More is Better. an investigation of monotonicity assumption in economics. Joohyun Shon. August 2008

Similar documents
Preferences. M. Utku Ünver Micro Theory. Boston College. M. Utku Ünver Micro Theory (BC) Preferences 1 / 20

Price Elasticity of Supply; Consumer Preferences

Walrasian Demand. u(x) where B(p, w) = {x R n + : p x w}.

Advanced Microeconomics

On Lexicographic (Dictionary) Preference

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Chapter 4 Online Appendix: The Mathematics of Utility Functions

Lecture Note 7: Revealed Preference and Consumer Welfare

Economics 2020a / HBS 4010 / HKS API-111 FALL 2010 Solutions to Practice Problems for Lectures 1 to 4

Lecture 2: Consumer Theory

Economics 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics Problem Set 2 1/20/10

Name. Final Exam, Economics 210A, December 2011 Here are some remarks to help you with answering the questions.

Tastes and Indifference Curves

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Economic Analysis for Business Decisions (EWMBA 201A)

Definition and Properties of the Production Function: Lecture

CHAPTER 3 CONSUMER BEHAVIOR

Introductory Notes on Demand Theory

Tastes and Indifference Curves

Constrained Optimisation

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

No: Bilkent University. Monotonic Extension. Farhad Husseinov. Discussion Papers. Department of Economics

Conditions for Efficiency in Package Pricing

1. Briefly explain what an indifference curve is and how it can be graphically derived.

Auctioning Keywords in Online Search

Consumer Theory. The consumer s problem

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

c 2008 Je rey A. Miron We have described the constraints that a consumer faces, i.e., discussed the budget constraint.

Managerial Economics Prof. Trupti Mishra S.J.M. School of Management Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay. Lecture - 13 Consumer Behaviour (Contd )

The fundamental question in economics is 2. Consumer Preferences

Chapter 3 Consumer Behavior

AK 4 SLUTSKY COMPENSATION

2. Information Economics

Problem Set #5-Key. Economics 305-Intermediate Microeconomic Theory

CITY AND REGIONAL PLANNING Consumer Behavior. Philip A. Viton. March 4, Introduction 2

Working Paper Series

Economics 200B Part 1 UCSD Winter 2015 Prof. R. Starr, Mr. John Rehbeck Final Exam 1

CHAPTER 4 Consumer Choice

DEMAND FORECASTING. Demand. Law of Demand. Definition of Law of Demand

0.0.2 Pareto Efficiency (Sec. 4, Ch. 1 of text)

Lecture Notes Intermediate Microeconomics. Xu Hu Department of Economics, Texas A&M University

Cost Minimization and the Cost Function

Investigación Operativa. The uniform rule in the division problem

Advanced International Economics Prof. Yamin Ahmad ECON 758

POTENTIAL OUTPUT and LONG RUN AGGREGATE SUPPLY

Notes V General Equilibrium: Positive Theory. 1 Walrasian Equilibrium and Excess Demand

Chapter 7. Sealed-bid Auctions

Practical Guide to the Simplex Method of Linear Programming

Constrained optimization.

Choice under Uncertainty

Practice Problem Set 2 (ANSWERS)

Gains from Trade. Christopher P. Chambers and Takashi Hayashi. March 25, Abstract

Economics of Insurance

Labor Demand The Labor Market

Sensitivity Analysis 3.1 AN EXAMPLE FOR ANALYSIS

UCLA. Department of Economics Ph. D. Preliminary Exam Micro-Economic Theory

Competitive Screening in Credit Markets with Adverse Selection: A Cover Version of Bester s Model

IBM Research Report. A Pricing Problem under Monge Property

3. Mathematical Induction

88 CHAPTER 2. VECTOR FUNCTIONS. . First, we need to compute T (s). a By definition, r (s) T (s) = 1 a sin s a. sin s a, cos s a

Synthetic Projective Treatment of Cevian Nests and Graves Triangles

Math 55: Discrete Mathematics

Inflation. Chapter Money Supply and Demand

ANSWER KEY 3 UTILITY FUNCTIONS, THE CONSUMER S PROBLEM, DEMAND CURVES

INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY

Properties of Real Numbers

PART II THEORY OF CONSUMER BEHAVIOR AND DEMAND

Empirical Applying Of Mutual Funds

The Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic

15 Kuhn -Tucker conditions

Economics 2020a / HBS 4010 / HKS API-111 Fall 2011 Practice Problems for Lectures 1 to 11

Linear Programming Notes V Problem Transformations

Convex Rationing Solutions (Incomplete Version, Do not distribute)

Arguments and Dialogues

A Portfolio Model of Insurance Demand. April Kalamazoo, MI East Lansing, MI 48824

Lecture 11 Uncertainty

Multi-variable Calculus and Optimization

U = x x x 1 4. What are the equilibrium relative prices of the three goods? traders has members who are best off?

Duality in Linear Programming

Homework #5: Answers. b. How can land rents as well as total wages be shown in such a diagram?

Duality of linear conic problems

1 Solving LPs: The Simplex Algorithm of George Dantzig

Consumer Theory: The Mathematical Core

MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 6.436J/15.085J Fall 2008 Lecture 5 9/17/2008 RANDOM VARIABLES

Microeconomics Sept. 16, 2010 NOTES ON CALCULUS AND UTILITY FUNCTIONS

Common sense, and the model that we have used, suggest that an increase in p means a decrease in demand, but this is not the only possibility.

So let us begin our quest to find the holy grail of real analysis.

Understanding the Slutsky Decomposition: Substitution & Income Effect

Economics 100A. Final Exam

or, put slightly differently, the profit maximizing condition is for marginal revenue to equal marginal cost:

Notes on Complexity Theory Last updated: August, Lecture 1

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 15: Repeated Games and Cooperation

1 if 1 x 0 1 if 0 x 1

Tiers, Preference Similarity, and the Limits on Stable Partners

Example 1. Consider the following two portfolios: 2. Buy one c(s(t), 20, τ, r) and sell one c(s(t), 10, τ, r).

Deriving Demand Functions - Examples 1

Set Theory Basic Concepts and Definitions

Adverse Selection and the Market for Health Insurance in the U.S. James Marton

The Role of Priorities in Assigning Indivisible Objects: A Characterization of Top Trading Cycles

a 11 x 1 + a 12 x a 1n x n = b 1 a 21 x 1 + a 22 x a 2n x n = b 2.

Microeconomics Topic 3: Understand how various factors shift supply or demand and understand the consequences for equilibrium price and quantity.

Transcription:

More is Better an investigation of monotonicity assumption in economics Joohyun Shon August 2008 Abstract Monotonicity of preference is assumed in the conventional economic theory to arrive at important conclusions such as more commodities are preferred to less. However, Gary Becker claims that monotonicity is not necessary for these conclusions in his book Economic Theory [1]. This paper investigates Becker s claim. 1 The Conventional Theory 1 Economists assume that economic agents (often referred to as the consumer in the context of utility maximization) attempt to maximize utility (which means satisfaction in vernacular). Definition 1.1. Let C denote a set of all possible spending arrangements. Consumption bundles, c, are elements of this set. Utility, U, can be representd as a function 2 from C to R. Definition 1.2. is a preference relation that denotes weak preference. If c 1 is weakly preferred to c 2 then c 1 c 2. In other words, U(c 1) U(c 2). is a preference relation that denotes strong preference. If c 1 is strongly preferred to c 2 then c 1 c 2. In other words, U(c 1) > U(c 2). Definition 1.3. is a preference relation that denotes indifference. If c 1 c 2 and c 1 c 2 are both true then the consumer is said to be indifferent. In other words, U(c 1) = U(c 2) With these definitions, one can now examine the so-called axioms of choice. Definition 1.4. Reflexibility For any bundle c i, c i c i 1 See Mas-Colell et al. [2] for more complete exposition of microeconomic theory. 2 There are many utility functions that are not continuous. I will only consider the continuous variety in this paper. 1

Definition 1.5. Completeness Given two bundles, one of the following is true: 1. c 1 c 2 2. c 1 c 2 3. c 1 c 2 Completeness implies that the consumer can judge between any two consumption bundles. Definition 1.6. Transitivity If c 1 c 2 and c 2 c 3 then c 1 c 3 Transitivity makes the completeness axiom applicable to any number of bundles. The consumer is said to be rational if his or her preference is transitive and complete. Definition 1.7. (Strict) Monotonicity 3 Suppose there are n commodities in both c 1 and c 2. Monotonicity means that if c 1 contains more of some or all commodities, but no less of any, than c 2 (c 1 c 2) then c 1 c 2. Strict monotonicity means that if c 1 contains more of each commodity than c 2 (c 1 > c 2) then c 1 c 2 Now let us consider the consequences that arise from monotonicity of preference. Definition 1.8. A function U is non-decreasing if c 1 c 2 implies U(c 1) U(c 2). A non-increasing utility function is defined similarly. A function U is strictly increasing if c 1 > c 2 implies U(c 1) > U(c 2). A strictly decreasing utility function is defined similarly. Theorem 1.1. Preferences are monotone if and only if U is non-decreasing and they are strictly monotone if and only if U is strictly increasing. Proof. First, we prove that the preference relation can be represented by a utility function. Then it becomes obvious that preferences are monotone if and only if U is non-decreasing. Utility functions are real valued functions defined on C. Therefore for any c 1, c 2 C, either U(c 1) U(c 2) or U(c 1) U(c 2) is true (1). If a utility function represents the then (1) implies that c 1 c 2 or that c 1 c 2 (2). (2) is true because of completeness. We now extend this result to any c C. Suppose c 1 c 2 and c 2 c 3. If a utility function represents then U(c 1) U(c 2) and U(c 2) U(c 3). Therefore, U(c 1) U(c 3) which implies that c 1 c 3 (3). (3) is true because of transitivity. It has now been proven that the preference relation can be represented by a utility function (and also that the consumer needs to be rational for the said representation to happen). The second part of the theorem is proven similarly. It is now clear that the monotonicity assumption implies that the consumer derives more pleasure from consuming more commodities (or more precisely, the consumer would not be saddened by the prospect of consuming a greater quantity of commodities). Consider constraints 3 A more general assumption of nonsatiation can be made in lieu of the monotonicity assumption it is essentially monotonicity defined in the language of limits. There always exists some bundle preferred to the bundle being consumed which may or may not be affordable. 2

the consumer would face when he or she attempts to maximize his or her utility. Expressed mathematically, the utility maximization problem is: max U = U(x x 1,...,x 1,..., x n) s.t. I n pixi where pi is the price of the n ith commodity, x i, and I is the consumer s income 4. If there were no constraints, the consumer would continue to consume more commodities because of monotonicity. And because of monotonicity, the solution to the utility maximization problem ends up at the boundary of the opportunity set (I = n pixi). In other words, the consumer would fully spend his or her income (whilst the consumer would still prefer to consume beyond his or her income). Definition 1.9. An indifference curve is the collection of all bundles of same utility; in other words, U(x 1,..., x n) = Ū. Where Ū is some fixed utility. The more technical, and therefore less interesting, consequence of monotonicity assumption is that the indifference curves cannot intersect. Theorem 1.2. Indifference curves cannot intersect. Proof. Consider two indifference curves, I 1 and I 2 Suppose the said indifference curves intersect and let c 1 be the bundle at the intersection, c 2 the bundle on I 1 and c 3 the bundle on I 2. Since c 2 and c 3 are on different indifference curves, U(c 2) > U(c 3) or U(c 2) < U(c 3) is true. In turn, either c 2 c 3 or c 2 c 3 is true. At the same time, c 2 is on the same indifference curve with c 1 and c 3 on the same curve with c 1. That is, c 1 c 2 and c 1 c 3. Since the preference relation is assumed to be monotone c 1 c 2 and c 1 c 3 cannot hold simultaneously contradiction. This concludes the very brief discussion of conventional economic theory. Armed with the knowledge of conventional theory, we can now investigate Becker s claim. 4 The utility maximization problem can therefore be solved using constrained optimization methods such as the Lagrangian method. 3

2 Becker s Claim In Economic Theory, Gary Becker claims that monotonicity is implied by the theory. Indeed, he only lists economic rationality as the necessary assumption for the mathematical treatment of utility maximization. Becker proves by contradiction why more is preferred to less. 5 If less of any good were preferred to more, and if the good had a non-negative price, a consumer would increase his utility by reducing his demand for that good until he either consumed none of it or preferred more to less. If a consumer were satiated indifferent between more and less of all goods and if work were irksome, he would reduce his hours worked and thus his income until either his income (or at least his earnings) vanished or he preferred more of some goods to less; he would then consume only these goods in positive quantities. It is this sense that utility theory implies that more is preferred to less of all goods actually consumed. Essentially Becker is not considering the consumer s income as given but as the consequence of his or her labor. Therefore the Beckerian utility maximization problem can be stated as: max U = U(x x 1,...,x 1,..., x n) n s.t. n pixi I = Y + w t, t + l = T where Y is non-earned income, w hourly wage, t hours worked, l leisure (hours spent not working) and T total time endowment. 6 In this model, it is clear that the consumer would always operate on the boundary of his or her opportunity set. If an interior bundle is preferred then the consumer would decrease the hours spent working thereby causing the line n pixi = I = Y + wt to move towards the origin until it touches the desired bundle. Another point needs to be discussed. We saw that indifference curves do not intersect because of the monotonicity assumption does the initial exclusion of monotonicity allow for the possibility of intersecting indifference curves? This is a very important question. If indifference curves can cross then the utility function does not accurately represent the consumer s preference the consumer cannot compare different bundles of commodities. 5 Note even if the consumer decides to save some of his or her income, the solution to his or her utility maximization problem will still be on the boundary if the savings are defined to be a commodity. Also consider the commodities that the sane would actually prefer less to more (say, deadly poison) defining a commodity to be lack of that commodity would ensure the boundary solution. 6 Becker s proof is merely the interpretation of the Beckerian utility maximization problem s first order conditions. 4

Theorem 2.1. Indifference curves cannot intersect (even without the monotonicity assumption). Proof. Consider two indifference curves, I 1 and I 2. Suppose the said indifference curves intersect and let c 1 be the bundle at the intersection, c 2 the bundle on I 1 and c 3 the bundle on I 2. Since c 2 and c 3 are on different indifference curves, U(c 2) > U(c 3) or U(c 2) < U(c 3) is true. In turn, either c 2 c 3 or c 2 c 3 is true. c 1 is on the same indifference curve with c 2 and with c 3. c 1 c 2 and c 1 c 3 are both true and by transitivity c 2 c 3 a contradiction. 3 Conclusion In the conventional economic theory, the assumption of monotonicity leads to three implications: (1) more is better ; (2) the solution to the utility maximization problem lies on the boundary of the opportunity set; and (3) indifference curves cannot intersect. Becker s formulation of the utility maximization problem excludes monotonicity assumption. Even though monotonicity is never assumed, the three implications of the assumption can still be derived. The Beckerian theory is stronger mathematically as it arrives at the same conclusion with fewer assumptions. Also a case can be made that the Beckerian theory also mimics the real world more closely than the conventional variety since Becker defines income not as a mere constraint but as a function of work only those of us who are incredibly lucky can count income as given. 4 References [1] Becker, G. S.: Economic Theory, Transaction Publishers, New Brunswick, N.J., 2008. [2] Mas-Colell, A., Whinston, M. D., Green, J. R.: Microeconomic Theory, Oxford University Press, New York, N.Y., 1995. 5