Lost in Linguistics. A Guide to the Current Landscape in Linguistic Theory. Denis Delfitto



Similar documents
How To Interpret The Effects Of Scrambling

Extended Projections of Adjectives and Comparative Deletion

The Italian left periphery: A view from locality

Against Optional and Null Clitics. Right Dislocation vs. Marginalization *

UNIVERSITY COLLEGE LONDON EXAMINATION FOR INTERNAL STUDENTS

How the Right-Periphery Shapes the Left-Periphery Lessons from Italian

Appendix to Chapter 3 Clitics

Movement and Binding

University of London. For The Following Qualification:-

Do we need Structured Question Meanings? Two Approaches to Questions

CRITERIAL POSITIONS AND LEFT PERIPHERY IN ITALIAN: EVIDENCE FOR THE SYNTACTIC ENCODING OF CONTRASTIVE FOCUS * Giuliano Bocci University of Siena

Constraints in Phrase Structure Grammar

CAS LX 522 Syntax I Fall 2000 November 13, 2000 Paul Hagstrom Week 10: Movement Theory

The mysterious specific indefinite

How To Distinguish Between Extract From Extraposition From Extract

The compositional semantics of same

The Problem With Corrective Exchanges

Medical Writing - Compilation of Mitigators and Parties

AnInterval-Based Semantics for Degree Questions: Negative Islands and Their Obviation

Placement Test. It is designed to enable us to place you in a class at the right level for you.


Utrecht Linguistic Database. Computational Tools for Linguistic Data March 15, Rapid Application Development

Wh-in-Situ and the Spanish DP: Movement or No Movement? Lara Reglero and Emma Ticio. 1 Introduction. 2 Two Theories of Wh-in-Situ

Lesson 201: Use of il quale

Nominative-Dative Inversion and the Decline of Dutch

Linear Compression as a Trigger for Movement 1

2. SEMANTIC RELATIONS

Constituency. The basic units of sentence structure

How Much Structure Does the Left Periphery Need?

Lexical Competition: Round in English and Dutch

Cross-linguistic differences in the interpretation of sentences with more than one QP: German (Frey 1993) and Hungarian (É Kiss 1991)

ž Lexicalized Tree Adjoining Grammar (LTAG) associates at least one elementary tree with every lexical item.

Emphatic Multiple Negative Expressions in Dutch A by-product of the loss of Negative Concord

Non-nominal Which-Relatives

Experimental investigation of the exhaustivity of structural focus

Movement and ellipsis: An analysis of gapping

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 3: Covert Movement vs. Type Shifting 1

L130: Chapter 5d. Dr. Shannon Bischoff. Dr. Shannon Bischoff () L130: Chapter 5d 1 / 25

B&P: intonation is not a reliable test to distinguish focus and topic. LD elements can be contrastively

English Descriptive Grammar

Does Dutch A-Scrambling Involve Movement? Evidence from Antecedent Priming

Adjacency, PF, and extraposition

Reinforcers in Italian: DP-internal and Left Peripheral 1. Marco Nicolis Georgetown University

On the Interpretation of there in Existentials

Freedom of Word Order and Domains for Movement: A flexible syntax of Hungarian. Akadémiai Doktori Értekezés. Surányi Balázs

What s in an island? HANS VAN DE KOOT & ERIC MATHIEU. Abstract. 1 Introduction

Superiority: Syntax or Semantics? Düsseldorf Jul02. Jill devilliers, Tom Roeper, Jürgen Weissenborn Smith,Umass,Potsdam

Identificational Focus revisited: The issue of exhaustivity (Paper presented at CLS 50) Katalin É. Kiss Lilla Pintér

Doubling constructions in first language acquisition

The impact of embedded pronouns on children's relative clause comprehension in Italian

Ling 201 Syntax 1. Jirka Hana April 10, 2006

Approximative of zo as a diagnostic tool

The structure of the English Sentence

On Dutch allemaal and West Ulster English all

Basic Notions of Information Structure *

KET SELF PLACEMENT TEST

A Comparative Analysis of Standard American English and British English. with respect to the Auxiliary Verbs

Language as Cognitive Science

Hadn t he been there before?

Pronouns: A case of production-before-comprehension

No Such Thing As Defective Intervention

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA SANTA CRUZ STRUCTURAL MARKEDNESS AND SYNTACTIC STRUCTURE: A STUDY OF WORD ORDER AND THE LEFT PERIPHERY IN MEXICAN SPANISH

[A Dutch version of this paper appeared in Nederlandse Taalkunde 13, , pp The English version was written in Spring 2009]

Summer Session III. Classes begin 6/27. Travel from 7/3-7/25/2013

How To Understand The Role Of Connectives In Utterance Interpretation

The syntax of focus negation

CARLA CONTEMORI Curriculum Vitae January 2010

REPORTED SPEECH. Reported speech is used to retell or report what other person has actually said. It is a very usual function in everyday language.

COMPARATIVES WITHOUT DEGREES: A NEW APPROACH. FRIEDERIKE MOLTMANN IHPST, Paris fmoltmann@univ-paris1.fr

It s a small word. Johan Rooryck & Guido Vanden Wyngaerd HIL Leiden/FWO - KUBrussel. 1. Introduction *

or conventional implicature [1]. If the implication is only pragmatic, explicating logical truth, and, thus, also consequence and inconsistency.

CS4025: Pragmatics. Resolving referring Expressions Interpreting intention in dialogue Conversational Implicature

Kangourou Italia - British Institutes Gara del 2 marzo 2010 Categoria Wallaby Per studenti della classe terza della Scuola Secondaria di Primo Grado

Grammar units I. He is coming out of the building over there. heard about it. He s is disagreeing with you in the politest way possible.

Errata: Carnie (2008) Constituent Structure. Oxford University Press (MAY 2009) A NOTE OF EXPLANATION:

Sentence Semantics. General Linguistics Jennifer Spenader, February 2006 (Most slides: Petra Hendriks)

Phrase Structure Rules, Tree Rewriting, and other sources of Recursion Structure within the NP

Examining domain widening and NPI any 1 Ana Arregui University of Ottawa

Kangourou Italia Cambridge English Language Assessment Gara del 26 febbraio 2014

COURSE SYLLABUS ESU 561 ASPECTS OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE. Fall 2014

PÁZMÁNY PÉTER KATOLIKUS EGYETEM BÖLCSÉSZETTUDOMÁNYI KAR

IP PATTERNS OF MOVEMENTS IN VSO TYPOLOGY: THE CASE OF ARABIC

Notes on wh in situ in French * Ur Shlonsky. Université de Genève

Is there repair by ellipsis?

Double Genitives in English

19. Morphosyntax in L2A

A (Covert) Long Distance Anaphor in English

Assessing the discourse referential properties of weak definites

Estudios de lingüística inglesa aplicada

Using a Dictionary for Help with GERUNDS and INFINITIVES

Consequences of Antisymmetry for the syntax of headed relative clauses (dissertation abstract)

Intonation and information structure (part II)

Year 9. European Studies Home Learning Booklet

Wallaby Choose the correct answer (Scegli la risposta giusta)

Weak and strong reflexives in Dutch

LICEO C. SIGONIO MODENA TEST D INGRESSO LINGUA INGLESE PER ESERCITAZIONI IN PREPARAZIONE AL PLACEMENT TEST ENGLISH PLACEMENT TEST

Dante Alighieri Society of Massachusetts Progetto Lingua Italiana Dante Alighieri - PLIDA 101

Introduction: Presuppositions in Context Theoretical Issues and Experimental Perspectives

Syntactic and Semantic Differences between Nominal Relative Clauses and Dependent wh-interrogative Clauses

CORSO DI LINGUA INGLESE Beginners Tursi. Corso di lingua inglese a cura della Prof.ssa Luisa PONTILLO

Transcription:

Lost in Linguistics. A Guide to the Current Landscape in Linguistic Theory Oslo October 10-14 Denis Delfitto Grammar/Discourse Interface: Cartographic and Non-cartographic Approaches Introduction The main issue: How are Topic and Focus grammatically represented? A. Cartographic approach: Topic and Focus are grammatical notions encoded in the Left-Periphery by dedicated positions Constituents are marked by dedicated corresponding features B. Non-cartographic approach: Topic and Focus are IS notions Topic and Focus are identified by the interpretive systems by means of specific Mapping Rules Section 1: Focus as a PF-phenomenon (Reinhart 2006) A more minimal and realistic assumption is that the focus constituent is coded at PF, as essentially assumed in Chomsky (1971). Since main stress is a requirement of the computational system (a derivation cannot be pronounced without main stress) an optimal language system would make use of this visible property of derivations to code information needed at the interface. What is needed on the view that focus is coded at PF, is a rule or definition that tells Inference and Context how to identify the focus unit, based on intonation. Cinque's generalization: (1) The focus of IP is a(ny) constituent containing the main stress of IP, as determined by the stress-rule (2) Focus set: The focus set of a derivation D comprises all and only subtrees (constituents) which contain the main stress of D. (3) a) [IP Subject [VP V Object]] b) [IP Subject [VP Object V]] c) Focus set: {IP, VP, Object} in actual use, any of the members of the set in (iiic) can serve as focus. At the interface, one member of the focus set is selected, as the actual focus of the sentence.

Example: (4a) - generated with stress on the object - can be used as an answer in any of the contexts in (4b-d), with the F-bracketed constituent as focus. (4) a) My neighbor is building a desk b) Speaker A: What's this noise? Speaker B: [F My neighbor is building a desk] c) Speaker A: What's your neighbor doing these days? Speaker B: My neighbor [F is building a desk] d) Speaker A: What's your neighbor building? Speaker B: My neighbor is building [F a desk] Discourse conditions, rather than syntax, determine whether a derivation with a particular stress is appropriate in a given context. A derivation is inappropriate in context, if no member of its focus set can be used as an actual focus in that context. (4a), for example, cannot be used as answer in either of the contexts of (5). (# indicates inappropriateness to context) (5) a) Speaker A: Has your neighbor bought a desk already? Speaker B: #No, my neighbor is [F building] a desk. b) Speaker A: Who is building a desk? Speaker B: #[F My neighbor] is building a desk. In the contexts of (5), the F-bracketed constituents should be the foci, but are not in the focus set generated by (2) for a sentence in which the object bears stress. Repair strategy: Stress shift correct focus Complicating factor: interference of anaphoric distressing Reinhart: effects can be factored out. Section 2. The cartographic analysis of Topic and Focus (Rizzi 1997) (6) [CP Force (Topic*) Focus (Topic*) Fin [IP (7) Credo che, il tuo libro, lo apprezzerebbero molto I believe that your book, they would appreciate it a lot (7 ) *Credo, il tuo libro, che lo apprezzerebbero molto I believe, your book, that they would appreciate it a lot (8) *Credo di, il tuo libro, apprezzarlo molto (8 ) Credo, il tuo libro, di apprezzarlo molto (9) *A chi, il premio Nobel, lo daranno? To whom, the Nobel Prize, will they give it? (9 ) Il premio Nobel, a chi lo daranno? The Nobel Prize, to whom will they give it? (10) Mi chiedo, il premio Nobel, a chi potrebbero darlo I wonder, the Nobel Prize, to whom they could give it (10 )?Mi chiedo a chi, il premio Nobel, potrebbero darlo I wonder to whom, the Nobel Prize, they could give it

(11) Qui c è un uomo al quale IL PREMIO NOBEL dovrebbero dare Here is a man to whom THE NOBEL PRIZE they should give (11 ) *A chi IL PREMIO NOBEL dovrebbero dare? To whom THE NOBEL PRIZE they should give? (12) Credo che QUESTO, a Giovanni, dovrebbero dire I believe that THIS, to John, they should say (12 ) Credo che a Giovanni QUESTO dovrebbero dire I believe that to John, THIS they should say (13) Topic vs. Focus: A. Gianni/*GIANNI sua madre l ha sempre apprezzato (weak crossover) Gianni his mother always praised him B. *Nessuno l ho visto / NESSUNO ho visto (bare quantifiers) Nobody I saw him C. *A GIANNI che cosa hai detto? A Gianni che cosa gli hai detto? (compatibility with wh) TO GIANNI what did you say? To Gianni what did you say? (14) Some issues left unresolved by the cartographic hypothesis in (1) A. Topic-positions have different properties crosslinguistically: English topicalization vs. Romance CLLD B. Why is the Topic-position recursive (above and below the Focus-position)? C. Why can Focus be fronted across an Aboutness or Familiar Topic but not across a Contrastive Topic? Section 3. Topic-structures as non-canonical predication structures (15) Topicalization as operator-movement in syntax a. *I said that that book to me Maxim gave (multiple topicalization) b.?*this book, to whom should I give? (intervention effects of wh on topic displacement) c.??the man to whom that book I gave (intervention effects of topics on wh-movement) d. *You know what in Scotland they eat e. *To whom did Lee think that, this present, Robert gave? (16) CLLD as operator-movement in semantics a. Marcello lo legge. Marcello reads it. b. [Top e] [λx (Marcello legge x)] c. Questo libro, Marcello lo legge. This book, Marcello reads it. d. [Top Questo libro] [λx (Marcello legge x)] (17) CLLD does not give rise to any intervention effect and is only constrained by strong islands. Strong islands as a constraint on scope-extension in the semantics: a. *Questo libro, non ho mai visto l uomo che Maria ha sposato prima di scriverlo

This book, I have never seen the man who Mary married before she wrote it Section 4. Topic recursion as multiple λ-abstraction on argument-positions (18) λxλy P (x,y ) (19) A: Lascerai la casa in campagna a tua sorella? (familiar topic) will you bequeath the country house to your sister? B: No, a mia sorella la casa in campagna non gliela lascerò mai No, to my sister the country house I will never bequeath it to her (20) A: Cosa intendi fare con l eredità? (contrastive topic: see also (39)-(40)below ) what will you do about the inheritance? B: Non lo so, ma a mia sorella la casa in campagna non gliela lascerò mai I don t know, but to my sister the country house I ll never bequeath it to her Section 4. Focus-movement as feature-driven movement (Horvath s Exhaustivity Operator) (21) Horvath 2010: In Hungarian, preposing a constituent to the alleged focus position involves a truth-conditional notion of exhaustivity, rather than a discourse notion of focus with a conversational implicature of exhaustivity. Focus-movement is triggered by a specific quantificational feature (exhaustivity) (22) Q: Who did they call up? a. They called up JOHN AND MARY. b. They called up JOHN. (23) In Hungarian (22b) is not a logical consequence of (22a) (24) Q: Who did they call up? SpeakerA: They called up JOHN. SpeakerB: Yes, and they also called up Mary #Not true. They also called up MARY (25) (24) holds in English. In Hungarian it s the other way around (26) a. Speaker A: Who did you meet yesterday? (Contrastive Focus in Italian) Speaker B: #MARY, I met b. Speaker A: I heard you met Anna Speaker B: No, MARY I met (27) The semantics of Information Focus in Rooth 1992 a. Presupposition: x (I invited x) b. Assertion: I invited Mary (28) A proposal for the semantics of Contrastive Focus as an Exhaustivity Operator a. Presupposition: I invited Anna b. Assertion: I invited Mary, and I did not invite Anna (29) A potential problem for Contrastive Focus as EO a. Speaker A: I heard you met Mary

Speaker B: No, LISA I met and actually, I also met Anna (30) A familiarity constraint on the comparison set to which EO applies a. Speaker A: Did you invite your friends Andrea, Carlo and Giorgio? Speaker B: No, GIOVANNI I invited Speaker C: That s not true! LUIGI you invited b. Speaker A: Did you invite your friends? (D-linking irrelevant) Speaker B: #No, CARLO ho invitato (31) Conclusion: In Italian the Exhaustivity-operator applies to a contextually relevant set of familiar objects, and excludes that the relevant property truly applies to these objects (32) What about Contrastive Focus in situ? a. Speaker A: I heard that you invited Andrea Speaker B: No, I invited CARLO b. Problem: The EO should trigger movement. We may assume remnant movement for CF in situ (cfr. Belletti 2004) (33) A number of interesting conclusions a. The prohibition on multiple Foci (as well as the incompatibility with wh-movement) derives from the quantificational nature of Contrastive Focus b. Information Focus is assigned by the Nuclear Stress Rule (cf. Reinhart 2006) c. Both in Hungarian and in Italian, exhaustivity is implicated with Information Focus and entailed with Contrastive Focus d. Contrastive Focus is not encoded at PF: The prosodic pattern found with CF extends to the contexts of stress-shift (in the sense of Reinhart 2006) e. A: Who invited Mary? B: MY NEIGHBOURS invited Mary Section 5. Grammar and Information Structure: Focus-Topic Interaction (34) a. TOPIC [COMMENT FOCUS [BACKGROUND... ]] b. *FOCUS [BACKGROUND... [ TOPIC [... ]]] (35) Neeleman s analysis of A -scrambling in Dutch: Movement triggers Contrast a. Ik geloof dat [ alleen DIT boek] Jan Marie t gegeven heeft I believe that only this book John Mary given has I believe that John has given only this book to Mary. b. Ik geloof dat [ zo n boek] alleen JAN Marie t gegeven heeft I believe that such-a book only John Mary given has I believe that only John has given such a book to Mary. (36) Neeleman s analysis of A -scrambling in Dutch: Focus across Topic A: Hoe zit het met het dressoir? Wie heeft grootvader dat nagelaten? How about the sideboard? To whom has granddad bequeathed that?

B: Nou, dat weet ik niet, maar ik geloof Well, I don t know, but I believe... a. dat grootpapa zijn buren de klok heeft willen nalaten that granddad his neighbours the clock has want bequeath b. # dat zijn buren grootpapa t de klok heeft willen nalaten. that his neighbours granddad the klok has want bequeath that granddad wanted to bequeath the clock to his neighbours. (37) Neeleman s analysis of A -scrambling in Dutch: Topic across Focus A: Hoe zit het met tante Jo? Wat heeft grootpapa haar nagelaten? How about auntie Jo? What has granddad bequeathed to her? B: Nou, dat weet ik niet, maar ik geloof Well, I don t know, but I believe... a. dat grootpapa zijn buren de klok heeft willen nalaten. that granddad his neighbours the clock has want bequeath b. dat [DP zijn buren] grootpapa t-dp de klok heeft willen nalaten that his neighbours granddad the clock has want bequeath that granddad wanted to bequeath the clock to his neighbours. (38) Neeleman s analysis of A -scrambling in Dutch: (topic cannot move below a displaced focus) A: Hoe zit het met de nietmachine? Wie heeft Jan daarom gevraagd? What about the stapler? Who has asked John for that? B: Nou, dat weet ik niet, maar... Well, I don t know, but... a. ik geloof dat PIET Jan om de liniaal heeft willen vragen. I believe that Peter John for the ruler has want ask b. # ik geloof dat PIET [PP om de liniaal] Jan t PP heeft willen vragen. I believe that Peter for the ruler John has want ask c. ik geloof dat [PP om de liniaal] PIET Jan t PP heeft willen vragen. I believe that for the ruler Peter John has want ask I believe that Peter has wanted to ask John for the ruler. (39) Fronted Focus and Contrastive Topic in Italian: The interface Condition (29) is confirmed! A. Che mi dici del comodino? A chi l ha lasciato il nonno? What about the bedside table? To whom did grandad bequeath it? B: Credo proprio che AI SUOI VICINI (non alla moglie!) il comodino il nonno l abbia lasciato I really believe that TO HIS NEIGHBOURS (not to his wife!) the bedside table granddad bequeathed it C: Non lo so, ma credo che l armadio il nonno l abbia lasciato AI SUOI VICINI I don t know, but I believe that the wardrobe granddad bequeathed it TO HIS NEIGHBOURS D: #Non lo so, ma credo che AI SUOI VICINI (non alla moglie!) l armadio il nonno l abbia lasciato I don t know, but I believe that TO HIS NEIGHBOURS (not to his wife!) the wardrobe granddad bequeathed it

(40) Multiple Contrastive Topics are admitted (modulo conflicts of NSR with destressing: Torregrossa 2011) A: Il nonno ha lasciato l orologio ai cugini? did granddad bequeath the clock to his cousins? B: Non lo so, ma ha lasciato la scacchiera ai fratelli I don t know, but he bequeathed the chessboard to his brothers C: Non lo so, ma la scacchiera, l ha lasciata ai fratelli I don t know, but the chessboard, he bequeathed it to his brothers D:?? Non lo so, ma ai fratelli, la scacchiera, gliel ha lasciata I don t know, but to his brother, the chessboard, he bequeathed it to them E: Non lo so, ma ai fratelli la scacchiera gliel ha venduta I don t know, but to his brothers the chessboard, he sold it to them F: Non lo so, ma ai fratelli la scacchiera non gliel ha lasciata I don t know, but to his brothers the chessboard, he didn t leave it to them G. Mario ha consegnato la bicicletta ai suoi clienti in officina? did Mario deliver the bike to his clients in the repair shop? H. Non lo so, ma ai suoi amici il motorino gliel ha consegnato nel garage I don t know, but to his friends the scooter he delivered it to them in the garage I. Non lo so, ma ai suoi amici il motorino non gliel ha consegnato in officina I don t know, but to his friends the scooter he didn t deliver it to them in the repair shop (41) Fronted Focus and Topic: A minimal pair A: Il nonno ha lasciato l orologio ai cugini? Did granddad bequeath the clock to his cousins? B: No, io credo che AI FRATELLI (non ai cugini!) l orologio il nonno l abbia lasciato No, I believe that TO HIS BROTHERS (not to his cousins!) the clock granddad bequeathed it C.??Non lo so, ma io credo che AI FRATELLI (non ai cugini!) la scacchiera il nonno l abbia lasciata I don t know, but I believe that TO HIS BROTHERS (not to his cousins!) the chessboard granddad bequeathed it Section 6. Focus-Topic Interaction: Comparing Theories (42) Focus can be moved over a familiar topic but not over a contrastive topic: (41B) vs (41C) (43) This follows both from Neeleman s proposal via (34) and from Frascarelli s cartographic proposal (by definition, in (6) the upper topic position is contrastive, and the lower topic position is familiar) (44) Focus movement to a higher clause across a contrastive topic makes the difference: it should be bad given (34) but it should be ok in the cartographic framework: (i) A. Che mi dici del libro di Tomasello? A chi l ha consigliato il professore? B. #Non lo so, ma AI SUOI STUDENTI io credo che il libro di Chomsky il professore l abbia consigliato

(45) This shows it cannot be a matter of position. It is rather a matter of feature-endowment and locality: a +Contr constituent A cannot cross over a +Contr constituent B (under Rizzi s Relativized Minimality) (46) The semantics of Contrast: If a constituent A is marked as +Contr, then the semantic value of A ( = A*) must be part of a non-singleton set of familiar objects, to which A* belongs (cf. Pesetsky s D-linking) For Topic, this entails that the +Contr topicalized constituent involves a comparison set, whereas for Focus this entails that Contrastive Focus involves exhaustivity with respect to a familiar set (as opposed to logical exhaustivity in Hungarian Focus) (47) Why is the order Topic-Focus admitted in Italian (and in Dutch)? (i) A. Che mi dici del libro di Tomasello? A chi l ha consigliato il professore? B. Non lo so, ma il libro di Chomsky io credo proprio che AI SUOI STUDENTI il professore l abbia consigliato For Italian, the topic is base-generated and there is then no RM effect. For Dutch, though the problem is compounded by the fact that topic-movement is A -scrambling, a solution might be empty-operator movement (modeled on the classical analysis of English topicalization), whereby the operator is devoid of the +Contr feature. (48) The alternative is a non-cartographic approach based on (34). SELECTED REFERENCES Belletti, A. (2004). Aspects of the low IP area. In The Structure of CP and IP. The Cartography of Syntactic Structures, Volume 2, ed. L. Rizzi, 16-51. New York: Oxford University Press. Büring, D. (1997). The Meaning of Topic and Focus. London: Routledge. Chomsky, N. (1977). On Wh-Movement. In: Culicover, P.W.; Wasow, T.; Akmajian, A. (eds.). Formal Syntax. New York: Academic Press, p. 71-132. Cinque, G. (1990). Types of A -Dependencies. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Culicover, P. (1991). Topicalization, inversion, and complementizers in English. OTS Working Papers. Utrecht University. Culicover, P. (1996). On Distinguishing A -Movements. Linguistic Inquiry 27: 445-463. Delfitto, D. (2002). On the semantics of pronominal clitics and some of its consequences. Catalan Journal of Linguistics, 1, 41-69. Frascarelli, M. and R. Hinterhölzl (2007). Types of topics in German and Italian, In: On information structure, meaning and form, Schwabe, K. and S. Winkler (eds.), 87 116. Horvath, J. (2010). Discourse features, syntactic displacement and the status of contrast. Lingua 120, 1346-1369. Kiss, K, É. (1998). Identificational focus versus information focus. Language 74: 245-273. Lambrecht, K. (1994). Information Structure and Sentence Form. Cambridge: CUP. Neeleman, A., E. Titov, H. van de Koot & R. Vermeulen (2011). A syntactic typology of Topic, Focus and Contrast. Ms., UCL Reinhart, T. (2006). Interface strategies: Optimal and costly computations. Cambridge. MIT Press. Rizzi, L. (1997). The fine structure of the left periphery. In: Elements of grammar: A handbook of generative syntax, ed. by Liliane Haegeman, 281 337. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Rooth, M. (1992). A Theory of Focus Interpretation. Natural Language Semantics, 1(1):75 116, 1992.

Schwarzschild, R. (1999). Givenness, AvoidF and other constraints on the placement of accents. Natural Language Semantics 7: 41 177. Slioussar, N. (2007). Grammar and information structure. A study with reference to Russian. Utrecht: LOT Publications. Torregrossa, J. (2011). Towards a semantics of contrast. Ms., University of Verona