The Cable Guy Paradox



Similar documents
When Betting Odds and Credences Come Apart: More Worries for Dutch Book Arguments

Self-locating belief and the Sleeping Beauty problem

Pascal is here expressing a kind of skepticism about the ability of human reason to deliver an answer to this question.

Lecture 8 The Subjective Theory of Betting on Theories

= = 106.

A Short Course in Logic Zeno s Paradox

A Dutch Book for Group Decision-Making?

Double Deck Blackjack

"I'll Be Glad I Did It" Reasoning and the Significance of Future Desires. Elizabeth Harman. Word Count: 4,499. I. Two Puzzles

Game Theory and Poker

AMS 5 CHANCE VARIABILITY

Sleeping Beauty, as described on wikipedia, citing Arnold

Last time we had arrived at the following provisional interpretation of Aquinas second way:

Does rationality consist in responding correctly to reasons? John Broome Journal of Moral Philosophy, 4 (2007), pp

Decision Theory Rational prospecting

arxiv: v1 [math.pr] 5 Dec 2011

MA 1125 Lecture 14 - Expected Values. Friday, February 28, Objectives: Introduce expected values.

Review. Bayesianism and Reliability. Today s Class

Donating vs. Investing

Harvard College Program in General Education Faculty of Arts and Sciences Harvard University. A Guide to Writing in Ethical Reasoning 15

Chapter 21: The Discounted Utility Model

7 Secrets To Websites That Sell. By Alex Nelson

SOLUTIONS TO ASSIGNMENT 1 MATH 576

Slippery Slopes and Vagueness

Probability and Expected Value

We never talked directly about the next two questions, but THINK about them they are related to everything we ve talked about during the past week:

Lawyers in Business Meetings

6.042/18.062J Mathematics for Computer Science. Expected Value I

1 Uncertainty and Preferences

! Insurance and Gambling

Gaming the Law of Large Numbers

Chapter 4 Lecture Notes

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican, Hertford College. Lecture 3: Induction

Lecture 13. Understanding Probability and Long-Term Expectations

Economics 1011a: Intermediate Microeconomics

Decision Making under Uncertainty

In Defense of Kantian Moral Theory Nader Shoaibi University of California, Berkeley

Service Outsourcing Handoff Run Amok - A Black Box Case Study from the Insurance Industry

Random Fibonacci-type Sequences in Online Gambling

15-251: Great Theoretical Ideas in Computer Science Anupam Gupta Notes on Combinatorial Games (draft!!) January 29, 2012

Wald s Identity. by Jeffery Hein. Dartmouth College, Math 100

The epistemic structure of de Finetti s betting problem

Moral Hazard. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

How To Understand The Theory Of Active Portfolio Management

Why Betting Odds and Credences Come Apart

TABLE OF CONTENTS FILING YOUR APPEAL...

An Introduction to Business Blogs, their benefits & how to promote them

After 3 races the player with the highest winnings has won that day s racing.

I LL BE GLAD I DID IT REASONING AND THE SIGNIFICANCE OF FUTURE DESIRES. Elizabeth Harman Princeton University

Getting your s opened (AND read)

Philosophical Review.

TeachingEnglish Lesson plans

Bonus Maths 2: Variable Bet Sizing in the Simplest Possible Game of Poker (JB)

I d Rather Stay Stupid: The Advantage of Having Low Utility

Choice Under Uncertainty

MONEY MANAGEMENT. Guy Bower delves into a topic every trader should endeavour to master - money management.

Phil 420: Metaphysics Spring [Handout 4] Hilary Putnam: Why There Isn t A Ready-Made World

SOME ASPECTS OF GAMBLING WITH THE KELLY CRITERION. School of Mathematical Sciences. Monash University, Clayton, Victoria, Australia 3168

On the Paradox of the Question

Week 2: Conditional Probability and Bayes formula

1/3 1/3 1/

Chapter 16: law of averages

BONUS REPORT#5. The Sell-Write Strategy

Types of Brokerage Accounts

Time Value of Money Dallas Brozik, Marshall University

The power of money management

Unit 19: Probability Models

TEST 2 STUDY GUIDE. 1. Consider the data shown below.

Standard 12: The student will explain and evaluate the financial impact and consequences of gambling.

CHAPTER II THE LIMIT OF A SEQUENCE OF NUMBERS DEFINITION OF THE NUMBER e.

How To Choose Between A Goat And A Door In A Game Of \"The Black Jackpot\"

Probability, statistics and football Franka Miriam Bru ckler Paris, 2015.

Discrete Math in Computer Science Homework 7 Solutions (Max Points: 80)

How to Communicate With Your Divorce Attorney, Reduce Your Level of Stress, And Actually Save Money

Starting a new Oil Analysis Program Burden or Benefit?

Insurance. Michael Peters. December 27, 2013

U N I V E R S I T Y O F C O P E N H A G E N. Use Your Master s Thesis Supervisor

Time and Causation in Gödel s Universe.

Why is Insurance Good? An Example Jon Bakija, Williams College (Revised October 2013)

Critical analysis. Be more critical! More analysis needed! That s what my tutors say about my essays. I m not really sure what they mean.

Phil 4800 Notes #1: Rational Choice & Framing

Growing Your Company Without Debt

Moving on! Not Everyone Is Ready To Accept! The Fundamental Truths Of Retail Trading!

1. Probabilities lie between 0 and 1 inclusive. 2. Certainty implies unity probability. 3. Probabilities of exclusive events add. 4. Bayes s rule.

7. Show that the expectation value function that appears in Lecture 1, namely

Samples of Opening Paragraphs for a Short Philosophy Paper

Homework Assignment #2: Answer Key

Statistics and Random Variables. Math 425 Introduction to Probability Lecture 14. Finite valued Random Variables. Expectation defined

Incentive Compensation in the Banking Industry:

rattlebones_rules_mas.indd :59

How To Increase Your Odds Of Winning Scratch-Off Lottery Tickets!

Expected Value and the Game of Craps

white paper Challenges to Target Funds James Breen, President, Horizon Fiduciary Services

STATISTICS 8: CHAPTERS 7 TO 10, SAMPLE MULTIPLE CHOICE QUESTIONS

Luc Bovens and Woldek Rabinowicz Bets on hats: on Dutch books against groups, degrees of belief as betting rates, and group-reflection

1 Speed of light is the maximal possible speed

Statistics 100A Homework 3 Solutions

Journal Of Financial And Strategic Decisions Volume 8 Number 1 Spring 1995 INTEREST RATE SWAPS: A MANAGERIAL COMPENSATION APPROACH

Lipstick on a Pig. Getting your multifamily property ready for a sale

Ch. 13.3: More about Probability

Transcription:

The Cable Guy Paradox Alan Hájek Analysis, Vol 65. No. 4, April 2005 The Cable Guy is coming. You have to be home in order for him to install your new cable service, but to your chagrin he cannot tell you exactly when he will come. He will definitely come between 8.a.m. and 4 p.m. tomorrow, but you have no more information than that. I offer to keep you company while you wait. To make things more interesting, we decide now to bet on the Cable Guy s arrival time. We subdivide the relevant part of the day into two 4-hour long intervals, morning : (8, 12], and afternoon : (12, 4). You nominate an interval on which you will bet. If he arrives during your interval, you win and I will pay you $10; otherwise, I win and you will pay me $10. Notice that we stipulate that if he arrives exactly on the stroke of noon, then (8, 12] is the winning interval, since it is closed on the right; but we agree that this event has probability 0 (we have a very precise clock!). At first you think: obviously there is no reason to favour one interval over the other. Your probability distribution of his arrival time is uniform over the 8 a.m. 4 p.m. period, and thus assigns probability 1/2 to each of the two 4-hour periods at issue. Whichever period you nominate, then, your expected utility is the same. The two choices are equally rational. But then you reason as follows. Suppose that you choose the morning interval. Then there will certainly be a period during which you will regard the other interval as

2 preferable. For even if the Cable Guy arrives in the morning interval (the best case scenario), some portion of that interval will have elapsed before his arrival. During that portion, you would be rationally required to swap your bet to the afternoon interval if given the opportunity (although there will be no such opportunity since the bets are irreversible). For example, if he arrives at 10 a.m., then for two hours your interval will have been gradually dwindling, while the afternoon interval remains fully intact. Indeed, an instant before 10 a.m., only two hours (plus that instant) of your interval will remain, and given your uniform distribution for his arrival time, your probability at that time of winning will be (approximately) only half your probability for the afternoon interval winning. Similar reasoning applies however early he might arrive in the morning: at 8:10, or at 8:01, or at a second past 8:00, or at least some of your interval will have been used up before his arrival, and during that time you will be rationally required to regard the afternoon interval, with its full complement of four hours, as more desirable. For each possible arrival time in the morning, there is an earlier time at which you must prefer the afternoon interval. Now suppose that you choose the afternoon interval. Then it is not the case that there will certainly be a period during which you will regard the other interval as preferable. On the contrary, if at 12:00 the Cable Guy still has not shown up (an event you now assign probability 1/2), then far from wishing that you could exchange your interval for the other one, you will know at that point that you will win. Of course, you do not know now that he will arrive during afternoon. You realize that if you nominate this interval, you may be wrong he may arrive in the morning, and in that case you will (retrospectively) regard that interval as preferable. However, this sort of preference-

3 switching is not guaranteed. And the prospect of this sort of preference-switching is the same whichever interval you pick: the risk of being wrong is the same. But nominating the morning interval commits you to a guaranteed and asymmetric preference-switching caused by watching at least some of your interval erode away before his arrival; nominating the afternoon interval protects you from such preference-switching. So you should nominate the afternoon interval. Where initially you regarded the two choices symmetrically, you have now found a symmetry-breaker. Note that we have not added any extra details to the original story. We have not, for example, added new considerations about the disutility of the pain of regretting one s choice, forcing a recalculation of the original expected utilities. All the reasoning assumes is that money is the only source of utility in this game, and that you are an expected utility maximizer. You are certain now that a rational future self of yours will assign higher probability to the Cable Guy s arriving in the afternoon than in the morning. Thus, you are certain now that a rational future self of yours will assign higher expected utility to betting on his arriving in the afternoon than in the morning. So you are certain now that a rational future self of yours will prefer betting on the afternoon interval. Why wait, then? It seems rationally required for you to form that preference now. Prompted by this talk of rational future selves, we may put the reasoning in terms of a plausible diachronic rationality principle somewhat in the spirit of van Fraassen s Reflection Principle (1984 and 1995). The idea is that you should not knowingly frustrate a rational future self of yours. I will call it the Avoid Certain Frustration Principle :

4 Suppose you now have a choice between two options. You should not choose one of these options if you are certain that a rational future self of yours will prefer that you had chosen the other one unless both your options have this property. I have carefully worded the principle so as to evade four types of potential counterexample the first ruled out by the word certain, the second by rational, the third by two options, and the fourth by unless both your options have this property : 1) Uncertain frustration: Of course, we frequently frustrate our future selves while acting fully rationally, because we are uncertain of how events will transpire. Suppose that a fair coin is about to be tossed, and you now have a choice between betting on heads and betting on tails. Quite rationally, you choose to bet on heads, fully aware that the coin may land tails, and that a rational future self of yours after the coin has landed will in that case prefer that you had chosen to bet on tails. But this is no counterexample to the Avoid Certain Frustration Principle, because the prospect of this frustration is uncertain. 2) Certain frustration when there are at least three options: Sometimes it is rational to knowingly frustrate a future self when one is choosing among three or more options, and when this does not reduce to a pair-wise choice in which there is such foreseen frustration. This can happen when there is foreseen frustration of some form or other, but it is not foreseen exactly which form it will take. (When there are only two options, the frustration over having chosen one option can only take one form: a preference for the other option.) Now suppose, for example, that we add a third choice to the coin tossing case: you may refuse to bet. This is surely a rational choice (even if it is not rationally

5 required, since the betting options have just as high expected utility). Yet you are certain that a rational future self of yours after the coin has landed will prefer that you had chosen to bet on the winning result. 1 But notice that this does not reduce to a two-option choice to which the Avoid Certain Frustration Principle would apply, for you are not certain now which of the two betting choices will eventually be regarded as preferable to not betting. You are not certain now, for example, that a rational future self of yours will prefer that you had chosen to bet on heads. So the Principle does not deliver an incorrect verdict here, because it does not deliver a verdict at all. 3) Rational protection against an irrational future self: In certain special cases, a rational agent may foresee a future lapse in rationality, and may act now knowingly so as to frustrate an irrational future self. In the Odyssey, as Ulysses approaches the sirens he has two options: tying himself to the mast so that he cannot steer his ship fatally to the cliff where they are irresistibly singing, or not doing so. He rationally chooses to tie himself to the mast, despite being certain that a future self of his (namely, one under the spell of the sirens) will prefer that he had chosen not to do so. He is thus certain to frustrate a future self of his. But Ulysses knows that the future self here is not rational, so this is no counterexample to the Avoid Certain Frustration Principle. 4) Frustration whatever you choose: The Avoid Certain Frustration Principle ends with a caveat: unless both your options have this property. There may be pathological cases of choices between two options that activate this caveat: whichever option you 1 I thank Marc Lange for a closely related example.

6 choose now, foreseeably a rational future self of yours will prefer that you had chosen the other one. Perhaps the infinite version of the two envelope paradox in which you get to open your envelope is like this: arguably, you know now that whatever you see, you will prefer having the other envelope. (See, e.g., Arntzenius and McCarthy 1997 and Chalmers 2002.) But we need not settle such cases, because the Avoid Certain Frustration Principle is suitably weakened by the caveat so as not to address them. None of these four kinds of excusing conditions for foreseeable future frustration applies in the Cable Guy scenario. The choice to bet on the morning interval falls squarely under the purview of the Avoid Certain Frustration Principle. It is thus ruled out. Rationality, then, requires you to bet on the afternoon interval (the only choice that is not so ruled out). This is paradoxical, because your initial reasoning that there is nothing to favour one interval over the other seemed impeccable. We can equally arrive at the paradox by focusing on the evidence that you are certain of receiving. At the moment, your evidence bears symmetrically on both the intervals; but you are certain of getting evidence that will bear asymmetrically on them. The Principle of Indifference seems to apply in your current epistemic state hence your initial 1/2-1/2 probability distribution over the two intervals. But you are certain that you will soon be in an epistemic state in which the Principle will not apply in which your probability distribution will favour the afternoon interval. All this without any epistemic impairment at any stage no sirens calling you to choose that interval, or what have you. Maximizing your probability of winning, given your evidence, is all the call you need. So you are certain now that if you choose the morning interval, you will receive evidence that will undermine that choice: having received the evidence, you will

7 rationally disprefer having made that choice. Call a choice self-undermining if, having made it, you are certain that you will receive undermining evidence regarding it. Betting on the morning interval is a self-undermining choice. Not so betting on the afternoon interval: having done so, you are not certain that you will receive undermining evidence regarding it. Now let us appeal to an equally plausible 2 and more succinct diachronic rationality principle, which I will call the Avoid Self-Undermining Choices Principle : Whenever you have a choice between two options, you should not make a selfundermining choice if you can avoid doing so. You can avoid making a self-undermining choice by betting on the afternoon interval. And so, apparently, you should. This is so even though the afternoon interval contains neither of its endpoints, so in that sense it appears to be shorter by a point! than the morning interval. Remember that the endpoints each have probability zero. Curiously, the topology of the set-up that the intervals are open on the left is crucial. Suppose, for example, that the first interval was instead [8, 12], so that the Cable Guy could arrive at 8:00 on the dot. If he did so, then none of the interval would have elapsed before his arrival. Then there would be no period of preference-switching, if that were your chosen interval. The inclusion or exclusion of a probability zero event makes all the difference to your reasoning: the diachronic rationality principles apply in one case, and not in the other. To be sure, we could strengthen those principles so that they would apply either way: by replacing their explicit or implicit reference to what you regard as certain with a cagier reference to what you assign probability 1. But thanks to the topology of our case, we need not do so. 2 In fact, I believe that it is equivalent to the Avoid Certain Frustration Principle, although proving this equivalence is beyond the scope of this paper.

8 Another curiosity is that despite your apparent preference for the afternoon interval, you should now choose the morning interval given the tiniest incentive. If I paid you a penny up front to choose the morning interval, you should: then, the expected utility of doing so would be a penny better than that of choosing the afternoon interval. If the incentive were a lottery ticket that had any positive probability, however small, of paying a penny, you should still choose the morning interval. You apparently prefer the afternoon interval to the morning interval, but there is no finite amount by which you prefer it. There is something of the snake eating its own tail in all of this. For the initial reasoning that concluded that the two intervals are exactly on a par was based on a consideration of expected utilities. But this is undercut by the second round of reasoning, whichever way we run it, and it is also essentially a consideration of expected utilities. Expected utility reasoning seems to conflict with itself, and is thus called into question. This seems absurd. I submit that it is the Avoid Certain Frustration and the Avoid Self-Undermining Choices Principles, innocent though they appeared, that have to be called into question. Sometimes it is rational to knowingly act against your rationallyformed future preferences, even when you know exactly how to avoid doing so. 3 3 I am grateful to Paul Bartha, Adam Elga, Andy Egan, Jim Joyce, Brad Monton, Harris Nover, Neil Thomason, Bas van Fraassen, Manuel Vargas, and especially to James Chase (who suggested a close relative of the first argument for preferring the afternoon interval), Chris Hitchcock, Marc Lange, and Peter Vranas for very useful comments.

9 REFERENCES Arntzenius, Frank and David McCarthy. 1997. The Two Envelope Paradox and Infinite expectations. Analysis, Vol. 57, No. 1: 42-50. Chalmers, David. 2002. The St. Petersburg Two-Envelope Paradox, Analysis 62:155-57, van Fraassen, Bas. 1984. Belief and the Will, Journal of Philosophy 81: 235-256 van Fraassen, Bas. 1995, Belief and the Problem of Ulysses and the Sirens, Philosophical Studies 77: 7-37 MATTHIAS: THERE IS A TIME WHEN YOU LL WANT TO SELL THE BET EVENTHOUGH THE DUTCH BOOKIE CAN T TELL YOU INADVANCE. INFINITELY MANY POISED TO STRIKE? BUT THEN THEY KNOW MORE THAN YOU!