bayer Spring 2008

Three Ways to Clarify Your Writing

INTRODUCTION TO ETHICS PHIL 160 Summer Session I

Sense-certainty and the this-such

From the Puzzle of Qualia to the Problem of Sensation

Kant s Dialectic. Lecture 3 The Soul, part II John Filling jf582@cam.ac.uk

Professional Ethics PHIL Today s Topic Absolute Moral Rules & Kantian Ethics. Part I

Sartre and Freedom. Leo Franchi. Human freedom is undoubtedly one of the most fundamental ideas that has driven the

Writing = A Dialogue. Part I. They Say

Social & Political Philosophy. Karl Marx ( ) Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844

Writer moves somewhat beyond merely paraphrasing someone else s point of view or

Writing in Psychology. General Advice and Key Characteristics 1

Mind & Body Cartesian Dualism

Kant s deontological ethics

PHIL 341: Ethical Theory

WRITING ACROSS THE CURRICULUM Writing about Film

Last May, philosopher Thomas Nagel reviewed a book by Michael Sandel titled

SCHOPENHAUER AND WITTGENSTEIN ON SELF AND OBJECT. In the 5.6 s of the Tractatus, Wittgenstein introduces remarks about the self and

Cross-Disciplinary Learning and Teaching Initiative Visual Literacies Summer 2015: Final Report

Read this syllabus very carefully. If there are any reasons why you cannot comply with what I am requiring, then talk with me about this at once.

PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AND SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY Session II Fall 2015 Course description

The Double Lives of Objects: An Essay in the Metaphysics of the Ordinary World

Organizing an essay the basics 2. Cause and effect essay (shorter version) 3. Compare/contrast essay (shorter version) 4

Biological kinds and the causal theory of reference

A Few Basics of Probability

Title: Duty Derives from Telos: The Teleology behind Kant s Categorical Imperative. Author: Micah Tillman

Time and Causation in Gödel s Universe.

Neil Murray University of South Australia April 2011

... methodology and two kinds of ethics

How To Understand The Moral Code Of A God (For Men)

4 Bolzano and Kant on Space and Outer Intuition *

Boonin on the Future-Like-Ours Argument against Abortion. Pedro Galvão Centro de Filosofia da Universidade de Lisboa

AQA PHILOSOPHY SYLLABUS: USEFUL WEB LINKS

Ethical Theory and Responsibility Ethics

Kant and the Turn to Romanticism

Transcription:

Siri Granum Carson, Jonathan Knowles, Bjørn K. Myskja (eds.) Kant: Here, Now, and How Essays in honour of Truls Wyller mentis PADERBORN

Einbandabbildung: Immanuel Kant (nach einem Kupferstich von Johann Friedrich Bause 1791.) Bibliografische Information Der Deutschen Nationalbibliothek Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der Deutschen Nationalbibliografie; detaillierte bibliografische Daten sind im Internet über http://dnb.d-nb.de abrufbar. Gedruckt auf umweltfreundlichem, chlorfrei gebleichtem und alterungsbeständigem Papier ISO 9706 2011 mentis Verlag GmbH Schulze-Delitzsch-Straße 19, D-33100 Paderborn www.mentis.de Alle Rechte vorbehalten. Dieses Werk sowie einzelne Teile desselben sind urheberrechtlich geschützt. Jede Verwertung in anderen als den gesetzlich zulässigen Fällen ist ohne vorherige Zustimmung des Verlages nicht zulässig. Printed in Germany Einbandgestaltung: Satz: Rhema Tim Doherty, Münster [ChH] (www.rhema-verlag.de) Druck: AZ Druck und Datentechnik GmbH, Kempten ISBN: 978-3-89785-764-3

Siri Granum Carson and Bjørn K. Myskja INTRODUCTION 1. Kant today It is hardly possible to overestimate the philosophical influence of Immanuel Kant. A significant part of modern philosophy may be categorized either as neo- Kantian in a narrow or broad sense, or as developed in dialogue or contrast with Kant s ideas. In this anthology we find examples that fit into all of these different categories. What the writers have in common, besides relating in some way to Kantian philosophy in the broad sense, is a relation to the Norwegian philosopher Truls Wyller, who celebrates his 60 th birthday this year. This anthology is put together in honour of Professor Wyller and his extensive efforts towards rethinking Kantian ideas and making them relevant for philosophy today. Among the many managers of the Kantian heritage we may distinguish between the»museum keepers«, who are eager to give a correct interpretation of what Immanuel Kant really meant or to pass on his original insights in untainted form; and more»reconstructive Kantians«, who apply a Kantian framework of some kind to new areas of research. Although being an insightful and careful interpreter of philosophical works, Professor Wyller primarily belongs to the second category. His many creative contributions to new ways of applying Kantian ideas, for example by combining them with ideas from Wittgenstein and the philosophy of language, have been an important contribution to philosophical research, in Norway and further afield. There is an increasing specialization in philosophy today, as in most areas in society. This means that many concentrate on one or two limited areas of philosophy from early on in their studies, through their PhD training to later in their academic careers. This stands in contrast to classic philosophers such as Kant, who wrote extensively on a broad area of subjects touching on all the philosophical disciplines: From ontology and epistemology to ethics and aesthetics. In the same spirit, Professor Wyller has a wide orientation, and has published books on topics ranging from ethics and the idea of a just war, to language, time, and the size of objects. In order to organize the contributions to this anthology, we have divided it into two parts in line with the traditional division of philosophy into a practical (ethics,

8 Siri Granum Carson and Bjørn K. Myskja politics, aesthetics) and theoretical (ontology, epistemology, theory of science) branch. The first part we have called»space, Time & Language«, and the second»life, Death, and Beauty«. 2. Space, time & language: A Kantian approach to knowledge and the world The I think must be capable of accompanying all my presentations. For otherwise something would be presented to me that could not be thought at all which is equivalent to saying that the presentation either would be impossible, or at least would be nothing to me. (Kant, 1996a, B132) These words from the Transcendental Deduction of the Critique of Pure Reason introduce what according to Truls Wyller is»perhaps the single most important passage in the complete writings of Kant«(cf. Wyller 2000, p. 16, our translation). But wherein exactly lies the philosophical significance of this passage? According to Wyller, the answer to this question can be summed up in the two words: apperception and spontaneity, which together enunciate Kant s characteristic take on human understanding of the world (including ourselves as part of that world) as a form of activity. Apperception signifies our rational ability for self-consciousness, as opposed to simple perception or consciousness; whereas spontaneity is the active contribution of our mind to understanding what the world is like, as contrasted with the mere reception of impressions. Understanding is according to Kant not limited to a passive registration of what our senses provide, neither is it determined by our bodily dispositions or the subjective mechanisms of our mental capacities. It involves an element of freedom spontaneity which contributes actively to the way we conceive the world. This is what Kant formulates as the»i think«accompanying all representation, but without itself being a representation of anything (e.g. a subject). This latter point, that the»i think«itself is not a representation, points to the particular role of thinking in our rational self-consciousness; that it cannot itself be reduced to an object of thinking. This insight has become an important point of departure in many later theories of human consciousness and subjectivity, as well as for much contemporary philosophy of language. Within this context, indexicality develops into a central philosophical concept. Through publications such as Indexikalische Gedanken: Über den Gegenstandsbezug in der raumzeitlichen Erkenntnis (Wyller, 1994), and through the organizing of two conferences on the topic of Idexicality and Idealism (in Trondheim in 1999 and 2000 two anthologies by the same name were published by mentis Verlag in 2000 and 2002), Wyller has contributed to this development. Indexicality, in the sense of the essentially context-dependent nature of concepts such as»i«,»here«, and»now«, brings into

Introduction 9 focus the relationship between irreducibly subjective experience (the»i think«) and the possibility of objective, context-free knowledge. The first article in this part, Geert Keil s»ich bin jetzt hier aber wo ist das?«sums up some central elements of indexicality in philosophy, with a focus on the specifically human capacity for spatio-temporal self-localization. Keil starts out from Kant s pre-critical writings on space, and specifically his determination of what Keil calls»der Nullpunkt der Orientierung«: that each of us constructs an egocentric space of orientation, a system of co-ordinates with our own body as»zero point«. Kant thus makes an important contribution to the philosophical investigation of the foundations of our orientational abilities, alongside those of Husserl, Strawson, Tugendhat and Evans. With regards to Wyller s contribution to this tradition, Keil stresses his anti-naturalistic efforts to make clear that the ability to determine our position in time and space has implications regarding the conditions of the very possibility of experience. Contra Wyller, however, Keil states that his intention in the investigation of indexicality is»to get by as far as possible without transcendental idealism«. Spatio-temporal localization is at the very centre of the philosophical interest of both Keil and Wyller. Space and time are everyday concepts, but at the same time they designate a branch of philosophy, as further exemplified by the articles of Solveig Bøe, Ronny S. Myhre, Thomas Krogh, and Dagfinn Dybvig. Wyller attempts to reconceptualize the Kantian view of time and space as aprioriforms of perception, in light of more recent philosophy of language and subjectivity. In her article, Solveig Bøe instead takes us back in time, to ancient Greece where time and space already were in the centre of philosophical attention. Aristotle discusses the concepts of time, place, andthe void in book IV of Physics. In her paper, Bøe investigates Aristotle s account of these concepts, and sees them in relation to Kant s theory. Specifically, she stresses the subjective dimension in Aristotle s analysis, which points in the direction of Kant s pre-critical account of time and space. Ronny S. Myhre views the Kantian account of space from a quite different perspective, namely in relation to neuroscientific findings regarding our visual system. Many interpretations of Kant suggest that his view is that representations of space are innate rather than learned through experience. However, Kant may be interpreted more interestingly, in a way which also corresponds better with recent neuroscience. Myhre discusses John O Keefe s theory of spatial representation in light of such an understanding of the Kantian account of space, as presented by Lorne Falkenstein. According to this view, spatial cognition according to Kant is a basic property of the constitution of our sensory systems rather than constructed by a prior cognitive operation. In Thomas Krogh s article,»the Past in the Present«, we are presented with two different views on the nature of time, by John McTaggard coined the A-theory and B-theory (or theory of A-series and B-series). The A-theory takes our

10 Siri Granum Carson and Bjørn K. Myskja intuitions of time in terms of past, present and future as its basis, while the B-theory claims that all positions in time can be uniquely determined by the relations of earlier and later. Krogh takes so-called presentism as his point of departure, understood as the view that neither past nor future exists only the present. By carefully examining this view, Krogh argues that while presentism is unsatisfactory as an account of time, such a view does not necessarily follow from an A-theory as some have argued. By establishing the possibility of a non-presentist A-theory, Krogh seeks to defend a more plausible version of this account of time. Time is of the essence in Dagfinn Dybvig s contribution as well. In»Kant in the Garden of Infinitely Forking Paths: Time, Causality and the Labyrinth of Philosophy«, Dybvig describes what he calls the labyrinths of philosophy, referring to the lack of straight lines in philosophical research, the lack of permanent results and definite progress, distinguishing it from science in the narrow sense. The relationship between causality and time-determination in the first Critique is the basis for Dybvig s investigation, which he carries out with reference to Jorge Luis Borges short-story The Garden of Forking Paths. Dybvig argues that to Kant a purely imaginative world would be a»garden of infinitely forking paths«in Borges sense, a surreal or labyrinthine»multiverse«. Thanks to the linearity of causality, we experience a comprehensive universe. Although Descartes considered himself as the first philosopher to have refuted scepticism, Kant directs his transcendental argument in the first Critique s Refutation of Idealism against Cartesian skepticism about the external world. Erling Skjei starts out from this relation in»a Pyrrhonian Critique of Descartes Critique of Global Scepticism«. Pyrrhonism refers to a form of global or universal scepticism, i.e. a denial or doubt that any knowledge or reasonable belief is possible. From this perspective, Skjei critically examines Descartes attempt to overthrow scepticism, and concludes that it will not overthrow the Pyrrhonian sceptic. Descartes sceptic is of an academic kind, in the sense that he seems to assert both that everything is doubtful and that he knows that he doubts; while the Pyrrhonian even doubts that he is doubting. Bengt Molander s»subjectivity, Fallibility and the Absence of Doubt«and Jonathan Knowles»Action, causes, and causal explanation«both take Truls Wyller s (2000) book on Kantian thinking, Objektivitet og jeg-bevissthet: En aktualisering av Immanuel Kants filosofi as their point of departure. Molander focuses on the first part of Wyller s book, challenging the expressivist or performativity account of Kant s notion of pure apperception defended in this part. Wyller claims here that Kant s transcendental idealism still has a lot to tell us about the nature of subjectivity in the world, even if Kant s version of it needs both elaboration and modification. Among the important heirs to Kantian thinking, according to Wyller, is Wittgenstein. However, Molander argues that Wittgenstein s position, particularly as developed in On Certainty, presents a much more substantial challenge to Kant s transcendental idealism than that Wyller accepts. The reason is

Introduction 11 partly the essentially social character of the»i«in Wittgenstein, and partly that thinking with and about this»i«is not infallible. In»Action, causes, and causal explanation«, Jonathan Knowles focuses on the theory of action presented in part two of Wyller s book, where transcendental idealism is (again) allied with Wittgensteinean considerations to form the basis for a critique of the causal theory of action, and for the view that actions demand a non-causal explanation. Knowles argues that, though Wyller s arguments go some way to undermining Donald Davidson s well-known causalist account, his central observations are in fact reconcilable with a causal understanding of action under an improved, non-humean account of the notion of cause. Agency and causality remain at the centre of attention in Audun Øfsti s»the Turntable. Two intersecting transformation spaces/frames«. According to Øfsti, the structure of colloquial language deviates from the empirical-observational frame of the natural sciences. However, these two frames»meet«in the descriptions of things and persons in ordinary, pre-scientific (natural, colloquial) language, and it is this intersection which according to Øfsti can function as a kind of»turntable«. This structure brings forth the irreducibility of ordinary language as the medium of interaction and understanding. This language is one of action verbs, pronouns and tenses, and is indispensably a language containing indexical expressions. That indexicals are context-dependent is hardly a controversial claim in the philosophy of language. More disputed, however, is the degree of context-dependence, and what kinds and sources of context-dependence there are. These topics are raised by Olav Asheim, who argues that the one and the same thought cannot be expressed in two different contexts. More specifically he argues that what is said with a sentence in a context C cannot be said with or any other sentence in a context different from C. Anton Koch s article,»die Bildtheorie des Elementarsatzes und die Lesbarkeit der Dinge (Wittgenstein, Sellars, Kant)«, concludes the first part of the anthology. Through his remarks on Wittgenstein, Sellars and Kant, Koch defends a thesis of the»readability of things«. He claims that, thanks to our linguistic capability, we may in a direct, non-metaphorical sense read the things surrounding us. This means, among other things, that we project a propositional form on the world, simply by talking about it, and of the things in it. Koch places this in connection with Kant s transcendental deduction, according to which this propositional form is the categorical structure of things, brought forth when we speak about them. This is the»copernican turn«of Kant.