Extended liability for environmental accidents: what you see is what you get

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Extended liability for environmental accidents: what you see is what you get"

Transcription

1 Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) Extended liability for environmental accidents: what you see is what you get Emma Hutchinson and Klaas van t Veld Department of Economics, University of Michigan, 611 Tappan St., Ann Arbor, MI , USA Received 18 July 2002; received in revised form 24 July 2003 Available online 7 July 2004 Abstract When a firm may be bankrupted by the liability from an environmental accident, current laws often allow for the extension of liability to third parties with whom the firm contracts, with the aim of inducing full internalization of social costs. We find that, when the firm can take both observable and unobservable care to reduce expected accident damages, extended liability indeed results in full cost internalization, but not in first-best levels of care. We also find that, whereas without extended liability there is excess entry into environmentally hazardous industries, introducing extended liability leads to exit that, while excessive relative to the first best, is second-best optimal given firms choice of care. Furthermore, we show that direct regulation of observable care, when combined with extended liability, further distorts firms incentives. However, when used alone, such regulation strictly dominates extended liability. r 2004 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. Keywords: Environmental risk; Judgment proof problem; Extended liability; Lender liability; Industrial accidents; Bankruptcy; CERCLA 1. Introduction Under many of the major US environmental laws e.g., the Comprehensive Environmental Response, Compensation, and Liability Act (CERCLA), the Oil Pollution Act, the Clean Water Corresponding author. Fax: address: ehutchin@umich.edu (E. Hutchinson) /$ - see front matter r 2004 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. doi: /j.jeem

2 158 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) Act firms face strict liability for damages from environmental accidents. From the law-andeconomics literature (e.g., [30]), it is well known that such ex post liability can provide firms with optimal incentives ex ante to take care i.e., to undertake safety measures that reduce expected damages because it induces firms to internalize the full costs associated with accidents. Because environmental cleanups are often very costly, however, it is not uncommon for environmental damages to exceed the market value of the firm responsible for an accident. In such cases, the firm is bankrupted by its liability, and is said to be judgment proof : because it cannot lose more than its market value in bankruptcy, it externalizes any residual damages in excess of this value. One way in which environmental laws attempt to remedy this judgment proof problem is by extending liability for residual damages to parties with whom a firm contracts. The argument for doing so (laid out for example by Segerson [28]) is that, using their contractual leverage, third parties will pass on their residual-liability costs to the judgment-proof firm, thereby restoring the firm s incentive to take optimal care. Formal analysis of this argument has shown that the degree to which it holds up in practice depends importantly on whether safety measures undertaken by the firm are observable to third parties ([6,7,9,15,18,22,23,25]). A standard assumption in the literature is that care is unobservable to third parties. 1 Equally standard and closely related is the assumption that care takes the form of safety measures that reduce the probability of an accident occurring. Because such care tends to be of a procedural nature for example, making sure that workers follow standard safety procedures it is reasonable to assume that it is difficult for third parties to observe. In reality, of course, firms can take measures to reduce not just the probability of an accident, but also the extent of damages if an accident occurs. Moreover, such damage-reducing measures tend to take the form of tangible investments, which are readily observable to third parties. In the oil-shipping business, for example, proper training and supervision of crews reduces the probability of tanker groundings or collisions, but is difficult to observe. On the other hand, fitting double hulls to oil tankers reduces the extent of oil spills in the event of an accident, and is readily observable. Similarly, in the hazardous-waste disposal business, day-to-day enforcement of procedures ensuring that hazardous waste is stored correctly reduces the probability of leaks, but is difficult to observe. On the other hand, installing monitoring wells reduces the extent of leaks (by enabling early intervention) and is readily observable. In this paper, we allow for both probability- and damage-reducing safety measures. In addition, we assume that damage-reducing measures are observable to third parties, while probabilityreducing measures are not. Sections 2 and 3 introduce the model and determine the socially optimal levels of care. Section 4 analyzes firms equilibrium choices of care in the absence of extended liability. Section 5 analyzes the effects of a specific form of extended liability, namely lender liability. 2 Section 6 discusses direct regulation of damage-reducing care as a possible complement to, or substitute for, extended liability. Section 7 concludes. 1 An interesting exception is Boyd and Ingberman [8], who abstract from the moral-hazard distortions that can result from care being unobservable to focus on a different issue, namely under what circumstances firms choose to dissolve rather than face their accident liability. 2 Much of the literature on extended liability (e.g., [9,18,25]) has focused on the specific example of lender liability. See [10] for an overview of the history of lender liability under CERCLA. See also [14] for a discussion of proposals to introduce lender liability in the European Union.

3 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) The model The representative firm in our model is considering engaging in an activity that carries with it a risk of a costly environmental accident. The activity generates fixed profits P, defined as revenues net of non-accident-related variable costs. An accident occurs with probability p and causes damages D. The firm faces strict liability for all accident damages, but this liability is limited by the firm s financial assets. If accident damages exceed these assets, then the firm will be bankrupted, and will therefore externalize some of the damages. The firm can reduce p by incurring non-pecuniary costs cð pþ, and it can reduce D by undertaking investments that involve up-front capital costs of IðDÞ. 3 The function cð pþ has the following properties: (i) cð pþ ¼0 at p ¼ p, (ii) c 0 ð pþo 0; c 00 ð pþ4 0; 8p 2ð0; pþ, and (iii) cð pþ!1 as p! 0. Similarly, the function IðDÞ has properties (i) IðDÞ ¼0atD ¼ D, (ii) I 0 ðdþo 0; I 00 ðdþ4 0; 8D 2ð0; DÞ, and (iii) IðDÞ!1as D! 0. To start up the activity, the firm must incur up-front capital costs of K in addition to IðDÞ. We assume that the firm has no initial wealth and therefore has to borrow to cover all up-front costs. We assume that the lending sector is competitive and that L1 : the lender s loan is secured, with the firm s assets as collateral, L2 : the firm s assets are not damaged or otherwise diminished in value if an accident occurs. Assumption L1 implies that if a bankrupting accident occurs, the lender will have first claim on the firm s assets, before any claims by accident victims. Assumption L2 implies that after repossessing the assets, the lender can in principle re-lend them to a new firm under the same terms as before. 4 We further assume that the firm s probability-reducing effort is not observable to (or verifiable by) the lender or any other outside parties, including the regulator, but its damage-reducing investment is. Hence, we use unobservable care and observable care as short-hand terms. 3. The social planner s problem In this section, we consider the social planner s problem, which is to choose the accident damage level D and the accident probability p that maximize welfare. To keep the welfare analysis simple, we assume that the firm s activity generates no consumer surplus. The welfare generated by the firm is then W p ½cð pþþriðdþþpdš; ð1þ where p P rk represents the firm s profits P less the opportunity cost rk to society from having productive capital K tied up in the firm for the period of the firm s operation. Throughout the paper we refer to p as the firm s gross profits (i.e., gross of any accident-related costs). The bracketed term on the right-hand side of (1) captures the social costs related to the possibility of 3 We define probability-reducing care costs as non-pecuniary because this is the standard assumption in much of the literature. In a working paper, we show that our results go through also if all care costs are pecuniary. 4 Allowing for damages to capital significantly complicates the analysis, but does not materially affect our results.

4 160 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) environmental accidents: the non-pecuniary cost of unobservable care cð pþ, the opportunity cost of investments in observable care riðdþ, and expected accident damages pd. Assuming that a unique interior solution to the social planner s problem exists, it will be characterized by the following first-order conditions: ri 0 ðdþ p ¼ 0; ð2þ c 0 ð pþ D ¼ 0: ð3þ The first condition equates the marginal costs ri 0 ðdþ of damage-reducing care to the marginal social benefit p. The second condition equates the marginal cost c 0 ð pþ of probability-reducing care to the marginal social benefit D. Fig. 1. Marginal costs ri 0 ðdþ of reducing accident damages and (inverse) marginal costs c 0 1 ðdþ zðdþ of reducing the accident probability.

5 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) For reasons of exposition, we define a function zðþ that is equal to the inverse of the function c 0 ðþ wherever this inverse exists (i.e., for po p), and equal to p otherwise. Condition (3) can then be rewritten as p ¼ zðdþ. As shown in Fig. 1, defining the zðþ function allows us to represent the social optimum ðd S ; p S Þ graphically in ðd; pþ space as the point where the ri 0 ðdþ and zðdþ curves cross. Also shown in the figure are two further critical values of D and p, namely D, which is the damage level that would be socially optimal if probability-reducing care were zero, and p, which is the probability that would be socially optimal if damage-reducing care were zero. Additionally, we define a critical value of p, namely p S cðp S ÞþrIðD S Þþp S D S, to denote the level of net benefits that just equals minimized accident-related costs. Clearly, firms with p less than p S will not be in business at the social optimum, as they would generate negative social welfare. For firms with p greater than p S, social welfare is positive and given by Eq. (1) evaluated at ðd S ; p S Þ. 4. The firm s problem without extended liability The firm s problem differs from the social planner s in two respects. First, whereas the social planner takes into account all damages associated with environmental accidents, the firm only takes into account those damages for which it can be held liable. Second, the firm must borrow capital, in return for a loan fee that allows the lender to at least break even in expectation. By assumption, the lender can observe the firm s investment in damage reduction, so that the terms of the loan contract can be conditioned on D. In contrast, the lender cannot observe the firm s expenditure on probability reduction, so that the loan contract cannot be conditioned on p. As illustrated in Fig. 2, we capture these observability assumptions by modeling the firm s and the lender s decisions as a three-stage game, which is solved by backwards induction. In stage 1, the firm chooses the level of damages D. In stage 2, lenders observe D and the loan fee is determined competitively. In stage 3, the firm chooses the accident probability p conditional on its earlier choice of D and the now contractually fixed loan fee. In both stages 1 and 3, the firm s objective is to maximize its payoff V ¼ p maxfðp DÞ; 0gþð1 pþðp Þ cð pþ: ð4þ With probability p the firm experiences an accident, and, after paying the lender, has financial assets of P with which to compensate accidents victims. 5 A solvent firm, whose assets exceed damages, is therefore left with P D in the event of an accident, while a judgment-proof firm is left with nothing. With probability ð1 pþ there is no accident, and the firm is then left with P. Irrespective of whether or not an accident occurs, the firm must incur the non-pecuniary care costs cð pþ. Given our assumptions of a competitive lending sector, the equilibrium loan fee is given by the break-even condition r½k þ IðDÞŠ ¼ 0: ð5þ 5 Recall that by Assumption L1 the lender has first claim on the firm s assets.

6 162 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) Fig. 2. Timeline of the model. Note that Assumptions L1 and L2 imply that the lender can repossess the firm s assets in order to recover the principal of the loan. Moreover, the lender does not incur any loss in the event of an accident. As a result, the loan fee need only cover the opportunity cost r½k þ IðDÞŠ of the loan, and does not depend on the firm s subsequent choice of accident probability. This in turn implies that, in the absence of extended liability, our assumption that p is unobservable to the lender is immaterial. We find that the solution to the firm s optimization problem in the absence of extended liability can be characterized as follows: Proposition 1. Without extended liability, the only locally optimal D and p values are (a) D S and p S for firms that are solvent at that combination, (b) D and p ¼ zðpþ for firms that are judgment proof at that combination. Proof. All proofs are given in Appendix A. & At ðd; pþ combinations where a firm is solvent, the firm fully internalizes all accident-related costs. As a result, only ðd S ; p S Þ can be optimal. At ðd; pþ combinations where a firm is judgment proof, it externalizes all damages in excess of its financial assets P ¼ p riðdþ. Because of this, there is no marginal benefit to reducing damages below D. Conditional on this damage level, the social planner would choose p ¼ zð DÞ, where the marginal cost c 0 ðpþ of further reductions in p just balances the social marginal benefit D. For the judgment-proof firm, however, the private marginal benefit of reducing p is only p rið DÞ ¼po D. As a result, it will choose a higher privately optimal accident probability p ¼ zðpþ. The result of Proposition 1 is only partial, in that it does not establish whether any given firm is in fact solvent at ðd S ; p S Þ or judgment proof at ð D; zðpþþ, or possibly both. Nor does the proposition establish how zðpþ compares to the socially optimal accident probability p S. In the Appendix, we establish formally the rather obvious fact that firms with low gross profits below a cutoff value that we denote p N are judgment proof in equilibrium, whereas firms with gross profits above p N are solvent. We show also, however, that, when accident damages are endogenous, the state of being judgment proof becomes for some firms namely those with intermediate profits endogenous as well: such firms can choose whether or not to keep damages at a level exceeding their financial assets. Moreover, some judgment-proof firms compensate for taking no damage-reducing care by taking more probability-reducing care than they would at the first best. 6 6 Beard [1], Craig and Thiel [12], Posey [26], and Dionne and Spaeter [13] also find that judgment-proof firms may take more than first-best probability-reducing care. In their models, this possibility arises for very different reasons, however, which moreover depend on treating care as pecuniary. A note expanding on this point is available from the authors upon request.

7 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) The latter result is illustrated in Fig. 1, which shows in ðd; pþ space the situation of two judgment-proof firms, a relatively rich one with gross profits p r and a relatively poor one with gross profits p p. Being judgment proof, both firms choose damage level D. However, because the rich firm has financial assets p r at stake that exceed D S, it has a greater incentive to avoid accidents than does the social planner, and so chooses an accident probability lower than p S. 7 The opposite is true for the poor firm. More generally, the lower a judgment-proof firm s gross profits p, the higher the accident probability it chooses. In the extreme case, a firm that has zero gross profits chooses p, i.e., takes no unobservable care. Because it takes no observable care either, Eq. (4) reduces to V ¼ 0 for this firm. Thus, firms with gross profits px0 are viable (in the sense that they have a non-negative payoff ) in the absence of extended liability. Note, however, that some of these firms (those with po p S ) are viable only because they externalize damages Welfare without extended liability To evaluate the welfare loss resulting from the judgment-proof problem without extended liability, we compare the welfare generated by firms (as given by Eq. (1)) when they choose their privately optimal values of D and zðpþ to the welfare generated at the social optimum. Recall from Section 3 that firms with po p S would not be in business at the social optimum. It follows that the welfare loss resulting from these firms being in business in the absence of extended liability corresponds to the negative welfare they generate at ð D; zðpþþ. Richer judgment-proof firms, in contrast, would be in business at the social optimum. For these firms, the welfare loss is therefore just the deadweight loss resulting from their distorted care choices. Fig. 3 illustrates this deadweight loss for the judgment-proof firm with profits p ¼ p r from Fig. 1. At the social optimum, the firm s full accident-related costs are equal to cðp S Þþp S D S þ riðd S Þ. At its privately optimal choice of D and p N ¼ zðpþ, the firm s full accident-related costs (including the expected damages p N ð D pþ that it externalizes) are cðp N Þþp N D. The difference between these two costs corresponds to the shaded area in the figure labeled DWL N. To understand the somewhat odd shape of this area, consider the following thought experiment. Suppose that, while holding damages constant at D, we reduce the accident probability p from p N to its optimal value conditional on D, namely p ¼ zð DÞ. Doing so increases unobservable care costs by the area to the left of the zðdþ curve between p and p N, but reduces expected damages by the rectangle ðp N pþ D. Thus, the net welfare gain is equal to the triangle above the zðdþ curve. Suppose that we then reduce damages from D to D S, while keeping the accident probability at its conditionally optimal value p ¼ zðdþ. This increases costs by the area under the ri 0 ðdþ curve, but yields a benefit equal to the area under the zðdþ curve. 8 Thus the net welfare gain is equal to the sliver between the zðdþ and ri 0 ðdþ curves. 7 It is important to note however, that the socially optimal accident probability p S is defined conditional on damages having been reduced to the socially optimal level D S. As discussed above, the socially optimal accident probability conditional on judgment-proof firms privately optimal damage level D is p ¼ zð DÞ, which is always lower than the accident probability p ¼ zðpþ chosen by such firms. 8 Recall that the the height of the ri 0 ðdþ curve is the marginal cost of damage reduction. By the envelope theorem, if the accident probability is kept at its conditionally optimal value, the marginal benefit of damage reduction is equal to p, i.e., to the height of the zðdþ curve.

8 164 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) Fig. 3. Deadweight loss of a judgment-proof firm with and without extended liability. 5. The firm s problem with extended liability In this section, we consider how extending liability for residual damages to lenders changes the incentives of the firm. 9 If lenders are liable for residual damages, then, all else equal, they will require a higher loan fee in order to break even. However, all else will not be equal: in anticipation of this response by the lender, the firm will in general choose a different level of damage-reducing investment. For solvent firms, the analysis of Section 4 goes through unchanged. Because such firms fully internalize all accident damages, there is no residual liability to pass on to lenders. For judgment- 9 Because the literature on extended liability has largely focused on the specific example of extending liability to lenders, we use this example in much of the remainder of this paper. However, so long as the third party to whom liability is extended passes back its residual-liability costs to the firm, the results of our model also carry through to other forms of extended liability.

9 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) proof firms, the stage-3 problem of optimally choosing p conditional on any given damage level D and given loan fee is unchanged as well. The firms will therefore still optimally choose p ¼ zðp Þ. The stage-1 problem of optimally choosing D does, however, change under extended liability, because the lender s stage-2 break-even constraint becomes p maxfd ðp Þ; 0g r½k þ IðDÞŠ ¼ 0: ð6þ With extended liability, the loan fee has to cover not just the opportunity cost of the loan but also the expected residual liability. 10 Given the change in the lender s break-even constraint, the solution to the firm s optimization problem changes as follows: Proposition 2. With extended liability, the only locally optimal D and p values are (a) D S and p S for firms that are solvent at that combination, (b) D L o D S and p L 4 p S such that ri 0 ðd L Þ¼p L ¼ zðp Þ for firms that are judgment proof at that combination. With lender liability, both solvent and judgment-proof firms now fully internalize all accidentrelated costs. For a judgment-proof firm, this is because the loan fee now includes the expected residual liability that the firm was able to externalize in the absence of lender liability. An immediate implication of this full cost internalization is that, ex ante, all firms would prefer to choose D S and p S, which minimizes these accident costs. However, the moral hazard problem prevents any judgment-proof firm from credibly committing to the choice of p S in stage 3, once the loan fee has been set. Instead, such a firm will choose an accident probability p L ¼ zðp Þ4 p S. As a result, in stage 1 it will choose a damage level D L o D S, such that ri 0 ðd L Þ¼p L. In effect, in order to keep its expected damages down, the judgment-proof firm partially compensates for taking too little unobservable care ex post, by spending what would otherwise be too much on observable care ex ante. Overall, however, because the firm is not making first-best care decisions, its total accident-related costs will exceed those at the social optimum. Once again, Proposition 2 leaves unanswered the question of which firms are judgment proof and which are solvent in equilibrium. In the Appendix, we show that the cutoff value p L above which firms are solvent is lower than p N, the cutoff value without extended liability. To see why, recall from our discussion following Proposition 1 that in the absence of extended liability there exists a range of relatively rich firms that are judgment proof by choice: these firms have the option of being solvent by choosing ðd S ; p S Þ, but also the option of achieving a higher payoff by externalizing damages. Introducing extended liability effectively removes the latter option, thereby inducing these firms to become solvent. As a result, these firms switch to taking socially optimal levels of both damage-reducing and probability-reducing care. 10 Note that enters the residual-liability term in (6), and that p is a function of. This implies that, for judgmentproof firms, increasing the loan fee now has two opposing effects on lender returns: it increases the lender s receipts, but also increases the lender s expected residual liability pfd ðp Þg. So as not to unnecessarily complicate the exposition of our model, we assume the first effect always outweighs the second. An appendix showing exactly what assumption is needed to ensure this, and the (very minor) implications for our results if this assumption fails, is available from the authors upon request.

10 166 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) We also show in the Appendix that firms with positive but low gross profits are driven out of business by extended liability. More specifically, we find that the cutoff value of p above which firms remain viable, which we denote p L, is higher than p S. Recall from Section 4 that firms with p 2½0; p S Þ are viable only because they externalize damages. These firms are driven out of business when extended liability is introduced, because they are now forced to fully internalize all costs. In addition, however, there is a range of firms with gross profits greater than p S that are driven out of business as well, because they internalize costs that exceed those at the social optimum Welfare effects of introducing extended liability The welfare effects of introducing extended liability again depends on firms gross profits: Proposition 3. (a) For firms with either low gross profits p 2½0; p S Þ or high gross profits p 2½p L ; p N Þ the welfare effect of introducing extended liability is unambiguously positive. (b) For firms with intermediate gross profits p 2ðp S ; p L Þ the welfare effect is ambiguous. (c) Without extended liability, there is excess entry of firms. Extending liability results in exit that is excessive relative to the first best, but that is second-best optimal. For firms with p 2½0; p S Þ, welfare unambiguously improves; these firms generate negative welfare in the absence of extended liability, and are driven out of business when extended liability is introduced. For firms with p 2½p L ; p N Þ, welfare unambiguously improves as well; these are the firms that switch from being judgment proof to being solvent, and thereby switch to making socially optimal decisions when extended liability is introduced. For firms with p 2ðp S ; p L Þ, however, introducing extended liability replaces one source of welfare loss with a different one. The net welfare effect turns out to be ambiguous, and depends on the shape of the cost curves. The interval ðp S ; p L Þ can be divided into two sub-intervals ðp S ; p L Þ and ½p L ; p L Þ. Consider first firms with p 2½p L ; p L Þ, i.e., firms that stay in business after extended liability is introduced. For these firms, introducing extended liability implies replacing deadweight loss DWL N with a new deadweight loss DWL L, illustrated in Fig. 3. We can again usefully divide this deadweight-loss area into two parts: a triangle to the left of D L and a sliver between D L and D S. Using a thought experiment very similar to that discussed in Section 4, it can be seen that the triangle represents the welfare gain from holding damages constant at D L but reducing the accident probability from p L to its conditionally optimal value zðd L Þ. It can also be seen that the sliver represents the welfare gain from then increasing damages from D L to D S, while keeping the accident probability at its conditionally optimal value zðdþ. To show that introducing extended liability may either decrease or increase welfare for these firms, it is sufficient to show that for some configurations of the cost curves DWL N will be zero and DWL L positive, while for other configurations the opposite will be true. This is easiest to establish for judgment-proof firms that have gross profits p4 D S. To see that the deadweight loss DWL N can be zero for such firms, note in Fig. 3 that what in Section 4 we called the triangle will be smaller, the closer to horizontal at p S the zðdþ curve is for all DXp (so that society gains little from changing the accident probability from p N to the conditionally optimal p). Moreover, what we called the sliver will be smaller, the closer the ri 0 ðdþ curve is to

11 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) the zðdþ curve for all DXD S (so that society gains little from reducing damages from D to D S ). In the limit where both the zðdþ and ri 0 ðdþ curves become arbitrarily close to horizontal at level p S everywhere to the right of D S, the deadweight loss becomes vanishingly small. It is also clear from the figure, however, that DWL L will be positive as long as the zðdþ and ri 0 ðdþ curves diverge everywhere to the left of D S. Conversely, if the curves coincide to the left of D S, but not to the right, DWL L will be zero, but DWL N positive. 11 Similar arguments can be used to show that the welfare effect of introducing extended liability is ambiguous also for firms with p 2ðp S ; p L Þ, i.e., firms that are driven out of business when extended liability is introduced. More specifically, we prove in the Appendix that the welfare generated by these firms in the absence of extended liability can itself be either positive or negative, so that driving these firms out of business can either decrease or increase welfare. 12 As for part (c) of the proposition, recall that, in the absence of extended liability, firms with p 2½0; p S Þ are viable, but generate negative welfare. In this sense, the absence of extended liability results in excess entry. When extended liability is introduced, these firms are driven out of business, but so are firms with p 2ðp S ; p L Þ. These latter firms would be viable and generate positive welfare if the commitment problem discussed above did not prevent them from taking first-best levels of care. In this sense, extended liability results in excess exit. Note, however, that in the absence of any mechanism that can induce judgment-proof firms to take first-best levels of care, driving firms with p 2½p S ; p L Þ out of business is secondbest optimal. If the first best cannot be implemented, a relevant question is whether there exists a policy that is feasible and dominates extended liability, in that it allows a greater range of firms to both stay in business and generate positive (though not necessarily maximal) welfare. The next section discusses one such policy, namely direct regulation of damage-reducing investments. 6. Direct regulation of damage-reducing investments Given our assumption that lenders can observe a firm s effort to reduce accident damages, but not its efforts to reduce the probability of accidents, it is reasonable to assume that the same would be true of regulators. If so, a natural question to ask is whether direct regulation of damage-reducing investments might either (1) complement extended liability, or (2) be a superior alternative to it. Taking these two questions in turn, we find the following: Proposition 4. Given a regime of strict but limited liability, (a) direct D-regulation does not complement extended liability: if extended liability is in place any binding restrictions on firms choices of D can only reduce welfare, 11 For firms with gross profits po D S, the conditions are only slightly different. Specifically, for DWL N to be zero but DWL L positive, the zðdþ and ri 0 ðdþ curves must converge at p S to the right of p (rather than D S ), and diverge to the left. 12 This result (that extended liability may drive firms out of business that generate positive welfare with strict liability alone) lends some support to the often-made claim (e.g., [11,17]) that extended liability deters socially productive investments.

12 168 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) (b) direct D-regulation is a superior alternative to extended liability if such regulation can be tailored to firms gross profit levels; if it cannot, then either policy may dominate the other. Part (a) of the proposition follows directly from the fact that the firm s choice of D is secondbest optimal under extended liability. Part (b) follows from the fact that direct D-regulation can replicate the damage levels chosen by all firms under extended liability, but can do so for judgment-proof firms at a lower loan fee. As a result, these firms will choose a lower accident probability, and social costs will therefore be lower as well. This unambiguous theoretical result, that direct D-regulation is superior to extended liability, of course depends importantly on the assumption that the regulator has the same information as the lender, and can therefore tailor the D-regulation to firms gross profits. 13 If this is not the case in practice, then we are back to welfare ambiguity Conclusions The model developed in this paper incorporates two stylized facts about real-world safety measures that firms may take to reduce expected damages from environmental accidents. One is that firms can usually reduce not just the accident probability but also the magnitude of damages. The other is that probability-reducing care tends to be of a procedural nature, and is therefore difficult for third parties to observe, whereas damage-reducing care tends to involve tangible investments, and is therefore readily observable. We find that under these conditions introducing extended liability for environmental accidents drives judgment-proof firms with low gross profits out of business, and induces judgment-proof firms with high gross profits to become solvent and choose socially optimal levels of care. For judgment-proof firms with intermediate gross profits, however, extending liability fails to induce socially optimal levels of care, even though it forces these firms to fully internalize accident damages. The first two results contrast with those of Pitchford [25], who considers only unobservable, probability-reducing care and shows that (with full debt financing) extending liability to lenders reduces welfare, because it exacerbates the moral-hazard problem. The same effect arises in our model as well, but we show that if firms can also take observable, damage-reducing care, they will increase such care in order to improve their contractual terms with the lender. Some firms will in fact reduce damages to the point where they become solvent, and then take socially optimal levels of both observable and unobservable care. Firms that remain judgment proof, however, end up taking more than first-best observable care to partially compensate for taking less than first-best 13 As discussed in the literature on relationship lending (e.g., [2 4]), banks may accumulate information about firms over time. In practice, therefore, they may know more than the regulator. 14 Furthermore, we are abstracting from any dynamic welfare effects that either extended liability or direct D- regulation might have, for instance by altering firms incentives to reduce costs of damage reduction through innovation.

13 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) unobservable care. Extending liability to these firms merely replaces one distortion with another, with an ambiguous net effect on welfare. More specifically, the net welfare effect depends on the precise shape of the care cost functions. It follows that determining whether extending liability is a desirable policy in practice may be difficult in industries with a rich array of care technologies, requiring more information on the part of the regulator than is likely to be available. One can imagine situations, however, where the regulator does have the relevant information, for instance because there is only a limited set of technologies available for damage and probability reduction. In such cases, extending liability is likely to be welfare-improving if the damage-reducing technologies are cheap relative to the probability-reducing ones, in the sense of reducing expected damages by more for a given level of expenditure. We find also, however, that if the regulator has information about costs and firm profits, a policy of direct regulation of damage-reducing investment combined with strict liability dominates extended liability. This result is interesting in light of the literature on combining ex ante regulation with ex post liability (see, e.g., [19 21,27,29]). The seminal paper in this literature is Shavell [29], who shows that if (i) the regulator cannot observe firm profits, (ii) some firms may be judgment proof, and (iii) the probability of successful prosecution is less than one, then a policy combining an ex ante regulation with ex post strict liability dominates either policy alone. A recent contribution by Schmitz [27] expands on this result by showing that if the regulator can observe profits and can moreover impose punitive damages (a possibility that Shavell does not consider), then either regulation or strict liability always dominates a combination of the two. Our result contrasts with Schmitz s in that we find that regulation can complement strict liability if it is targeted at observable, damagereducing care. Although our paper focuses on extended liability, the literature has also considered financialresponsibility requirements such as mandatory insurance and bonding as alternative remedies to the judgment-proof problem ([9,15,16,24]). 15 Such remedies will have the same effects in our model as extended liability: the only difference is that, instead of the loan fee increasing to cover residual liability, the firm will now face an insurance premium or bond fee. Our paper has also focused exclusively on debt-financed firms. The results we derive also carry through to the case of equity-financed firms, as long as owner equity is insufficient to make the firm solvent in the event of an accident. Acknowledgments The authors thank Robert Innes, Matthew Kotchen, an anonymous referee, and participants at the Second World Congress of Environmental and Resource Economists and the First CIRANO- IDEI-LEERNA Conference on the Management of Major Industrial/Environmental Risks for useful comments. 15 See [5] for an excellent discussion of existing financial-responsibility requirements under US environmental statutes.

14 170 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) Appendix A Proof of Proposition 1. Part (a): Immediate from the fact that a solvent firm s payoff V ¼ p riðdþ pd cð pþ coincides with welfare W. Part (b): The judgment-proof firm s stage-3 optimization problem, conditional on its earlier choice of D and on the fixed loan fee, is max V ¼ð1 pþ½p Š cð pþ s:t: ppp; p with solution p ¼ zðp Þ. After substituting p and the lender s break-even condition (5) into V, the firm s stage-1 optimization problem becomes max V ¼ð1 D p Þ½P rk riðdþš cð p Þ s:t: Dp D; with solution D ¼ D. Substituting this back into the expressions for and p and using p P rk yields p ¼ zðpþ. & The remaining results discussed briefly in Section 4 can be stated formally as follows: Lemma 1. There exist critical gross-profit values D S o p L o p N o D such that (a) Firms with p 2½p L ; DÞ can choose to be either solvent or judgment proof, in the sense that for these firms both ðd S ; p S Þ and ð D; zðpþþ are locally optimal. (b) Firms with p 2½0; p N Þ are judgment proof in equilibrium; firms with p 2½p N ; 1Þ are solvent. (c) Of the firms that are judgment proof in equilibrium, those with p 2½0; D S Þ take less than first-best unobservable care ðzðpþ4 p S Þ; those with p 2ðD S ; p N Þ take more ðzðpþo p S Þ. Proof. Part (a): A firm is solvent at D S if its resulting financial assets p riðd S Þ weakly exceed D S, i.e., if pxd S þ riðd S Þp L, and judgment proof at D if its resulting financial assets p fall short of D. Both are true for some range of firms, since by our assumptions on the IðÞ and zðþ functions, D S þ riðd S Þ¼D S þ Z D D S ri 0 ðdþ ddo D S þ Z D D S zðdþ ddo D S þ ¼ D: Part (b): Let V s ðpþ denote a firm s payoff if it chooses D S and p S and is solvent at that combination, and let V N j ðpþ denote a firm s payoff without extended liability if it chooses D and p ¼ zðpþ and is judgment proof at that combination. Since both functions are continuous in p, itis sufficient to show that V N j ðp L Þ4 V s ðp L Þ and lim p! D V N j ðpþo V s ð DÞ, because the V N j ðpþ function must then cross the V s ðpþ function from above at some intermediate value p N 2ðp L ; DÞ. That V N j ðp L Þ4 V s ðp L Þ follows from Z D D S 1 dd V s ðp L Þ¼ð1 p S ÞD S cðp S Þo ð1 p S Þp L cðp S Þo ð1 zðp L ÞÞp L cðp L Þ ¼ V N j ðp L Þ;

15 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) using that p L D S þ riðd S Þ and that p ¼ zðpþ uniquely maximizes the value V ¼ð1 pþp cð pþ of a judgment-proof firm. That lim p! D V N j ðpþo V s ð DÞ follows from V N j ð DÞ ¼ D rið DÞ p D cðpþo D riðd S Þ p S D S cðp S Þ¼V s ð DÞ; using that ðd S ; p S Þ uniquely maximizes the value V ¼ p riðdþ pd cð pþ of a solvent firm. Part (c): Since z 0 ðþo 0, zðpþ4 ðo Þ zðd S Þ¼p S if po ð4 Þ D S. & Proof of Proposition 2. As noted in the text, extended liability changes only a judgment-proof firm s stage-1 optimization problem. For purposes of the proof, it is convenient to recast this problem as that of choosing both D and simultaneously, subject to the new lender break-even condition (6) and to Dp D. The Lagrangian associated with this problem is L ¼ð1 p Þ½P Š cð p Þþl ½ð1 p Þ rk riðdþ p fd PgŠ þ l D ½ D DŠ; where p ¼ zðp Þ. Differentiating w.r.t. and ¼ ð1 p Þþl ð1 p Þ z 0 ðp ÞfD ðp Þg ¼ 0; ¼ l ½ ri 0 ðdþ p Š l D ¼ 0: ða2þ The only value of D consistent with condition (A2) and the first-order conditions involving l and l D is D such that ri 0 ðdþ ¼p ¼ zðp Þ. From the properties of the zðþ and IðÞ functions, this solution condition and the inequality P o D that defines a judgment-proof firm can hold simultaneously only at ðd; pþ combinations with Do D S and p4 p S. & The remaining results discussed briefly in Section 5 can be stated formally as follows: Lemma 2. There exists a critical gross-profit value p L 2ðp S ; p L Þ such that only firms with pxp L remain in business under extended liability. Of these, firms with p 2½p L ; p L Þ are judgment proof, while firms with p 2½p L ; 1Þ are solvent. Proof. Let V L j ðpþ denote a firm s payoff with extended liability if it chooses DL and p L such that ri 0 ðd L Þ¼p L ¼ zðp Þ and is judgment proof at that combination. The critical gross-profit level p L is defined implicitly by V L j ðpl Þ¼0. That p L o p L follows from the fact that V L j ðpþ is increasing in p, and that Z p Z p cðp S Þ¼ c 0 ð pþ dpo c 0 ðp S Þ dp ¼ D S dp ¼ðp p S ÞD S o ð1 p S ÞD S ; p S p S p S so lim p!p LV L j ðpþ ¼ð1 ps ÞD S cðp S Þ is strictly positive. That p S o p L follows from 0 V L j ðpl Þ¼p L riðd L Þ p L D L cðp L Þo p L riðd S Þ p S D S cðp S Þ ¼ p L p S ; Z p

16 172 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) since ðd S ; p S Þ uniquely minimizes full accident-related costs riðdþþpd þ cð pþ. The remainder of the lemma follows by recalling from the proof of Lemma 1 that the conditions defining V s ðpþ hold iff pxp L, and checking that the conditions defining V L j ðpþ hold iff p 2½pL ; p L Þ. & Proof of Proposition 3. Part (a): Immediate from the text. Part (b): Divide the interval ðp S ; p L Þ into sub-intervals ðp S ; p L Þ and ½p L ; p L Þ. That the welfare effect of extending liability is ambiguous for firms with p 2½p L ; p L Þ is immediate from the text. To establish the same for firms with p 2ðp S ; p L Þ, let W N ðpþ denote the welfare generated by these firms in the absence of extended liability, at p ¼ zðpþ and D ¼ D. Also, let W S ðpþ denote the welfare generated by these firms at p S and D S. We must show that W N ðpþ can be either positive or negative, so that driving these firms out of business can either decrease or increase welfare. To show that W N ðpþ can be positive, note that W S ðpþ W N ðpþ is just the deadweight loss DWL N, and that the conditions identified in Section 5 under which DWL N is zero for firms with p 2½p L ; p L Þ apply equally to firms with p 2½p S ; p L Þ. If these conditions hold, so that DWL N is indeed zero, then, since W S ðpþ is positive all firms with p 2ðp S ; p L Þ, W N ðpþ will be positive also. To show that W N ðpþ can be negative, consider the limiting case where zðdþ!zðd S Þ¼p S for all D (so p is in effect fixed at p S and cðp S Þ¼0), and ri 0 ðdþ!0 for all D 2ðD S ; DŠ (so riðd S Þ¼0). In this limit, W N ðpþ reduces to p p S D, and the equation V s ðp N Þ¼V N j ðp N Þ that defines p N reduces to p N p S D S ¼ p N p S p N, or p N ¼ D S. It follows that lim p!p NW N ðpþ ¼D S p S D, which can clearly be negative for sufficiently large D. Since W N ðpþ is increasing in p, this in turn implies that W N ðpþ will be negative for all judgment-proof firms (i.e., all firms with p 2½0; p N Þ), including firms with p 2ðp S ; p L Þ. Part (c): Immediate from the text. & Proof of Proposition 4. Immediate from the text. & References [1] T.R. Beard, Bankruptcy and care choice, RAND J. Econ. 21 (4) (1990) [2] A.N. Berger, G.F. Udell, Relationship lending and lines of credit in small firm finance, J. Bus. 68 (3) (1995) [3] A.N. Berger, G.F. Udell, Small business credit availability and relationship lending: the importance of bank organisational structure, Econ. J. 112 (477) (2002) F32 F53. [4] A.W.A. Boot, Relationship banking: What do we know?, J. Finan. Intermediation 9 (1) (2000) [5] J. Boyd, Financial responsibility for environmental obligations: are bonding and assurance rules fulfilling their promise? Discussion Paper 01-42, Resources for the Future, Washington, DC, August [6] J. Boyd, D.E. Ingberman, The polluter pays principle : should liability be extended when the polluter cannot pay?, Geneva Pap. Risk Ins. 21 (79) (1996) [7] J. Boyd, D.E. Ingberman, The search for deep pockets: Is extended liability expensive liability?, J. Law Econ. Organ. 13 (1) (1997) [8] J. Boyd, D.E. Ingberman, Fly by night or face the music; Premature dissolution and the desirability of extended liability, Amer. Law Econ. Rev. 5 (1) (2003) [9] M. Boyer, J.J. Laffont, Environmental risks and bank liability, Euro. Econ. Rev. 41 (8) (1997) [10] R. Burke, Sailing in safe harbors: recent developments regarding lender liability under CERCLA, Pace Environ. Law Rev. 16 (1998) [11] J.J. Byrne, T.J. Greco, Comment: superfund reform needed to keep credit flowing, Amer. Banker (1994) 17. [12] B. Craig, S.E. Thiel, Large risks and the decision to incorporate, J. Econ. Bus. 42 (3) (1990)

17 E. Hutchinson, K. van t Veld / Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 49 (2005) [13] G. Dionne, S. Spaeter, Environmental risk and extended liability: the case of green technologies, J. Public Econ. 87 (5 6) (2003) [14] E. Feess, Lender liability for environmental harm: an argument against negligence based rules, Euro. J. Law Econ. 8 (3) (1999) [15] E. Feess, U. Hege, Environmental harm and financial responsibility, Geneva Pap. Risk Ins.: Issues Practice 25 (2) (2000) [16] E. Feess, U. Hege, Safety monitoring, capital structure and financial responsibility, Int. Rev. Law Econ. 23 (3) (2003) [17] M.I. Greenberg, D.M. Shaw, To lend or not to lend: that should not be the question: the uncertainties of lender liability under CERCLA, Duke Law J. 41 (5) (1992) [18] A.G. Heyes, Lender penalty for environmental damage and the equilibrium cost of capital, Economica 63 (250) (1996) [19] R. Innes, Optimal liability with stochastic harms, judgement-proof injurers and asymmetric information, Int. Rev. Law Econ. 19 (2) (1999) [20] R. Innes, Enforcement costs, optimal sanctions and the choice between ex-post liability and ex-ante regulation, Int. Rev. Law Econ., forthcoming. [21] C. Kolstad, T. Ulen, G. Johnson, Ex-post liability for harm vs. ex-ante safety regulation: substitutes or complements, Amer. Econ. Rev. 80 (4) (1990) [22] T.R. Lewis, D.E.M. Sappington, Using decoupling and deep pockets to mitigate judgment-proof problems, Int. Rev. Law Econ. 19 (2) (1999) [23] T.R. Lewis, D.E.M. Sappington, How liable should a lender be? The case of judgment-proof firms and environmental risk: comment, Amer. Econ. Rev. 91 (3) (2001) [24] G.D. Mattiacci, F. Parisi, The cost of delegated control: vicarious liability, secondary liability and mandatory insurance, Law and Economics Working Paper Series 02-27, George Mason University, School of Law, [25] R. Pitchford, How liable should a lender be? The case of judgment-proof firms and environmental risk, Amer. Econ. Rev. 85 (5) (1995) [26] L.L. Posey, Limited liability and incentives when firms can inflict damages greater than net worth, Int. Rev. Law Econ. 13 (3) (1993) [27] P.W. Schmitz, On the joint use of liability and safety regulation, Int. Rev. Law Econ. 20 (3) (2000) [28] K. Segerson, Liability transfers: an economic-assessment of buyer and lender liability, J. Environ. Econ. Manage. 25 (1) (1993) S46 S63. [29] S. Shavell, A model of the optimal use of liability and safety regulation, RAND J. Econ. 15 (1984) [30] S. Shavell, Economic Analysis of Accident Law, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1987.

HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS

HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS chissn 1045-6333 ECONOMICS AND LIABILITY FOR ACCIDENTS Steven Shavell Discussion Paper No. 535 12/2005 Harvard Law School Cambridge, MA 02138

More information

Minimum asset requirements and compulsory liability insurance as solutions to the judgment-proof problem

Minimum asset requirements and compulsory liability insurance as solutions to the judgment-proof problem RAND Journal of Economics Vol. 36, No. 1, Spring 2005 pp. 63 77 Minimum asset requirements and compulsory liability insurance as solutions to the judgment-proof problem Steven Shavell Minimum asset and

More information

Credible Discovery, Settlement, and Negative Expected Value Suits

Credible Discovery, Settlement, and Negative Expected Value Suits Credible iscovery, Settlement, and Negative Expected Value Suits Warren F. Schwartz Abraham L. Wickelgren Abstract: This paper introduces the option to conduct discovery into a model of settlement bargaining

More information

CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS AND ORGANIZATION RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS AND ORGANIZATION RESEARCH PAPER SERIES Modeling the Choice Between Regulation and Liability in Terms of Social Welfare Marcel Boyer and Donatella Porrini USC Center for Law, Economics & Organization Research Paper No. C03-27 CENTER FOR LAW,

More information

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Nathaniel Hendren January, 2014 Abstract Both Akerlof (1970) and Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976) show that

More information

The Reasonable Person Negligence Standard and Liability Insurance. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University

The Reasonable Person Negligence Standard and Liability Insurance. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University \ins\liab\dlirpr.v3a 06-06-07 The Reasonable Person Negligence Standard and Liability Insurance Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University Paul Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas Thistle s research

More information

Moral Hazard. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Moral Hazard. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Moral Hazard Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania 1 Principal-Agent Problem Basic problem in corporate finance: separation of ownership and control: o The owners of the firm are typically

More information

Chapter 7. Sealed-bid Auctions

Chapter 7. Sealed-bid Auctions Chapter 7 Sealed-bid Auctions An auction is a procedure used for selling and buying items by offering them up for bid. Auctions are often used to sell objects that have a variable price (for example oil)

More information

THE FINANCING DECISIONS BY FIRMS: IMPACT OF CAPITAL STRUCTURE CHOICE ON VALUE

THE FINANCING DECISIONS BY FIRMS: IMPACT OF CAPITAL STRUCTURE CHOICE ON VALUE IX. THE FINANCING DECISIONS BY FIRMS: IMPACT OF CAPITAL STRUCTURE CHOICE ON VALUE The capital structure of a firm is defined to be the menu of the firm's liabilities (i.e, the "right-hand side" of the

More information

. In this case the leakage effect of tax increases is mitigated because some of the reduction in disposable income would have otherwise been saved.

. In this case the leakage effect of tax increases is mitigated because some of the reduction in disposable income would have otherwise been saved. Chapter 4 Review Questions. Explain how an increase in government spending and an equal increase in lump sum taxes can generate an increase in equilibrium output. Under what conditions will a balanced

More information

Slides 9. Debraj Ray. Columbia, Fall 2013. Credit Markets. Collateral. Adverse selection. Moral hazard. Enforcement

Slides 9. Debraj Ray. Columbia, Fall 2013. Credit Markets. Collateral. Adverse selection. Moral hazard. Enforcement Slides 9 Debraj Ray Columbia, Fall 2013 Credit Markets Collateral Adverse selection Moral hazard Enforcement Credit Markets Formal sector: State or commercial banks. Require collateral, business plan Usually

More information

Stochastic Inventory Control

Stochastic Inventory Control Chapter 3 Stochastic Inventory Control 1 In this chapter, we consider in much greater details certain dynamic inventory control problems of the type already encountered in section 1.3. In addition to the

More information

Incentive Compensation for Risk Managers when Effort is Unobservable

Incentive Compensation for Risk Managers when Effort is Unobservable Incentive Compensation for Risk Managers when Effort is Unobservable by Paul Kupiec 1 This Draft: October 2013 Abstract In a stylized model of a financial intermediary, risk managers can expend effort

More information

Week 7 - Game Theory and Industrial Organisation

Week 7 - Game Theory and Industrial Organisation Week 7 - Game Theory and Industrial Organisation The Cournot and Bertrand models are the two basic templates for models of oligopoly; industry structures with a small number of firms. There are a number

More information

An Empirical Analysis of Insider Rates vs. Outsider Rates in Bank Lending

An Empirical Analysis of Insider Rates vs. Outsider Rates in Bank Lending An Empirical Analysis of Insider Rates vs. Outsider Rates in Bank Lending Lamont Black* Indiana University Federal Reserve Board of Governors November 2006 ABSTRACT: This paper analyzes empirically the

More information

Credit Lectures 26 and 27

Credit Lectures 26 and 27 Lectures 26 and 27 24 and 29 April 2014 Operation of the Market may not function smoothly 1. Costly/impossible to monitor exactly what s done with loan. Consumption? Production? Risky investment? Involuntary

More information

Lecture notes for Choice Under Uncertainty

Lecture notes for Choice Under Uncertainty Lecture notes for Choice Under Uncertainty 1. Introduction In this lecture we examine the theory of decision-making under uncertainty and its application to the demand for insurance. The undergraduate

More information

Empirical Applying Of Mutual Funds

Empirical Applying Of Mutual Funds Internet Appendix for A Model of hadow Banking * At t = 0, a generic intermediary j solves the optimization problem: max ( D, I H, I L, H, L, TH, TL ) [R (I H + T H H ) + p H ( H T H )] + [E ω (π ω ) A

More information

Regret and Rejoicing Effects on Mixed Insurance *

Regret and Rejoicing Effects on Mixed Insurance * Regret and Rejoicing Effects on Mixed Insurance * Yoichiro Fujii, Osaka Sangyo University Mahito Okura, Doshisha Women s College of Liberal Arts Yusuke Osaki, Osaka Sangyo University + Abstract This papers

More information

TOPIC 6: CAPITAL STRUCTURE AND THE MARKET FOR CORPORATE CONTROL

TOPIC 6: CAPITAL STRUCTURE AND THE MARKET FOR CORPORATE CONTROL TOPIC 6: CAPITAL STRUCTURE AND THE MARKET FOR CORPORATE CONTROL 1. Introduction 2. The free rider problem In a classical paper, Grossman and Hart (Bell J., 1980), show that there is a fundamental problem

More information

Schooling, Political Participation, and the Economy. (Online Supplementary Appendix: Not for Publication)

Schooling, Political Participation, and the Economy. (Online Supplementary Appendix: Not for Publication) Schooling, Political Participation, and the Economy Online Supplementary Appendix: Not for Publication) Filipe R. Campante Davin Chor July 200 Abstract In this online appendix, we present the proofs for

More information

Prices versus Exams as Strategic Instruments for Competing Universities

Prices versus Exams as Strategic Instruments for Competing Universities Prices versus Exams as Strategic Instruments for Competing Universities Elena Del Rey and Laura Romero October 004 Abstract In this paper we investigate the optimal choice of prices and/or exams by universities

More information

Notes on indifference curve analysis of the choice between leisure and labor, and the deadweight loss of taxation. Jon Bakija

Notes on indifference curve analysis of the choice between leisure and labor, and the deadweight loss of taxation. Jon Bakija Notes on indifference curve analysis of the choice between leisure and labor, and the deadweight loss of taxation Jon Bakija This example shows how to use a budget constraint and indifference curve diagram

More information

Screening by the Company You Keep: Joint Liability Lending and the Peer Selection Maitreesh Ghatak presented by Chi Wan

Screening by the Company You Keep: Joint Liability Lending and the Peer Selection Maitreesh Ghatak presented by Chi Wan Screening by the Company You Keep: Joint Liability Lending and the Peer Selection Maitreesh Ghatak presented by Chi Wan 1. Introduction The paper looks at an economic environment where borrowers have some

More information

CostandQualityIncentivesinHealthCare: Altruistic Providers

CostandQualityIncentivesinHealthCare: Altruistic Providers CostandQualityIncentivesinHealthCare: Altruistic Providers Ching-to Albert Ma Department of Economics Boston University 27 Bay State Road Boston Massachusetts 2215 ma@bu.edu December, 1997 JEL Classification

More information

Conditions for Efficiency in Package Pricing

Conditions for Efficiency in Package Pricing Conditions for Efficiency in Package Pricing Babu Nahata Department of Economics University of Louisville Louisville, Kentucky 40292, USA. e-mail: nahata@louisville.edu and Serguei Kokovin and Evgeny Zhelobodko

More information

Work incentives and household insurance: Sequential contracting with altruistic individuals and moral hazard

Work incentives and household insurance: Sequential contracting with altruistic individuals and moral hazard Work incentives and household insurance: Sequential contracting with altruistic individuals and moral hazard Cécile Aubert Abstract Two agents sequentially contracts with different principals under moral

More information

Vilnius University. Faculty of Mathematics and Informatics. Gintautas Bareikis

Vilnius University. Faculty of Mathematics and Informatics. Gintautas Bareikis Vilnius University Faculty of Mathematics and Informatics Gintautas Bareikis CONTENT Chapter 1. SIMPLE AND COMPOUND INTEREST 1.1 Simple interest......................................................................

More information

How To Understand The Relationship Between Health Insurance And Moral Hazard

How To Understand The Relationship Between Health Insurance And Moral Hazard Optimal health insurance contract : can moral hazard incresase indemnity? David Alary SDFi, University Paris Dauphine Franck Bien LEGOS, University Paris Dauphine Abstract In this note, we generalize the

More information

Chapter 21: The Discounted Utility Model

Chapter 21: The Discounted Utility Model Chapter 21: The Discounted Utility Model 21.1: Introduction This is an important chapter in that it introduces, and explores the implications of, an empirically relevant utility function representing intertemporal

More information

Investor protection and equity markets $

Investor protection and equity markets $ Journal of Financial Economics 66 (2002) 3 27 Investor protection and equity markets $ Andrei Shleifer a, *, Daniel Wolfenzon b a Littauer Center Department of Economics, Harvard University, Cambridge,

More information

A Simple Model of Price Dispersion *

A Simple Model of Price Dispersion * Federal Reserve Bank of Dallas Globalization and Monetary Policy Institute Working Paper No. 112 http://www.dallasfed.org/assets/documents/institute/wpapers/2012/0112.pdf A Simple Model of Price Dispersion

More information

Optimal health insurance contract: Is a deductible useful?

Optimal health insurance contract: Is a deductible useful? Economics Letters 87 (2005) 313 317 www.elsevier.com/locate/econbase Optimal health insurance contract: Is a deductible useful? David Bardey a, T, Romain Lesur b a GREMAQ UMR CNRS 5604-Manufacture des

More information

Financial Institutions I: The Economics of Banking

Financial Institutions I: The Economics of Banking Financial Institutions I: The Economics of Banking Prof. Dr. Isabel Schnabel Gutenberg School of Management and Economics Johannes Gutenberg University Mainz Summer term 2011 V4 1/30 I. Introduction II.

More information

Market Power and Efficiency in Card Payment Systems: A Comment on Rochet and Tirole

Market Power and Efficiency in Card Payment Systems: A Comment on Rochet and Tirole Market Power and Efficiency in Card Payment Systems: A Comment on Rochet and Tirole Luís M. B. Cabral New York University and CEPR November 2005 1 Introduction Beginning with their seminal 2002 paper,

More information

Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zurich. Working Paper Series ISSN 1424-0459. Working Paper No. 229

Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zurich. Working Paper Series ISSN 1424-0459. Working Paper No. 229 Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zurich Working Paper Series ISSN 1424-0459 Working Paper No. 229 On the Notion of the First Best in Standard Hidden Action Problems Christian

More information

Switching Cost, Competition, and Pricing in the Property/Casualty Insurance Market for Large Commercial Accounts

Switching Cost, Competition, and Pricing in the Property/Casualty Insurance Market for Large Commercial Accounts Switching Cost, Competition, and Pricing in the Property/Casualty Insurance Market for Large Commercial Accounts Lisa L. Posey * Abstract: With large commercial accounts, a small number of insurers negotiate

More information

ECON 312: Oligopolisitic Competition 1. Industrial Organization Oligopolistic Competition

ECON 312: Oligopolisitic Competition 1. Industrial Organization Oligopolistic Competition ECON 312: Oligopolisitic Competition 1 Industrial Organization Oligopolistic Competition Both the monopoly and the perfectly competitive market structure has in common is that neither has to concern itself

More information

Second degree price discrimination

Second degree price discrimination Bergals School of Economics Fall 1997/8 Tel Aviv University Second degree price discrimination Yossi Spiegel 1. Introduction Second degree price discrimination refers to cases where a firm does not have

More information

Economics Working Paper Series 2011-4. Medical Malpractice and Physician Liability Under a Negligence Rule

Economics Working Paper Series 2011-4. Medical Malpractice and Physician Liability Under a Negligence Rule Economics Working Paper Series 2011-4 Medical Malpractice and Physician Liability Under a Negligence Rule Donald J. Wright March 2011 Medical Malpractice and Physician Liability Under a Negligence Rule

More information

On Compulsory Per-Claim Deductibles in Automobile Insurance

On Compulsory Per-Claim Deductibles in Automobile Insurance The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, 28: 25 32, 2003 c 2003 The Geneva Association On Compulsory Per-Claim Deductibles in Automobile Insurance CHU-SHIU LI Department of Economics, Feng Chia

More information

THE EFFECT OF SETTLEMENT IN KAPLOW S MULTISTAGE ADJUDICATION

THE EFFECT OF SETTLEMENT IN KAPLOW S MULTISTAGE ADJUDICATION THE EFFECT OF SETTLEMENT IN KAPLOW S MULTISTAGE ADJUDICATION Abraham L. Wickelgren Professor Louis Kaplow s article, Multistage Adjudication, presents an extremely useful framework for thinking about how

More information

tariff versus quota Equivalence and its breakdown

tariff versus quota Equivalence and its breakdown Q000013 Bhagwati (1965) first demonstrated that if perfect competition prevails in all markets, a tariff and import quota are equivalent in the sense that an explicit tariff reproduces an import level

More information

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES OPTIMAL PROVISION OF LOANS AND INSURANCE AGAINST UNEMPLOYMENT FROM A LIFETIME PERSPECTIVE. Joseph Stiglitz Jungyoll Yun

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES OPTIMAL PROVISION OF LOANS AND INSURANCE AGAINST UNEMPLOYMENT FROM A LIFETIME PERSPECTIVE. Joseph Stiglitz Jungyoll Yun NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES OPTIMAL PROVISION OF LOANS AND INSURANCE AGAINST UNEMPLOYMENT FROM A LIFETIME PERSPECTIVE Joseph Stiglitz Jungyoll Yun Working Paper 19064 http://www.nber.org/papers/w19064 NATIONAL

More information

Economics 2020a / HBS 4010 / HKS API-111 FALL 2010 Solutions to Practice Problems for Lectures 1 to 4

Economics 2020a / HBS 4010 / HKS API-111 FALL 2010 Solutions to Practice Problems for Lectures 1 to 4 Economics 00a / HBS 4010 / HKS API-111 FALL 010 Solutions to Practice Problems for Lectures 1 to 4 1.1. Quantity Discounts and the Budget Constraint (a) The only distinction between the budget line with

More information

MULTIPLE LOSSES, EX ANTE MORAL HAZARD, AND THE IMPLICATIONS FOR UMBRELLA POLICIES

MULTIPLE LOSSES, EX ANTE MORAL HAZARD, AND THE IMPLICATIONS FOR UMBRELLA POLICIES C The Journal of Risk and Insurance, 2005, Vol. 72, No. 4, 525-538 MULTIPLE LOSSES, EX ANTE MORAL HAZARD, AND THE IMPLICATIONS FOR UMBRELLA POLICIES Michael Breuer ABSTRACT Under certain cost conditions

More information

Capital Structure. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Capital Structure. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Capital Structure Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania 1 Debt and Equity There are two main types of financing: debt and equity. Consider a two-period world with dates 0 and 1. At

More information

Optimal demand management policies with probability weighting

Optimal demand management policies with probability weighting Optimal demand management policies with probability weighting Ana B. Ania February 2006 Preliminary draft. Please, do not circulate. Abstract We review the optimality of partial insurance contracts in

More information

The Elasticity of Taxable Income: A Non-Technical Summary

The Elasticity of Taxable Income: A Non-Technical Summary The Elasticity of Taxable Income: A Non-Technical Summary John Creedy The University of Melbourne Abstract This paper provides a non-technical summary of the concept of the elasticity of taxable income,

More information

Economics of Insurance

Economics of Insurance Economics of Insurance In this last lecture, we cover most topics of Economics of Information within a single application. Through this, you will see how the differential informational assumptions allow

More information

No Claim Bonus? by John D. Hey*

No Claim Bonus? by John D. Hey* The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance, 10 (No 36, July 1985), 209-228 No Claim Bonus? by John D. Hey* 1. Introduction No claim bonus schemes are a prominent feature of some insurance contracts, most

More information

Optimal Age Specific Income Taxation

Optimal Age Specific Income Taxation Optimal Age Specific Income Taxation Jean-Marie Lozachmeur 1 October, 2005 1 GREMAQ, University of Toulouse. Mailing: Gremaq, 21 Allée de Brienne F- 31000 Toulouse. E-mail: jean-marie.lozachmeur@univ-tlse1.fr.

More information

The Greater the Differences, the Greater the Gains?

The Greater the Differences, the Greater the Gains? The Greater the Differences, the Greater the Gains? Wilfred J. Ethier Department of Economics University of Pennsylvania First version: 30 November 2007 This printing: 21 April 2009 The Greater the Differences,

More information

Why Plaintiffs Attorneys Use Contingent and Defense Attorneys Fixed Fee Contracts

Why Plaintiffs Attorneys Use Contingent and Defense Attorneys Fixed Fee Contracts Why Plaintiffs Attorneys Use Contingent and Defense Attorneys Fixed Fee Contracts Winand Emons 1 Claude Fluet 2 1 Department of Economics University of Bern, CEPR, CIRPEE 2 Université du Québec à Montréal,

More information

2. Information Economics

2. Information Economics 2. Information Economics In General Equilibrium Theory all agents had full information regarding any variable of interest (prices, commodities, state of nature, cost function, preferences, etc.) In many

More information

Pricing in a Competitive Market with a Common Network Resource

Pricing in a Competitive Market with a Common Network Resource Pricing in a Competitive Market with a Common Network Resource Daniel McFadden Department of Economics, University of California, Berkeley April 8, 2002 I. This note is concerned with the economics of

More information

Liability Insurance as Protection Against Legal Error. Vickie Bajtelsmit Colorado State University. and

Liability Insurance as Protection Against Legal Error. Vickie Bajtelsmit Colorado State University. and lipale.v2a 07-17-08 Liability Insurance as Protection Against Legal Error Vickie Bajtelsmit Colorado State University and Paul D. Thistle * University of Nevada Las Vegas Thistle s research was supported

More information

Inflation. Chapter 8. 8.1 Money Supply and Demand

Inflation. Chapter 8. 8.1 Money Supply and Demand Chapter 8 Inflation This chapter examines the causes and consequences of inflation. Sections 8.1 and 8.2 relate inflation to money supply and demand. Although the presentation differs somewhat from that

More information

Interlinkages between Payment and Securities. Settlement Systems

Interlinkages between Payment and Securities. Settlement Systems Interlinkages between Payment and Securities Settlement Systems David C. Mills, Jr. y Federal Reserve Board Samia Y. Husain Washington University in Saint Louis September 4, 2009 Abstract Payments systems

More information

The Effect of Third-Party Funding of Plaintiffs on Settlement. Andrew F. Daughety and Jennifer F. Reinganum. Online Appendix

The Effect of Third-Party Funding of Plaintiffs on Settlement. Andrew F. Daughety and Jennifer F. Reinganum. Online Appendix 1 The Effect of Third-Party Funding of Plaintiffs on Settlement Andrew F. Daughety and Jennifer F. Reinganum Online Appendix See the main paper for a description of the notation, payoffs, and game form

More information

)LQDQFLDO$VVXUDQFH,VVXHV RI(QYLURQPHQWDO/LDELOLW\

)LQDQFLDO$VVXUDQFH,VVXHV RI(QYLURQPHQWDO/LDELOLW\ )LQDQFLDO$VVXUDQFH,VVXHV RI(QYLURQPHQWDO/LDELOLW\ ([HFXWLYH6XPPDU\ %\ 3URI'U0LFKDHO*)DXUH//0 DQG 0U'DYLG*ULPHDXG Maastricht University and European Centre for Tort and Insurance Law (ECTIL) Final version

More information

ECON20310 LECTURE SYNOPSIS REAL BUSINESS CYCLE

ECON20310 LECTURE SYNOPSIS REAL BUSINESS CYCLE ECON20310 LECTURE SYNOPSIS REAL BUSINESS CYCLE YUAN TIAN This synopsis is designed merely for keep a record of the materials covered in lectures. Please refer to your own lecture notes for all proofs.

More information

Practice Problems on the Capital Market

Practice Problems on the Capital Market Practice Problems on the Capital Market 1- Define marginal product of capital (i.e., MPK). How can the MPK be shown graphically? The marginal product of capital (MPK) is the output produced per unit of

More information

Natural and Industrial Disasters: Land Use and Insurance

Natural and Industrial Disasters: Land Use and Insurance Natural and Industrial Disasters: Land Use and Insurance Céline Grislain-Letrémy 1 Bertrand Villeneuve 2 Paris, 25 October 2013 1 CREST and University Paris-Dauphine 2 University Paris-Dauphine and CREST

More information

On the irrelevance of government debt when taxes are distortionary

On the irrelevance of government debt when taxes are distortionary On the irrelevance of government debt when taxes are distortionary Marco Bassetto a,b,, Narayana Kocherlakota c,b a Department of Economics, University of Minnesota, 271 19th Ave. S., Minneapolis, MN 55455,

More information

Two Papers on Internet Connectivity and Quality. Abstract

Two Papers on Internet Connectivity and Quality. Abstract Two Papers on Internet Connectivity and Quality ROBERTO ROSON Dipartimento di Scienze Economiche, Università Ca Foscari di Venezia, Venice, Italy. Abstract I review two papers, addressing the issue of

More information

Financial Development and Macroeconomic Stability

Financial Development and Macroeconomic Stability Financial Development and Macroeconomic Stability Vincenzo Quadrini University of Southern California Urban Jermann Wharton School of the University of Pennsylvania January 31, 2005 VERY PRELIMINARY AND

More information

LIABILITY FOR ACCIDENTS

LIABILITY FOR ACCIDENTS Chapter 2 LIABILITY FOR ACCIDENTS STEVEN SHAVELL * School of Law, Harvard University, and National Bureau of Economic Research Contents 1. Introduction 142 Part A: Central theory of liability 142 2. Incentives

More information

Why is Insurance Good? An Example Jon Bakija, Williams College (Revised October 2013)

Why is Insurance Good? An Example Jon Bakija, Williams College (Revised October 2013) Why is Insurance Good? An Example Jon Bakija, Williams College (Revised October 2013) Introduction The United States government is, to a rough approximation, an insurance company with an army. 1 That is

More information

Should Banks Trade Equity Derivatives to Manage Credit Risk? Kevin Davis 9/4/1991

Should Banks Trade Equity Derivatives to Manage Credit Risk? Kevin Davis 9/4/1991 Should Banks Trade Equity Derivatives to Manage Credit Risk? Kevin Davis 9/4/1991 Banks incur a variety of risks and utilise different techniques to manage the exposures so created. Some of those techniques

More information

Moral Hazard, Market Power, and Second Best Health Insurance

Moral Hazard, Market Power, and Second Best Health Insurance Moral Hazard, Market Power, and Second Best Health Insurance by Berthold U. Wigger* Department of Economics University of Erlangen-Nuremberg D-90403 Nürnberg berthold.wigger@wiso.uni-erlangen.de and Markus

More information

Midterm Exam:Answer Sheet

Midterm Exam:Answer Sheet Econ 497 Barry W. Ickes Spring 2007 Midterm Exam:Answer Sheet 1. (25%) Consider a portfolio, c, comprised of a risk-free and risky asset, with returns given by r f and E(r p ), respectively. Let y be the

More information

Empirical Comparisons of the Contributory versus Comparative Negligence Rules. Michelle J. White

Empirical Comparisons of the Contributory versus Comparative Negligence Rules. Michelle J. White Empirical Comparisons of the Contributory versus Comparative Negligence Rules Michelle J. White The liability rule traditionally used in accident law when both the injurer s and the victim s behaviour

More information

Specific abilities to take certain types of collateral. Can price out distortions via multi-market contact 0-2

Specific abilities to take certain types of collateral. Can price out distortions via multi-market contact 0-2 Slides 9 Debraj ay Columbia, Fall 2013 Credit Markets Collateral Adverse selection Moral hazard Enforcement Credit Markets Formal sector: 0-0 State or commercial banks. equire collateral, business plan

More information

A Litigator s View of the Special Employer Doctrine

A Litigator s View of the Special Employer Doctrine A Litigator s View of the Special Employer Doctrine By: Richard M. Williams, Esq. Published By: Employee Benefit Plan Review July 2013 INTRODUCTION It is a well-established principle of common law that

More information

Adverse selection and moral hazard in health insurance.

Adverse selection and moral hazard in health insurance. Adverse selection and moral hazard in health insurance. Franck Bien David Alary University Paris Dauphine November 10, 2006 Abstract In this paper, we want to characterize the optimal health insurance

More information

A Portfolio Model of Insurance Demand. April 2005. Kalamazoo, MI 49008 East Lansing, MI 48824

A Portfolio Model of Insurance Demand. April 2005. Kalamazoo, MI 49008 East Lansing, MI 48824 A Portfolio Model of Insurance Demand April 2005 Donald J. Meyer Jack Meyer Department of Economics Department of Economics Western Michigan University Michigan State University Kalamazoo, MI 49008 East

More information

EC372 Bond and Derivatives Markets Topic #5: Options Markets I: fundamentals

EC372 Bond and Derivatives Markets Topic #5: Options Markets I: fundamentals EC372 Bond and Derivatives Markets Topic #5: Options Markets I: fundamentals R. E. Bailey Department of Economics University of Essex Outline Contents 1 Call options and put options 1 2 Payoffs on options

More information

The Real Business Cycle model

The Real Business Cycle model The Real Business Cycle model Spring 2013 1 Historical introduction Modern business cycle theory really got started with Great Depression Keynes: The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money Keynesian

More information

Insurance. Michael Peters. December 27, 2013

Insurance. Michael Peters. December 27, 2013 Insurance Michael Peters December 27, 2013 1 Introduction In this chapter, we study a very simple model of insurance using the ideas and concepts developed in the chapter on risk aversion. You may recall

More information

FIN-40008 FINANCIAL INSTRUMENTS SPRING 2008

FIN-40008 FINANCIAL INSTRUMENTS SPRING 2008 FIN-40008 FINANCIAL INSTRUMENTS SPRING 2008 Options These notes consider the way put and call options and the underlying can be combined to create hedges, spreads and combinations. We will consider the

More information

Online Appendix Feedback Effects, Asymmetric Trading, and the Limits to Arbitrage

Online Appendix Feedback Effects, Asymmetric Trading, and the Limits to Arbitrage Online Appendix Feedback Effects, Asymmetric Trading, and the Limits to Arbitrage Alex Edmans LBS, NBER, CEPR, and ECGI Itay Goldstein Wharton Wei Jiang Columbia May 8, 05 A Proofs of Propositions and

More information

Entrepreneurs Heterogeneity and New Ventures Financing. Eli Berkovitch Interdisciplinary Center, Hertzliya e-mail: elib@idc.ac.il

Entrepreneurs Heterogeneity and New Ventures Financing. Eli Berkovitch Interdisciplinary Center, Hertzliya e-mail: elib@idc.ac.il Work in Progress. Please don't quote or circulate. Entrepreneurs Heterogeneity and New Ventures Financing Eli Berkovitch Interdisciplinary Center, Hertzliya e-mail: elib@idc.ac.il Yaniv Grinstein Cornell

More information

The Trip Scheduling Problem

The Trip Scheduling Problem The Trip Scheduling Problem Claudia Archetti Department of Quantitative Methods, University of Brescia Contrada Santa Chiara 50, 25122 Brescia, Italy Martin Savelsbergh School of Industrial and Systems

More information

Optimal insurance contracts with adverse selection and comonotonic background risk

Optimal insurance contracts with adverse selection and comonotonic background risk Optimal insurance contracts with adverse selection and comonotonic background risk Alary D. Bien F. TSE (LERNA) University Paris Dauphine Abstract In this note, we consider an adverse selection problem

More information

Ch. 18: Taxes + Bankruptcy cost

Ch. 18: Taxes + Bankruptcy cost Ch. 18: Taxes + Bankruptcy cost If MM1 holds, then Financial Management has little (if any) impact on value of the firm: If markets are perfect, transaction cost (TAC) and bankruptcy cost are zero, no

More information

THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF ARBITRAGE PRICING

THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF ARBITRAGE PRICING THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF ARBITRAGE PRICING 1. Introduction The Black-Scholes theory, which is the main subject of this course and its sequel, is based on the Efficient Market Hypothesis, that arbitrages

More information

Universidad de Montevideo Macroeconomia II. The Ramsey-Cass-Koopmans Model

Universidad de Montevideo Macroeconomia II. The Ramsey-Cass-Koopmans Model Universidad de Montevideo Macroeconomia II Danilo R. Trupkin Class Notes (very preliminar) The Ramsey-Cass-Koopmans Model 1 Introduction One shortcoming of the Solow model is that the saving rate is exogenous

More information

Biform Games: Additional Online Material

Biform Games: Additional Online Material Biform Games: Additional Online Material Adam Brandenburger Harborne Stuart July 2006 These appendices supplement Brandenburger and Stuart [1, 2006], [2, 2006] ( Biform Games ). Appendix C uses the efficiency

More information

Working Paper Series

Working Paper Series RGEA Universidade de Vigo http://webs.uvigo.es/rgea Working Paper Series A Market Game Approach to Differential Information Economies Guadalupe Fugarolas, Carlos Hervés-Beloso, Emma Moreno- García and

More information

RICARDIAN EQUIVALENCE WITH A TAX ON INTEREST INCOME by Steven E. Landsburg University of Rochester

RICARDIAN EQUIVALENCE WITH A TAX ON INTEREST INCOME by Steven E. Landsburg University of Rochester RICARDIAN EQUIVALENCE WITH A TAX ON INTEREST INCOME by Steven E. Landsburg University of Rochester 1. Introduction cut: Consider the following two propositions concerning the effects of a deficit-financed

More information

Money and Public Finance

Money and Public Finance Money and Public Finance By Mr. Letlet August 1 In this anxious market environment, people lose their rationality with some even spreading false information to create trading opportunities. The tales about

More information

Optimal Auctions Continued

Optimal Auctions Continued Lecture 6 Optimal Auctions Continued 1 Recap Last week, we... Set up the Myerson auction environment: n risk-neutral bidders independent types t i F i with support [, b i ] residual valuation of t 0 for

More information

On the Dual Effect of Bankruptcy

On the Dual Effect of Bankruptcy On the Dual Effect of Bankruptcy Daiki Asanuma Abstract This paper examines whether the survival of low-productivity firms in Japan has prevented economic recovery since the bursting of the financial bubble

More information

Asset liquidity, capital structure, and secured debt $

Asset liquidity, capital structure, and secured debt $ Journal of Financial Economics 61 (1) 17 6 Asset liquidity, capital structure, and secured debt $ Erwan Morellec* William E. Simon Graduate School of Business Administration, University of Rochester, Rochester,

More information

CHAPTER 2 THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN NO-FAULT INSURANCE AND DRIVER BEHAVIOR

CHAPTER 2 THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN NO-FAULT INSURANCE AND DRIVER BEHAVIOR -5- CHAPTER 2 THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN NO-FAULT INSURANCE AND DRIVER BEHAVIOR Under a traditional tort system, at-fault drivers are liable for the economic and noneconomic damages they inflict on third

More information

Eighteenth Meeting of the IMF Committee on Balance of Payments Statistics Washington, D.C., June 27 July 1, 2005

Eighteenth Meeting of the IMF Committee on Balance of Payments Statistics Washington, D.C., June 27 July 1, 2005 BOPCOM-05/29 Eighteenth Meeting of the IMF Committee on Balance of Payments Statistics Washington, D.C., June 27 July 1, 2005 The Treatment of Nonperforming Loans Prepared by the Statistics Department

More information

1 Uncertainty and Preferences

1 Uncertainty and Preferences In this chapter, we present the theory of consumer preferences on risky outcomes. The theory is then applied to study the demand for insurance. Consider the following story. John wants to mail a package

More information

1 Introduction to Option Pricing

1 Introduction to Option Pricing ESTM 60202: Financial Mathematics Alex Himonas 03 Lecture Notes 1 October 7, 2009 1 Introduction to Option Pricing We begin by defining the needed finance terms. Stock is a certificate of ownership of

More information

Online Supplementary Material

Online Supplementary Material Online Supplementary Material The Supplementary Material includes 1. An alternative investment goal for fiscal capacity. 2. The relaxation of the monopoly assumption in favor of an oligopoly market. 3.

More information