The structural deficiency of verbal pro-forms * Bill Haddican, University of York

Similar documents
Constraints in Phrase Structure Grammar

Chapter 13, Sections Auxiliary Verbs CSLI Publications

Extended Projections of Adjectives and Comparative Deletion

The syntactic positions of adverbs and the Second Language Acquisition

Syntactic and Semantic Differences between Nominal Relative Clauses and Dependent wh-interrogative Clauses

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 3: Covert Movement vs. Type Shifting 1

The compositional semantics of same

L130: Chapter 5d. Dr. Shannon Bischoff. Dr. Shannon Bischoff () L130: Chapter 5d 1 / 25

Non-nominal Which-Relatives

Constituency. The basic units of sentence structure

I have eaten. The plums that were in the ice box

Right Node Raising and the LCA

Index. 344 Grammar and Language Workbook, Grade 8

Straightforward Pre-intermediate Practice Online

Introduction to Semantics. A Case Study in Semantic Fieldwork: Modality in Tlingit

A Comparative Analysis of Standard American English and British English. with respect to the Auxiliary Verbs

A Minimalist View on the Syntax of BECOME *

What VP Ellipsis Can Do, and What it Can t, but not Why *

Double Genitives in English

Syntactic Theory. Background and Transformational Grammar. Dr. Dan Flickinger & PD Dr. Valia Kordoni

19. Morphosyntax in L2A

Movement and Binding

The structure of the English Sentence

Actuality and fake tense in conditionals *

Rethinking the relationship between transitive and intransitive verbs

COURSE SYLLABUS ESU 561 ASPECTS OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE. Fall 2014

The mysterious specific indefinite

Cross-linguistic differences in the interpretation of sentences with more than one QP: German (Frey 1993) and Hungarian (É Kiss 1991)

Simple maths for keywords

Intending, Intention, Intent, Intentional Action, and Acting Intentionally: Comments on Knobe and Burra

Sentence Blocks. Sentence Focus Activity. Contents

Syntax: Phrases. 1. The phrase

Extraposition, the Right Roof Constraint, Result Clauses, Relative Clause Extraposition, and PP Extraposition

PÁZMÁNY PÉTER KATOLIKUS EGYETEM BÖLCSÉSZETTUDOMÁNYI KAR

Adjacency, PF, and extraposition

Modal Verbs. Modal verbs for BSL are Can, Must, Should, Want (these are productive requirements)

PS I TAM-TAM Aspect [20/11/09] 1

Linguistics, Psychology, and the Ontology of Language. Noam Chomsky s well-known claim that linguistics is a branch of cognitive

Phrase Structure Rules, Tree Rewriting, and other sources of Recursion Structure within the NP

Structure of Clauses. March 9, 2004

COMPARATIVES WITHOUT DEGREES: A NEW APPROACH. FRIEDERIKE MOLTMANN IHPST, Paris fmoltmann@univ-paris1.fr

Early Morphological Development

The Book of Grammar Lesson Six. Mr. McBride AP Language and Composition

EAP Grammar Competencies Levels 1 6

Estudios de Asia y Africa Idiomas Modernas I What you should have learnt from Face2Face

GMAT.cz GMAT.cz KET (Key English Test) Preparating Course Syllabus

Ling 201 Syntax 1. Jirka Hana April 10, 2006

IP PATTERNS OF MOVEMENTS IN VSO TYPOLOGY: THE CASE OF ARABIC

Continuous Acceptability, Categorical Grammaticality, and Experimental Syntax

Is there repair by ellipsis?

REPORTED SPEECH. Reported speech is used to retell or report what other person has actually said. It is a very usual function in everyday language.

How To Understand A Sentence In A Syntactic Analysis

Appendix to Chapter 3 Clitics

Linguistics, Psychology, and the Ontology of Language. Noam Chomsky s well-known claim that linguistics is a branch of cognitive

The Structure of English Language - Clause Functions

Section 8 Foreign Languages. Article 1 OVERALL OBJECTIVE

Compound Sentences and Coordination

TERMS. Parts of Speech

INFORMATION STRUCTURE ANNOTATION IN DanPASS. Patrizia Paggio August 2006

Wh-in-Situ and the Spanish DP: Movement or No Movement? Lara Reglero and Emma Ticio. 1 Introduction. 2 Two Theories of Wh-in-Situ

Refer to: Present & future If-clause Main clause. ZERO Present + Present. If you can meet me at the car, that s easiest for me.

MARY. V NP NP Subject Formation WANT BILL S

stress, intonation and pauses and pronounce English sounds correctly. (b) To speak accurately to the listener(s) about one s thoughts and feelings,

Lecture 9. Phrases: Subject/Predicate. English 3318: Studies in English Grammar. Dr. Svetlana Nuernberg

LESSON THIRTEEN STRUCTURAL AMBIGUITY. Structural ambiguity is also referred to as syntactic ambiguity or grammatical ambiguity.

On Dutch allemaal and West Ulster English all

Infinitives are Tenseless. Susi Wurmbrand * 1 Introduction. 2 Future Tense

Noam Chomsky: Aspects of the Theory of Syntax notes

COMPUTATIONAL DATA ANALYSIS FOR SYNTAX

Linguistics & Cognitive Science

MATRIX OF STANDARDS AND COMPETENCIES FOR ENGLISH IN GRADES 7 10

Ellipsis and Anaphora

Paraphrasing controlled English texts

A Beautiful Four Days in Berlin Takafumi Maekawa (Ryukoku University)

A Writer s Reference, Seventh Edition Diana Hacker Nancy Sommers

Structure of the talk. The semantics of event nominalisation. Event nominalisations and verbal arguments 2

Outline of today s lecture

Language as Cognitive Science

Clauses and phrases are the building blocks of sentences. A phrase is a

Prepositions. (Like conjunctions and determiners, prepositions can be seen as a kind of sentence glue)

The finite verb and the clause: IP

English Language (first language, first year)

Consequences of Antisymmetry for the syntax of headed relative clauses (dissertation abstract)

Annotation Guidelines for Dutch-English Word Alignment

Electronic offprint from. baltic linguistics. Vol. 3, 2012

According to the Argentine writer Jorge Luis Borges, in the Celestial Emporium of Benevolent Knowledge, animals are divided

English Subordinators in Finite Clause: Definition and Classification

Have to and the Scope of Modality

English Descriptive Grammar

English Appendix 2: Vocabulary, grammar and punctuation

Report of AG 1: Experimental and theoretical approaches to relative clauses reconciled

Mixed Sentence Structure Problem: Double Verb Error

Sentence Structure/Sentence Types HANDOUT

Historical Linguistics. Diachronic Analysis. Two Approaches to the Study of Language. Kinds of Language Change. What is Historical Linguistics?

Online Tutoring System For Essay Writing

2. PRINCIPLES IN USING CONJUNCTIONS. Conjunction is a word which is used to link or join words, phrases, or clauses.

Methodological Issues for Interdisciplinary Research

Can May Must Shall Will Could Might Should Would. Be able to Be supposed to Have to Ought to Have better Be going to Be to Have got to Used to

A discourse approach to teaching modal verbs of deduction. Michael Howard, London Metropolitan University. Background

Invited talks (in Hungary unless marked otherwise)

Transcription:

The structural deficiency of verbal pro-forms * Bill Haddican, University of York This squib discusses two kinds of verbal pro-forms in British English, do and do so. Examples of these forms are given in (1). (1) British English a. Terry will eat pasta and Ines will do, too. [With second sentence interpreted as, Ines will eat pasta. ] b. Terry will eat pasta and Ines will do so, too. [With second sentence interpreted as, Ines will eat pasta. ] In the spirit of Cardinaletti and Starke s (1999) typology of strong, weak and clitic pronouns, this squib argues that do is a structurally deficient relative of do so. In particular, while both of these pro-forms are headed by v, do but not do so, lacks a VP complement. This approach is shown to account for certain prosodic and semantic differences between these forms. The analysis, if correct, suggests that many of Cardinaletti and Starke s findings for pro-forms in the nominal domain may extend to pro-forms in verbal shells, and also lends support to Cardinaletti and Starke s approach to variation in the behavior of different pronoun classes as determined by relative differences in functional richness. 1

1. British do as a verbal pro-form As shown in (1), British English exhibits variation in VP-ellipsis constructions. Other varieties of English, including American English, lack the option in (1a). (2) American English Will she eat? *She should do. [on any reading] as in (3). In addition, British English, like other varieties of English, allows true elisions (3) British English Terry will eat pasta and Ines will, too. [With second sentence interpreted as, Ines will eat pasta. ] Baltin (2004, 2005) suggests that the do of (1a) is a pro-form. In particular, he points out that, from the perspective of sentences such as (1a) as true elisions, it is mysterious why elided constituents under do cannot contain internal structure. Whtraces, for example are impossible in the VP covered up by do, and inverse scope is likewise unavailable out of these constituents. 1 (4) (Baltin 2004) *Although I don t know which book Fred will read, I do know which book Tom will do. 2

(5) (Baltin 2004) Some man will read every book and some woman will do too. [Only interpretable with some scoping over every in both clauses.] Similar evidence to this effect comes from the fact that do is unavailable with ACD, comparative deletions and pseudo-gapping as illustrated in (6)-(8). (6) ACD * Bart can eat anything that Homer can do. (7) Comparative deletions * Bart can eat more than Homer can do. (8) Pseudo-gapping. *Although she won t eat pasta she will do pizza. Crucially, these properties of British do are shared by do so (in both British and American English), which is often taken to be a pro-form (Ross 1970, Johnson 2001, Stroik 2001, Horvath and Siloni 2003). (9) wh-extraction *Although I don t know which book Fred will read, I do know which book Tom will do so. 3

(10) inverse scope Some man will read every book and some woman will do so too. [Only interpretable with some scoping over every in both clauses.] (11) ACD *Bart can eat anything that Homer can do so. (12) Comparative deletions * Bart can eat more than Homer can do so. (13) Pseudo-gapping *Although she won t eat pasta she will do so pizza. 2. do vs. do so In view these data, let us follow Baltin (2005) in assuming that British do like do so is a verbal pro-form. A question that arises under this assumption, then, is whether the phonetic difference between these two forms correlates with any structural difference. I will argue that in fact it does, as suggested by the following differences between these forms. First, in do so constructions, stress may fall on do/did/does so as in (14). (14) Q: Has Ines eaten? A: I don t know, but she should DO so. 4

By contrast, do in sentences such as (1a) can never be stressed. In (15), for instance a do example parallel to (14) stress cannot fall on do. Rather, it obligatorily falls on the preceding modal. (15) Q: Has Ines eaten? A: I don t know, but she SHOULD do./*i don t know, but she should DO. Second, British do, unlike do so, cannot be separated from the preceding modal by parentheticals or epistemic adverbs such as obviously. 2 (16) I don t know if she ll come, but she should obviously do so. (17) *I don t know if she ll come, but she should obviously do. (18) I don t know if she ll come, but she should, it seems, do so. (19) *I don t know if she ll come, but she should, it seems, do. Third, British do, unlike do so tends to be poor under infinitival to, as illustrated by the contrast between (20) and (21). 3 (20)??I don t know if she ll come but she needs to do. (21) I don t know if she ll come but she needs to do so. antecedents. Fourth and finally, British do, unlike do so is compatible with non-agentive 5

(22) I don t know if she suffers from arthritis; she might do. (23) *I don t know if she suffers from arthritis; she might do so. (24) I don t know if it ll rain today but it might do. (25) *I don t know if it ll rain today but it might do so. 3. The structural deficiency of do Let us consider each of these differences in turn. First, the fact that British do, unlike do so, cannot be stressed or separated from the preceding modal by parentheticals and epistemic adverbs as illustrated in (15)-(17) suggests that it is a clitic. In addition, an approach to do as a clitic suggests an account of the fact that do, unlike do so, is poor below infinitival to. In particular, it seems plausible to relate the unavailability of do below to to the fact that to, unlike other modals, does not admit cliticization of not. (26) She tried not to go. (27) She tried to not go. (28) *She tried ton t go. Note, that it is not infinitival embedding per se that is incompatible with do, since participial done is fine in infinitives. (29) I don t know if she s turned in her paper, but she needs to have done. 6

In view of these facts, I will assume that do is in fact a clitic. An immediate difficulty for this approach, however, is that light-verb do in other environments does not seem to be particularly clitic-like. In pseudo-clefts such as (30), for example, do may be stressed. (30) What she DID was eat pasta. It can also be separated from surrounding material by obviously. (31) What she obviously DID was eat pasta. (32) What she DID, obviously, was eat pasta. In these respects, then, light-verb do seems to be rather un-clitic-like. Crucially, however, do in this guise, like do so, is incompatible with non-agentive predicates. (33) *What she DID, then, was suffer from her illness. The generalization, then, seems to be that if do is not a clitic, then it must be agentive. These facts recall Cardinaletti and Starke s (1999) observation that (prosodically/phonetically) strong pronouns are semantically restricted in ways that weak pronouns are not. In particular, weak pronouns, unlike strong pronouns, may be expletives and have impersonal interpretations and non-human referents. To account for these facts, Cardinaletti and Starke propose that strong pronouns contain an 7

additional functional layer CP lacked by weak pronouns. In the case of strong pronouns, this C head receives default values e.g. [+human] which accounts for their more restricted range of interpretations (Cardinaletti and Starke 1999:187-190). Cardinaletti and Starke further suggest that this structural difference is responsible for the prosodic differences between strong and weak pronouns. In particular, they propose that weak pronouns are prosodically dependent because they are not full CP s and therefore do not constitute a major syntactic constituent. Following Cardinaletti and Starke, let us assume that do is a structurally reduced relative of do so. On the standard assumption that light verbs like do are merged in v, a position above V, both do and do so might be viewed as headed by v (Baltin 2005, Stroik 2001). As Baltin (2005) suggests, however, do plausibly lacks a VP complement, as in (34). Crucially, the fact that do is compatible with nonagentive antecedents suggests that do may be a defective v. I will return to this property of do, shortly. (34) do [ v/v* do The form, do so, by contrast, is plausibly richer in structure. Stroik (2001), for example, proposes the structure in (35) for do so constructions. (35) do so (Stroik 2001) [ v* do [ VP so 8

Evidence in favor of this proposal comes from pseudo-clefts and wh-questions questioning the verb as in (36) and (37). As Stroik (2001) notes, the fact that what can range over VPs in such cases suggests that do is not a main verb in VP, but rather in a higher position, plausibly v. (36)=(30) What she DID was eat pasta. (37) Q: What will she do? A: Eat pasta. 4 Similar evidence comes from relative clauses of the kind in (38). (38) (Ross 1970) Ted left, which he shouldn t have done. I will adopt from Stroik s paper the idea that do and so are merged as distinct heads. I will depart from this proposal, however, in taking so to be merged not in V, but rather as a nominal complement of V as in (39). (39) do so [ v* do [ VP [ NP so 5 In particular, the fact that, in other environments, what is a nominal whelement suggests that wh-questions questioning the verb such as (36) and (37) involve a nominal complement. Additional evidence to this effect comes from the fact that in 9

some languages, including Basque the wh-element in wh-questions questioning the verb trigger object agreement on the auxiliary. (40) Zer egin du Inesek? What.ABS do-perf ABS.AUX.ERG Ines-ERG What has Ines done? replaced by it. Similarly, as Stroik (2001) notes, so can also (more marginally, perhaps) be (41) Q: Should I leave now? A: Don t do it. These facts, then, support a view of do so, and wh-questions questioning the verb as consisting of a light verb + nominal complement as illustrated in (39). In addition, such a view of do so suggests an account of the fact that do so is incompatible with non-agentive antecedents. That is, because do takes a nominal complement to which it assigns case, it cannot be a defective v head, but rather must be φ-complete in Chomskyan (2001) terms. By contrast, British do, which lacks complement structure, never need assign case and therefore may be defective. Under this view, then, several differences between weak and strong verbal pro-forms reduce to a single structural difference, namely whether the pro-form in question takes a complement VP. If, as suggested by Cardinaletti and Starke, prosodic weakness is a symptom of lacking a major category, then, the prosodic 10

weakness of British pro-form do, might plausibly be attributed to the fact that do lacks a complement VP and/or a nominal complement. By contrast, do so and the do of pseudo-clefts and wh-questions questioning the verb are not clitics because they take a complement VP (itself containing a nominal complement.) Similarly, the fact that do but not do so is compatible with non-agentive antecedents is plausibly attributable to the fact that the latter contains a case-marked nominal complement and therefore must have a non-defective v. 6 This proposal, if correct, suggests that Cardinaletti and Starke s basic approach to variation in the behavior of different pronoun classes in terms of differences in their functional makeup might plausibly extend to the lower functional sequence of the clause. References: Baltin, Mark. 2004. The position of adverbials. Ms., NYU, New York. Baltin, Mark. 2005. The non-unity of VP-Preposing. Ms. NYU, New York. To appear in Language. Cardinaletti, Anna and Michal Starke. 1999. The typology of structural deficiency: A case study of the three classes of pronouns. In Clitics in the Languages of Europe, ed. Henk van Riemsdijk, 145-233. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. Ken Hale: A life in language, ed. Michael Kenstowicz, 1-52. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Horvath, Barbara and Tal Siloni. 2003. Against the little-v hypothesis. In 11

Proceedings of the Israel Association for Theoretical Linguistics, 19. ed. Yehuda N. Falk. http://atar.mscc.huji.ac.il/%7eenglish/iatl/ Johnson, Kyle. 2001. What VP-Ellipsis can do, and what it can t, but not why. In The Handbook of Syntactic Theory, ed. Mark Baltin and C. Collins, 439-279, Oxford: Blackwell. Pollock, Jean Yves. 1989. Verb movement, universal grammar and the structure of IP. Linguistic Inquiry 20: 365-424. Ross, John R. 1970. Act. In Semantics of Natural Language, eds. D. Davidson and G. Harmon, 70-126. Dordrecht: Reidel. Stroik, Thomas. 2001. On the Light Verb Hypothesis. Linguistic Inquiry 32:2. Notes: * I am grateful to xx, xx, xx and xx for judgments and/or helpful discussions of the data presented here. All errors are my own. 1 Baltin (p.c.) notes that this characterization of British do as entirely lacking internal structure may be too strong. In particular, he observes the possibility of do with raising predicates as in (i). (i) John might seem to enjoy it and Fred might do, too. I will not attempt to explain this fact here. Whatever the analysis of such examples, the crucial point, for the purpose of the following discussion will be that do behaves like do so in crucial respects. 2 As xx (p.c.) points out, other adverbs, such as possibly more easily intervene between modals and do. (i) I don t know if she ll come, but she might possibly do. 12

I will set aside the issue of how to account for this difference between possibly and obviously/parentheticals. What is crucial for the purposes of the present discussion, is that parentheticals and epistemic adverbs, unlike possibly, tend to require an intonational break in such cases, which suggests that the relevant distinction is prosodic. 3 Many speakers find that sentences such as (20) improve when followed by additional material. (i) I don t know if she ll come but she needs to do soon. I will set aside the question of how to account for the difference between (20) and (i). For the purposes of the present discussion, it will suffice to observe the difference between (20) and (21). 4 Speakers typically accept nominal answers to questions like (37) e.g. the laundry though often find them less than fully cooperative. This suggests that in such cases, what preferably ranges over VPs. 5 As Horvath and Siloni (2003) note, nothing may intervene between do and so (cf. Stroik 2001). This suggests the possibility that so raises from V to v and encliticizes to do in such cases. 6 This proposal, if it is on the right track, might plausibly be extended to do-support (Richard Kayne p.c., cf. Pollock 1989:420 fn.49). Again, in the spirit of Cardinaletti and Starke s (1999) proposal, one might view the do/does/did of do-support as an even more deficient relative of do/do so. In particular, the do of do-support is similar to the behaviour of clitics in three ways. First, in constructions in which it appears, it doubles its referent in a way comparable to clitic-doubling in Romance. Second, do 13

in do-support canonically appears higher in the clause than its referent. This recalls Cardinaletti and Starke s generalization that weaker pronouns and clitics surface higher than stronger relatives. Third and finally, do, in its do-support guise often allow phonological reductions not available in the case of light verb do. (i) Who d you see. (ii) What you did was eat pasta. (iii) *What you d was eat pasta. Whether, in fact, do-support might be usefully analyzed as clitic doubling I will leave to further research. 14