Lecture Note 7: Revealed Preference and Consumer Welfare



Similar documents
CHAPTER 3 CONSUMER BEHAVIOR

Preferences. M. Utku Ünver Micro Theory. Boston College. M. Utku Ünver Micro Theory (BC) Preferences 1 / 20

Managerial Economics Prof. Trupti Mishra S.J.M. School of Management Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay. Lecture - 13 Consumer Behaviour (Contd )

Problem Set #5-Key. Economics 305-Intermediate Microeconomic Theory

Consumer Theory. The consumer s problem

The fundamental question in economics is 2. Consumer Preferences

One Period Binomial Model

Chapter 3 Consumer Behavior

Problem Set #3 Answer Key

1. Briefly explain what an indifference curve is and how it can be graphically derived.

CONSUMER PREFERENCES THE THEORY OF THE CONSUMER

Demand. Lecture 3. August Reading: Perlo Chapter 4 1 / 58

chapter >> Consumer and Producer Surplus Section 3: Consumer Surplus, Producer Surplus, and the Gains from Trade

Chapter 27: Taxation. 27.1: Introduction. 27.2: The Two Prices with a Tax. 27.2: The Pre-Tax Position

REVIEW OF MICROECONOMICS

Choice under Uncertainty

Theory of Demand. ECON 212 Lecture 7. Tianyi Wang. Winter Queen s Univerisity. Tianyi Wang (Queen s Univerisity) Lecture 7 Winter / 46

Common sense, and the model that we have used, suggest that an increase in p means a decrease in demand, but this is not the only possibility.

Lecture 2. Marginal Functions, Average Functions, Elasticity, the Marginal Principle, and Constrained Optimization

. In this case the leakage effect of tax increases is mitigated because some of the reduction in disposable income would have otherwise been saved.

Our development of economic theory has two main parts, consumers and producers. We will start with the consumers.

The Mathematics 11 Competency Test Percent Increase or Decrease

c 2008 Je rey A. Miron We have described the constraints that a consumer faces, i.e., discussed the budget constraint.

U = x x x 1 4. What are the equilibrium relative prices of the three goods? traders has members who are best off?

Pre-Algebra Lecture 6

3. Mathematical Induction

CHAPTER 4 Consumer Choice

Price Elasticity of Supply; Consumer Preferences

ECON 305 Tutorial 7 (Week 9)

DEMAND FORECASTING. Demand. Law of Demand. Definition of Law of Demand

Week 3: Demand Theory and Welfare Analysis

The Cobb-Douglas Production Function

Lesson 7 - The Aggregate Expenditure Model

Chapter 21: The Discounted Utility Model

Chapter 4 Online Appendix: The Mathematics of Utility Functions

Economics 2020a / HBS 4010 / HKS API-111 FALL 2010 Solutions to Practice Problems for Lectures 1 to 4

Walrasian Demand. u(x) where B(p, w) = {x R n + : p x w}.

Profit Maximization. 2. product homogeneity

Review of Fundamental Mathematics

The Central Idea CHAPTER 1 CHAPTER OVERVIEW CHAPTER REVIEW

Natural Resources and International Trade

ECON 600 Lecture 5: Market Structure - Monopoly. Monopoly: a firm that is the only seller of a good or service with no close substitutes.

MATH10212 Linear Algebra. Systems of Linear Equations. Definition. An n-dimensional vector is a row or a column of n numbers (or letters): a 1.

Solution to Exercise 7 on Multisource Pollution

Exercises Lecture 8: Trade policies

On Lexicographic (Dictionary) Preference

Basic Components of an LP:

INTRODUCTORY MICROECONOMICS

Notes on indifference curve analysis of the choice between leisure and labor, and the deadweight loss of taxation. Jon Bakija

I. Introduction to Taxation

Knowledge Enrichment Seminar for Senior Secondary Economics Curriculum. Macroeconomics Series (3): Extension of trade theory

Microeconomics Sept. 16, 2010 NOTES ON CALCULUS AND UTILITY FUNCTIONS

Cost of Production : An Example

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2015

CHAPTER 7: CONSUMER BEHAVIOR

Economics 326: Duality and the Slutsky Decomposition. Ethan Kaplan

Tastes and Indifference Curves

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A)

18.01 Single Variable Calculus Fall 2006

Consumers face constraints on their choices because they have limited incomes.

Module 49 Consumer and Producer Surplus

Decision Making under Uncertainty

Price Theory Lecture 4: Production & Cost

People have thought about, and defined, probability in different ways. important to note the consequences of the definition:

Price Discrimination and Two Part Tariff

Covariance and Correlation

ECON 103, ANSWERS TO HOME WORK ASSIGNMENTS

Introductory Notes on Demand Theory

Next Tuesday: Amit Gandhi guest lecture on empirical work on auctions Next Wednesday: first problem set due

Chapter 7 Monopoly, Oligopoly and Strategy

Table of Contents MICRO ECONOMICS

Review Question - Chapter 7. MULTIPLE CHOICE. Choose the one alternative that best completes the statement or answers the question.

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces

4 THE MARKET FORCES OF SUPPLY AND DEMAND

Chapter 4 Individual and Market Demand

MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 6.436J/15.085J Fall 2008 Lecture 5 9/17/2008 RANDOM VARIABLES

Name Eco200: Practice Test 2 Covering Chapters 10 through 15

Second degree price discrimination

Chapter 25: Exchange in Insurance Markets

Economics 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics Problem Set 2 1/20/10

The aerodynamic center

AK 4 SLUTSKY COMPENSATION

6. Budget Deficits and Fiscal Policy

POTENTIAL OUTPUT and LONG RUN AGGREGATE SUPPLY

1.7 Graphs of Functions

Deriving MRS from Utility Function, Budget Constraints, and Interior Solution of Optimization

Efficiency and Equity

Polynomial Invariants

COST THEORY. I What costs matter? A Opportunity Costs

Practice Problem Set 2 (ANSWERS)

Notes - Gruber, Public Finance Chapter 20.3 A calculation that finds the optimal income tax in a simple model: Gruber and Saez (2002).

Homework #5: Answers. b. How can land rents as well as total wages be shown in such a diagram?

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 2: Strategic Form Games

Week 4: Standard Error and Confidence Intervals

Web Supplement to Chapter 2

Midterm Exam #1 - Answers

Pre-Test Chapter 25 ed17

Chapter 4 The Theory of Individual Behavior

Chapter 3. The Concept of Elasticity and Consumer and Producer Surplus. Chapter Objectives. Chapter Outline

Capital Structure. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Transcription:

Lecture Note 7: Revealed Preference and Consumer Welfare David Autor, Massachusetts Institute of Technology 14.03/14.003 Microeconomic Theory and Public Policy, Fall 2010 1

1 Revealed Preference and Consumer Welfare We have to date been applying an axiomatic approach to characterizing consumer choice, based on the five axioms given in Lecture 3. But there is an approach to assessing utility that requires even fewer assumptions and nevertheless gives strong results. This approach is called Revealed Preference. Consider the figure below, where the consumer sequentially faces two budget sets, I 1 I 1 and I 2 I 2.Point A on I 1 I 1 is initially chosen. This point is said to be revealed preferred to all other feasible points inside of the budget set. 8#1 I 1 A I 2 B C I 1 I 2 Now the consumer is faced with I 2 I 2. If the consumer chooses point B, are they better or worse off? Worse off, because point A was revealed preferred to point B under the initial choice conditions. If they choose point C, are they better or worse off? The axiomatic approach would tend to suggest they are better off because unless the indifference curve tangent to point A has an extremely shallow slope, point C would probably put them on a higher indifference curve. But under Revealed Preference, the answer is ambiguous. The reason is that we do not have any revealed preference information on whether A is preferred to C or vice versa these choices were never available simultaneously. 2

Take a second example (below) y 8#2 I 1 No longer feasible under I 2 I 2 I 2 A A Newly feasible under I 2 -I 2 A I 1 I 2 x Here the second budget set rotates through the originally chosen point A on the first budget set. We do not know the consumer s new choice. Is the consumer better off, worse off, or can t we say? We know that point A r.p. (A, A ] We do not know but it is possible that a point on (A, A ] is preferred to A. We say that the consumer is weakly better off. Definition 1 Weak Axiom of Revealed Preference: If A, B feasible and A chosen, then at any prices and income where A, B are feasible, the consumer will choose A over B. This axiom says two things: 1. People choose what they prefer. 2. Preferences are consistent. Therefore, a single observed choice reveals a stable preference. There is also a stronger form of this axiom. 3

1.1 The power of WARP 1.1.1 Demonstration 1 X The result that Px u=u 0 < 0 (i.e., the compensated demand curve is always downward sloping) depends on an untested assumption about diminishing MRS, giving rise to indifference curves that are bowed inward towards the origin. Can we obtain the same result using only WARP? Suppose two points C, D on intersecting budget sets. Assume that these points are indifferent for consumer utility (see Figure 8#3). That is, the consumer has told us that he or she is indifferent. C = (X c,y c ) D = (X d,y d ). y 8#3 C D x Note that the indifference curve drawn here is simply meant to represent the fact that the consumer says she is indifferent. There is no notion of indifference curves in the Revealed Preference approach. 4

Since C, D do not lie in the same budget sets, when C is available, D is not and vice versa. Since C D, ismustbetruebywarp that P x c X c + P y c Y c P x c X d + P y c Y d when C is chosen, Rearranging, we get: P d X d + P d Y d P d X c + P d Y c when D is chosen. x y x y P x c (X c X d )+ P y c (Y c Y d ) 0, P x d (X d X c )+ P y d (Y d Y c ) 0. which simply says that at prices where C is purchased, D must have been at least as expensive as C (or C would have been purchased), and at prices where D is purchased, C must have been at least as expensive as D (or D would have been purchased). Combining, we get (we add the two inequalities - remember if something is smaller than or equal to zero, the combination of the two must also be smaller than or equal to zero) (P x c P x d )(X c X d )+(P y c P y d )(Y c Y d ) 0. (1) Now, consider a case where only the price of X, (P x ) changes and assume that P y c = P y d. Using (1), thisgives whichincalculusterms is equivalent to: (P x c P x d )(X c X d ) 0, X u=u0 0. P x (Remember that C D, so we are holding utility constant.) So, WARP is sufficient to establish weakly downward sloping compensated demand curves. [Why Compensated? Because utility is held constant in this example since C D.] The entire idea of revealed preference is simply by using the weak notion of choosing what you prefer, you get strong rationality properties, including: Weakly downward sloping demand curves. Only relative prices matter (as can be seen in the example above). We therefore don t have to make strong assumptions about diminishing MRS to get strong predictions about rational behavior. 5

1.1.2 Demonstration 2 Here s a second proof of the above that does not invoke indifference. Without talking about indifference curves, we can t really hold U constant. But we can still talk about compensated demand. Suppose that the consumer is initially buying some bundle A. The price of X goes up, and we give the consumer just enough extra income to make A affordable again (see figure below). Y 8 #3 Y max B A X max X The new budget line is X max Y max. Is it possible that the consumer would choose a point on this budget line between X max and A? No. These points were all available to the consumer at the original prices and income, and the consumer chose A instead. Under WARP, the only points on the new budget line that the consumer would be expected to choose are between A and Y max, since these were not available before. These points all have the consumer buying the same or less X than she bought at A (when the price of X was lower). Note: the potential weakness of this proof is that the Axiomatic approach to consumer 6

theory would suggest that the consumer is strictly better off along the new budget set than the old one (given that A is available, she cannot be worse off; given reasonable preferences, she is likely on a higher indifference curve). Thus, this proof does not strictly hold utility constant, which is required for the definition of compensated demand. 1.2 The Strong Axiom of Revealed Preference (SARP) Definition 2 Strong Axiom of Revealed Preference (SARP): If commodity bundle 0 is revealed preferred to bundle 1 and bundle 1 is r.p. to bundle 2 and bundle 2 is r.p. to bundle 3... and bundle k 1 is r.p. to bundle k, then bundle k cannot be r.p. to bundle 0. SARP is simply WARP with an added transitivity assumption. But this places much greater strictures on behavior. 2 Using WARP to evaluate the consequences of taxation For many reasons, governments need to tax: Pay for public goods: Defense, law enforcement, regulatory agencies. Transfer income social insurance. Correct externalities (pollution, sins ). Are there better and worse ways to tax? Let s compare two types of taxes: A lump-sum tax: reduces the consumer s budget by L. A sales tax on a single good: charge tax t on X so that P x t = P x + t. Obviously, consumer s are worse off for being taxed, but can we say anything stronger than that? See figure. 7

y 8#4 I/p y (I - L)/p y Lump sum taxation (I - L)/p x I/p x x Note the algebra of the lump sum tax: XP x + YP y = I, (2) X L P x + Y L P y = I L, (3) (X X L )P x +(Y Y L )P y = L To compare the lump-sum tax with a revenue equivalent sales tax, we need revenue equivalence (i.e., same level of taxes collected). Let s consider a tax of t on purchases of good X. So, for every X consumed, the consumer pays t in taxes. For t to be revenue-equivalent to L, the following condition must hold: t d x (P x + t,p y,i)=l. In words, the revenue equivalent sales tax generates the same total taxation as L by charging t on each X purchased. To see this, note: X t (P x + t )+Y t P y = I, (4) I X t P x YP y = X t t. 8

So, for revenue equivalence, we need X t t = L. We know from (2) that the budget set that characterizes the lump-sum tax is given by X L P x + Y L P y = I L. So, the revenue equivalent tax must also put the consumer on this budget set. Hence, X t P x + Y t P y = X L P x + Y L P y. Graphically, the revenue equivalent tax is the tax that causes the consumer to consume on the Lump-sum budget set. See figure. y 8#5 I/p y (I - L)/p y C A B I/(p x +t) (I L)/p x I/p x x Notice that the exact tax t that solves this problem depends upon consumer preferences. If consumption of X is highly elastic to the tax (that is, it falls precipitously), we ll need to set t fairly high to get t X t = L. Since the tax puts the consumer back on the lump-sum budget set, does this imply that she is just as well off under either tax scheme? No. By WARP, the consumer is weakly worse off under the sales tax than the lump-sum tax. By shifting the price ratio, the tax has caused the consumer to choose a point on the lump-sum budget set that is not the most preferred point on this set. Tax has distorted the choice. 9

This is a Revealed Preference argument: We know by WARP that B is the most preferred point on the budget set [(I L) /p x, (I L)/p y ]. So, if taxation causes the consumer to choose any point other than B on this budget set, the consumer must be at least weakly worse off. A powerful and general result: If you must tax, you harm consumers less by simply taking a chunk of their budget than by distorting prices and ultimately taxing an identical share of their budget. Drawing on the axiomatic approach to consumer utility, what is the exact distortion? In the lump-sum case, it remains true that U x U y P x P y =. Whereas in the revenue equivalent taxation case, the consumer s optimal choice will satisfy U x U y P x + t =. Their consumption choices do not reflect the real costs of goods provided in the market they are distorted by the tax. There are producers willing to sell X at price P x and consumers who would gladly pay P x. But they will notpurchaseatthisprice dueto the tax. However, consumers and producers can transact for Y at price P y. As a result consumers will under-consume X and overconsume Y relative to their real market costs. Consider: What would be the efficiency consequences (relative to a revenue equivalent lump sum tax) of charging the same proportional tax on all goods? 2.1 Proof of distortionary impact of non-neutral taxation of goods Consider (implausibly) a tax that is fully rebated to the consumer: t d x (P x + t, P y,i + Z) = Z. (5) P y This tax is revenue neutral for consumer; rebated exactly the amount paid in taxes (Z). Hence, only effect is to alter the price ratio faced by consumer. A critical (but strange) assumption here is that the consumer does not realize that the tax is fully rebated; that is, when the consumer buys X, she does not consider that she ll get 10

Z = tx tax rebate in return. If she did realize this, it would make the exercise pointless; the consumer would, in effect, face no real tax on X. This can be reconciled with the assumption there is a multiple identical individuals with the same preferences, therefore one individual s rebate will be dependant on other people s choices and not his own. You can check that the consumer spends the original budget I by writing: (P x + t) d x (P x + t, P y,i + Z)+P y d y (P x + t, P y,i + Z) =I + Z. Subtracting (5) from both sides, we get P x d x (P x + t, P y,i + Z)+P y d y (P x + t, P y,i + Z) =I. Hence, the consumer is on the original budget set. But as long as the consumer changes the consumption bundle in response to the tax-ratio (i.e., as would occur for any utility function satisfying the standard 5 axioms), then the consumption bundle is distorted by the tax: d x (P x + t, P y,i + Z) = d x (P x,p y,i), d y (P x + t, P y,i + Z) = d y (P x,p y,i). In words, the consumer will be consuming on a different point on the original budget set I under the taxed price ratio. If so, the consumer is worse off by Revealed Preference. Hence, the distortion induced by non-neutral taxation is that it causes the consumer to pick a non-preferred point on the true (non-distorted) budget set. Note that this argument does not depend on any axioms of utility theory other than WARP.The essentialpoint is: We know that the consumer will have to pick a point on the original budget set for the tax to be revenue equivalent. But rather than allow the consumer to simply face that budget set and choose the preferred point, we are distorting her behavior by shifting the slope while ultimately placing them back somewhere on the same line. 11

If they choose any other point than the preferred point on the un-distorted budget set, they are weakly worse off. (Only weakly because we have no way of knowing whether the consumer was indifferent among multiple points on the original budget set, such as A and B). y (I+Z)/p y A point chosen on orginal budget set 8#6 I/p y B point chosen on tax rebate budget set B A I/(p x +t) (I+Z)/(p x +t) I/p x x 12

MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 14.03 / 14.003 Microeconomic Theory and Public Policy Fall 2010 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms.