Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) *

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) *"

Transcription

1 Published in Andrews Reath, Barbara Herman and Christine Korsgaard, Eds., Reclaiming the History of Ethics: Essays for John Rawls (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1997), available through Adrian M. S. Piper Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) * In 1951 John Rawls expressed these convictions about the fundamental issues in metaethics: [T]he objectivity or the subjectivity of moral knowledge turns, not on the question whether ideal value entities exist or whether moral judgments are caused by emotions or whether there is a variety of moral codes the world over, but simply on the question: does there exist a reasonable method for validating and invalidating given or proposed moral rules and those decisions made on the basis of them? For to say of scientific knowledge that it is objective is to say that the propositions expressed therein may be evidenced to be true by a reasonable and reliable method, that is, by the rules and procedures of what we may call "inductive logic"; and, similarly, to establish the objectivity of moral rules, and the decisions based upon them, we must exhibit the decision procedure, which can be shown to be both reasonable and reliable, at least in some cases, for deciding between moral rules and lines of conduct consequent to them. 1 In this passage Rawls reconfigured the issue of moral objectivity and so reoriented the practice of metaethics from linguistic analysis to rational methodology. In so doing, his work has provided inspiration to philosophers as disparate in normative views as Thomas Nagel, 2 Richard Brandt 3, Alan Gewirth 4, and David Gauthier. 5 Rawls replaced the Moorean question, Do moral terms refer? with the Rawlsian question, Can moral judgments be the outcome of a rational and reliable procedure? He later gave a resoundingly positive answer to this question 6 and later still, a more tentative one. 7 Rawls' considered qualification of his earlier enthusiasm about the extent to which moral philosophy could be "part of the theory of rational choice" 8 is a tribute to the seriousness with which he took his critics' objections. * APRA Foundation Berlin

2 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 2 The above passage, and the article from which it is excerpted, make clear that Rawls took his original inspiration from a carefully worked out analogy with inductive logic in scientific procedure. But a fellow traveler among rational methodologists in metaethics namely Kant risked defending an even closer and more controversial relationship between scientific and moral objectivity. I shall argue that Kant's thesis that the moral law is objectively necessary 9 relies on the same type and degree of objectivity he earlier claimed for scientific knowledge. Thus Rawls' youthful impatience with "speculative" metaethics, and the boldness of his claiming for ethics the same sort of procedural rigor to be found in the natural sciences, puts him in the best possible philosophical company: of those whose ambitions for moral philosophy and the philosophical powers by which they serve it are greatest. In the Groundwork Kant characterizes the moral law as an objective principle that compels imperfectly rational human beings with objective necessity (Ak ). Kant establishes the metaethical foundations and technical terminology for his conception of moral objectivity in the Analytic and Dialectic of the Critique of Pure Reason. 10 Although many of Kant's views undergo revision or development from the first Critique to the Groundwork to the second Critique, 11 we will see that the conceptual foundations Kant establishes early on for addressing the issue of moral objectivity remain firmly in place. I. Understanding A. Synthesis A representation, for Kant, is any mental content. Representations can be either intuitional or nonintuitional. Intuitional representations "get directly to" 12 an object that is given to us in sensibility (A 19/B 34). An intuitional representation organizes the data of sense in space and time, which Kant calls the forms of intuition. So only intuitional representations are directly of given objects. All nonintuitional representations are themselves of representations rather than directly of objects (A 68/B 93). Since intuitional representations are by definition of objects and not of other representations, and since empirical objects are themselves representations, the objects intuitional representations represent cannot be, in turn, empirical objects. Rather, they are objects in themselves apart from their representations. 13 A concept "orders various representations under one common representation" (A 68/B 93). We do this spontaneously in that this mental act is not a reaction to some

3 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 3 external cause, as sensation is (A 50/B 74, passim). Conceptualizing representations is something we initiate rather than something that is imposed upon us. This, Kant thinks, is what it means to be an intelligence (B 158, n.). And to conceive ourselves in this way as active, spontaneously reasoning and thinking agents is to conceive ourselves as persons. 14 The representations we conceptualize can be either intuitional or nonintuitional. They have in common what is expressed by the representation that subsumes them. The common representation is the concept that unifies the various representations under it. A concept, then, is a rule of selection for collecting mental contents similar in a certain respect under the rubric of that concept; or, as Kant also puts it, a function (A 79/B 105). "Since," Kant tells us, "no representation other than intuition gets directly to the object, a concept is never in unmediated relation to an object, but rather to some other representation of it (be it an intuition, or itself a concept)" (A 68/B 93). Concepts, therefore, mediate and qualify our relation to externally given objects. Synthesis is Kant's technical term for the process by which different, specifically intuitional representations are collected under one concept. Synthesis is collection when applied specifically to intuitional representations. It is, Kant tells us, "the act of adding different representations together, and of grasping their manifoldness in one cognition" (A 77/B 103). Synthesis supplies order and continuity to our moment-tomoment sense experience (A ). It also unites intuitional representations into a particular, identifiable content (A 78/B 103). This content is what the concept that unites them expresses. So intuitional representations are synthesized according to a particular rule of selection, and this rule can be inferred from the content of the concept under which they are subsumed. What determines the content of that rule of selection? That is, what determines which similarities among intuitional representations are relevant to their synthetic grouping under concepts? Kant uses the term "synthesis" specifically in connection with intuitional representations, and intuitional representations are direct and unmediated representations of externally given objects in themselves. So it would be tempting to think that the similarities represented were similarly given by those objects; and therefore that the basis for our grouping of representations was to be traced to attributes of those objects themselves. But Kant thinks that the similarities most salient to us, and therefore the best candidates for conceptual synthesis, are those which most

4 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 4 closely conform to the innate conceptual preconceptions we bring to the act of cognitive discrimination. The concepts that select and group intuitional representations are what Kant calls the pure transcendental concepts of the understanding, or categories. These include substance and attribute, and cause and effect. These pairs are not analytic, i.e. conjoined by definition as are the concepts of a bachelor and an unmarried man. Rather, they are conjoined in the spatiotemporal form of our intuitional representations. And since, according to Kant, they are innate, logically necessary 15 and universal concepts, they are cognitive preconditions for experiencing something as a coherent and unified object at all. B. Judgment Kant thinks that "the understanding can make no other use of these concepts other than to judge by means of them" (A 68/B 93). A judgment more specifically, a categorical judgment that ascribes predicate to subject does exactly what concepts do, only at a more abstract level: it collects relevantly similar representations that are already subsumed under a less abstract concept under a more abstract concept (A 79/B 105). A synthetic a priori judgment, then, is an innate, logically necessary and universal judgment that collects intuitional representations under the pure concepts of the understanding listed in the Table of Categories (A 80/B 106). Kant tells us that by abstracting from the content of any such judgment and "attending only to the mere form of [our] understanding" (A 70/B 95), we can cull the formal rules of selection among representations. These are the logical forms of judgment set out by Kant in their entirety in the Table of Judgment (A 70/ B 95). So whereas the categories of the understanding listed in the Table of Categories combine the innate, logically necessary and universal rules for collecting representations with specifically intuitional representations, the logical forms of judgment listed in the Table of Judgments abstract from both intuitional and nonintuitional representations. Subtract representations themselves from the conceptual rules for collecting them and you get the logical forms of those rules. Among the representations subsumed by a judgment under any concept, whether transcendental or empirical, there will be at least one which is intuitional, i.e. in

5 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 5 direct relation to a given object."[a]ll judgments," Kant says, "are functions of unity among our representations, since instead of an unmediated representation, a higher one, which comprises this and more, are used in knowing the object, and thereby many possible cognitions are gathered into one" (A 69/B 94). Thus the underlying structure of the categorical judgment, "All bodies are divisible," might look something like this: r5 : divisibility } mediated relation to object r4 : body, area, real number, etc. } mediated relation to object r3 : sentient creature, table, rock, etc. } mediated relation to object r2 : Transcendental Object = X 16 }(= fits categories of substance/attributes, cause/effect) } mediated relation to object r1 : intuitions: (= appearances) } unmediated relation to object thing in itself =??? (= [noumenal] object[s]) In this judgment, relevantly similar intuitional representations of (a) given noumenal object(s) r1 are synthesized under the transcendental concept of an object r2, to which certain categories apply, such as substance/accident and cause/effect. These situate the appearance of the object in space and time. They also define what it is for something to be an object of our experience. We must represent it as a discrete substance with attributes. We must also represent it as both having and being susceptible to causal force. Once we become aware of something as satisfying the cognitive criteria for being an object, we are in the realm of empirical objects of experience. Here we next try to ascertain what kind of object it is. We collect observational representations under higher-level empirical attributes. Representations of the relevantly similar empirical attributes of that object are in turn collected under a more abstract empirical concept r3, that of a sentient creature; that representation, in turn, along with representations of other relevantly similar three-dimensional entities under a yet more abstract concept r4, that of a body; and that representation, finally,

6 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 6 along with representations of other similarly individuated but non-three dimensional entities under the even more abstract concept r5, divisibility. So on the one hand, all higher concepts or representations implicitly embed externally given objects in the judgments we make, no matter how tenuous or distanced our conceptual connection to those objects. On the other, any nonintuitional representation distances us from the object to some extent, including the representations "I", "I think," or "is my experience." All of our experience is theoryladen in this way. This is what Kant means when he says that "[j]udgment is... the mediate knowledge of an object, that is, the representation of a representation of it" (A 68/B 93). Any cognition that I can recognize and represent as mine is thereby distanced from sensibility and mediated by that judgment itself. On Kant's view, being "detached" from my "feelings" is the necessary price of unifed selfhood. C. Categorical Indicatives The two logical forms of judgment of interest for this discussion are the first two under "III. Relation," in the Table of Judgments of the first Critique, the categorical and the hypothetical. Relational judgments generally connect a priori concepts that have already synthesized intuitional representations. Categorical judgments more specifically, categorical indicative judgments have the form, "All (or some) A is B." Categorical indicatives relate the predicate concept to the subject concept by way of the representations subsumed under each. An example would be the judgment, "The human soul is immortal." A second example would be "All bodies are divisible." Both examples relate predicate to subject, but only the second relates attributes to substances because the first is true by definition of the concept of a soul, whereas the second connects intuitional (as well as nonintuitional) representations of objects. Hypothetical judgments have the form, "If P then Q." Hypothetical judgments relate two categorical indicative judgments as antecedent (or, to use Kant's technical term, ground) to consequent. For example, the hypothetical judgment, "If there is a perfect justice, the obstinately wicked are punished," relates the two categorical indicatives, "There is a perfect justice," and "The obstinately wicked are punished" (A 73/B 98). Another example of a hypothetical judgment would be, "If one answers the telephone, it ceases ringing." This one relates the two categorical indicatives, "One

7 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 7 answers the telephone," 17 and "The telephone ceases ringing." Both examples relate antecedent to consequent, but only the second relates cause to effect, and again the reason is the same. The first is true by definition of the concept of perfect justice, whereas the second connects intuitional representations of objects. At B 141 fn. and A 73/B 98 - A74/B 99 Kant inveighs against the reduction of hypothetical and disjunctive judgment forms to the categorical. 18 Nevertheless he is wrong. Disjunctive judgments can be translated into hypothetical ones, and any hypothetical judgment can be replaced by a categorical one that ascribes to the subject a complex property, such as that of being an antecedent to the consequent or a cause of the effect. For example, the above two hypothetical judgments can instead be rendered as "Perfect justice requires punishing the wicked," and "Answering the telephone stops its ringing." By reducing the number of judgment forms Kant claims to be transcendentally necessary to the categorical and extending its scope to cover antecedental and causal predicates, Kant's argument for the objectivity of empirical knowledge is strengthened, not weakened as he seems to think. The reason is that categorical indicatives have a special status in Kant's theory; and in the B Deduction Kant explains what it is: [A categorical indicative] judgment is nothing other than the way to bring given cognitions to the objective unity of apperception. This is what the relational term "is" aims at: to distinguish the objective unity of given representations from the subjective. It denotes their relation to original apperception, and its necessary unity, even if the judgment itself is empirical, and therefore contingent, as for example, in the judgment, "Bodies are heavy." I.. here assert that these representations... belong to one another in virtue of the necessary unity of apperception in the synthesis of intuitions... Only thus does there arise from this relation a judgment, that is, a relation which is objectively valid, and so can be adequately distinguished from a relation of the same representations that would have only subjective validity, for example according to laws of association. In the latter case, I would only be able to say, "When I carry a body, I feel an impression of weight"; but not, "It, the body, is heavy;" which is as much as to say that these two representations are bound together in the object, i.e. without regard to the state of the subject, and not merely in perception (as often as that perception may be repeated) (B 142).

8 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 8 Kant's point is that the relational term that connects predicate with subject in a categorical indicative judgment and it is a point that would apply as well to "has the attribute of" as it does to "is" objectifies that connection as being in the object rather than in the subject. To recognize the connection of representations as being in the object is to recognize the representations that constitute that object as epistemically distinct from those that constitute the subject. Now the logical function of judgment, Kant tells us, is to collect all such representations, whether intuitional or conceptual, in one consciousness, or apperception; that is, to finally subsume all of them under the concept "I think" (B 143). This means that necessarily, I must be able to conceive of any such representation, concept or judgment, no matter how abstract or removed from sensibility, as mine in order for it to be part of my consciousness. But the representations that collectively comprise the representation of a unified object presuppose a unified conscious subject the transcendental unity of apperception in which those representations are ordered and collected according to innate, logically necessary, and universal concepts. Therefore, a categorical indicative asserts a connection among representations that is as objective as anything can be for us. Kant s doctrine of transcendental idealism clearly rejects any concept of empirical objectivity as consisting in the ontological independence of the object. And the Analogies demonstrate Kant s attempts to ground the objectivity of objects and causally related events in an analysis of temporally sequential representations. Objectivity, for Kant, is objectivity of knowledge, not the ontological independence of the object from the knowing subject. On Kant's view, objectivity just is the conceptual a priority, logical necessity, and universality of judgment about the object. 19 Even if we concede Kant his insistence on the essential difference between categorical, hypothetical and disjunctive judgments, however, hypothetical and disjunctive judgments both still embed categorical indicatives that implicitly assert objective relations between subject and predicate. Therefore, all such relational judgments implicitly presuppose the objectivity of these relations. Whether the telephone ceases ringing because I answer it or not may be open to question; that I answer it, and that it ceases ringing, is not. But all such empirical hypothetical judgments presuppose the transcendental forms of judgment that unify a priori intuitional representations. Kant describes all of

9 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 9 the synthetic a priori judgments that comprise the Table of Categories as universal rules of unity in the synthesis of appearances that have objective reality as necessary conditions of experience (A 157/B 196). What he means is that the relational judgment forms (inter alia) we find in the Table of Judgments, when applied to the synthesis of intuitional representations, further objectify those representations by linking them in the form of discriminable events and entities. These empirical events and entities are, from the point of view of my experience, fully objective and veridical. A fortiori, the hypothetical judgment form synthesizes intuitional representations already objectified by their categorical indicative form into a causal relation that, from the point of view of experience, objectifies them even further. 20 II. Reason A. Ideas In the Analytic of the first Critique, Kant has tried to show that the logical forms of relational judgment listed in the Table of Judgments, when combined with intuitional representations, yield objective knowledge. In the Dialectic he tries to show that these same three logical functions, when extended beyond intuitional representations, yield increasingly abstract, comprehensive concepts and theories that encompass all lowerlevel representations; and finally yield transcendent and transcendental ideas of reason. Kant defines an idea or concept of reason as "a concept formed from [pure concepts of the understanding] that transcends the possibility of experience" (A 320/B 377). Ideas are highly abstract concepts that unify less abstract concepts of a certain kind under a single, comprehensive concept. An idea can be a theoretical entity (such as a perfectly rational being or a quark), a theoretical law (such as that of freedom or relativity) or a concept strictly speaking (such as immortality or the unified field). Ideas deal only indirectly with experience (B 359), since "an object that would be adequate to the transcendental idea can never be found within experience" (A 327/B 384). However, these most sweepingly universal concepts do not abstract from intuitional representations, but instead embed them in more abstract and general judgments. Thus when Kant characterizes reason as the faculty of principles, and knowledge from principles as "that knowledge in which I cognize the particular in the universal through concepts" (A 299/B 356-A 300/B 357), he is making the same point about the theory-ladenness of experience he made at A 68/B 93-A 69/B 94 discussed in

10 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 10 Section I.B, but at a higher level of abstraction. Reason, he says, is the faculty of judging mediately (A 330/B 386). There are many ideas of reason. 21 But Kant claims that the three most abstract, comprehensive and universal ones are engendered by the three relational judgment forms themselves. We have seen in Section I.A that when these judgment forms apply to to the intuitional data of sense they yield the categories. But when their scope of application is extended sufficiently far beyond the data of sense they yield the higherlevel concepts Kant calls ideas (A 323/B 380). First, there is the idea of immortality, which he argues is engendered by universalizing the categorical judgment form: The search for completeness and comprehensiveness of predication yields the concept of a subject which is never a predicate. Since ideas of reason must unify intuitional as well as nonintuitional representations and lower-level principles, this, in turn, according to Kant, becomes the idea of "the absolute unity of the thinking subject" (A 335/B 392), which itself undergoes no change. 22 Second, there is the idea of freedom, which is engendered by universalizing the hypothetical judgment form: In hypothetical reasoning, the search for completeness and comprehensiveness in the series of antecedents of a consequent yields the concept of the original antecedent without antecedents the groundless ground. Because it, too, must unify intuitional as well as nonintuitional representations, it, in turn, yields the idea of freedom as the first or uncaused cause of everything, the "absolute totality of the series of conditions for any given appearance" (A 340/B 398). Of course a judgment characterizing a groundless ground or first cause could also be rendered as a categorical indicative that predicates the consequent as a property of the antecedent qua subject that cannot be predicated of any further subject. A judgment ascribing an action to a free agent would, for example, satisfy this criterion. Finally, there is the idea of God, which is engendered by universalizing the disjunctive judgment form: Here the search for completeness and comprehensiveness in the set of disjuncts that jointly exhaust the scope of a concept (A 73/B 99) yields the concept of the aggregate of all disjuncts of the most complete concept; and this becomes the idea of God as the totality of all parts of the system, the "being of all beings" (A 336/B 393). In the Dialectic Kant tries to show how all of these ideas of reason naturally develop as higher-level universal principles from the conceptual presuppositions or

11 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 11 Grund of objective empirical knowledge, namely the logically necessary functions of thought. He characterizes these ideas, and the reasoning by which we arrive at them, in the same indicative mood as he did the concepts of the understanding and the synthetic process of judgment by which we unify and objectify our experience. Kant argues that, being committed to the objectivity of our empirical experience, we then must be committed to the regulative authority of the abstract theories and universal principles it engenders. Since they transcend the empirically verifiable, we cannot experientially confirm their truth. But since they naturally arise out of it, we cannot easily reject them either. B. Vernunftschlüsse 23 Kant's account of the way in which ideas of reason are engendered from objective knowledge is based on his conception of cognitive functions as fundamentally spontaneous i.e. active rather than reactive and synthetic that is, unifying rather than particularizing. We saw in Section I.A that concepts collect representations, and in Section I.B that relational judgments collect concepts. Similarly, syllogisms, or inferences of reason Vernunftschlüsse collect relational judgments (A 301/B 358). Therefore inferences of reason indirectly collect representations and concepts. 24 Whereas the understanding collects intuitional representations under lawlike concepts, reason collects what we've conceptualized under yet more abstract and universal explanatory principles that organize and unify them in relation to each other (A 302/B 359). Kant thinks we are so constituted cognitively as to strive naturally to reduce, simplify, and extend the explanatory scope of theoretical principles to cover the greatest variety of intuitional and nonintuitional representations. Reason embeds the particulars of experience in universal judgments that define the broadest possible theoretical framework because to universalize over the particulars of experience is a natural and necessary expression of the self's striving for rational coherence. 25 According to Kant, the forms a Vernunftschluß can take depend on the logical form of judgment employed. Again the categorical and hypothetical forms are most important for our purposes, and the categorical form is the foundation from which the others are constructed:

12 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 12 categorical (indicative): hypothetical (indicative): Major Premise: All A are B. If D is E then F is G. Minor Premise: All/Some C are A. D is E. Conclusion: All/Some C are B. F is G. In each case the major premise is a given judgment stating a universal rule that ascribes a predicate to all subjects of a certain kind (A 322/ B 379). The minor premise is a judgment that subsumes a second subject, or condition, under the concept of the first. And the conclusion yields a further judgment by applying the universal rule of the major premise to the subsumed condition of the minor premise. A condition, for Kant, is a certain kind of state of affairs. In a categorical indicative judgment that functions as a premise in a categorical Vernunftschluß, it is the referent of the subject of the antecedent in the major premise (and, of course, of the subject of the minor premise). 26 Thus a condition functions as does the premise whose subject refers to it, as an antecedent from which some consequent or conclusion can be inferred (this is why Kant sometimes uses the terms condition and premise interchangeably). The conclusion then describes the conditioned (A 330/B A331/B 387), and the major premise conditions the conclusion: that is, it explains the condition or subject described in the conclusion by subsuming it under a general rule. Reason seeks to subsume that kind of subject under more and more abstract and universal kinds in a series of increasingly general judgments. Take the categorical indicativevernunftschluß, (1) Major Premise: All humans are mortal. Minor Premise: Caius is human. Conclusion: Caius is mortal. The major premise of (1) may be in turn the conclusion of even more general and abstract ones, such as (2) Major Premise: All sentient creatures are mortal. Minor Premise: All humans are sentient creatures. Conclusion: All humans are mortal.

13 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 13 And the minor premise of (1) also may be conditioned by prior Vernunftschlüsse, such as (3) Major Premise: All featherless bipeds are human. Minor Premise: Caius is a featherless biped. Conclusion: Caius is human. In both cases reason seeks more general and abstract principles under which a judgment can be subsumed, and from which it can be derived. For any Vernunftschluß, both of its premises can be regarded as conditioned by the more general Vernunftschluß from which they are derived as conclusions. The principle of reason in general, according to Kant, is "to find for the conditioned knowledge of the understanding the unconditioned whereby its unity is completed" (A 307/B 364). This then becomes a regulative principle of pure reason on the presupposition that "if the conditioned is given, the whole series of conditions subordinated to one another, which itself is therefore unconditioned is also given..." A regulative principle is one that guides and directs our innate patterns of reasoning in a way that enables us to extend it past the empirical limits of experience (A 509/B 537). It contrasts with a constitutive principle that defines and determines objectively the existence of some object or state of affairs. The regulative principle of pure reason, then, leads us to seek that most abstract, universal and all-inclusive first principle or Grund from which everything else can be deduced. 27 Thus in order to generalize over such principles to increasing degrees of abstraction, Kant argues, we must assume a totality of such conditions (or premises) for any given conditioned (or subject to which those predicates are ascribed in the conclusion). The complete series of conditions contained in prior universal judgments that determine a conclusion about some object or state of affairs is what Kant calls the unconditioned (A 322/B 379). The unconditioned, then, is the idea of a first and most abstract, universal idea or descriptive principle that functions as a premise subsuming all lower-level descriptive principles or premises under itself. This idea of the unconditioned leads us to try to generate a series of Vernunftschlüsse whose major premises increase in generality and comprehensiveness relative to the particular facts

14 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 14 (or "empirical conditions") with which it begins what Kant describes as the ascending or regressive series (A 331/B 388). The transcendental ideas of God, freedom and immortality are unconditioned in that they express the most abstract and universal principles under which all lower-level disjunctive, hypothetical and categorical Vernunftschlüsse respectively must finally be subsumed (A 336/B A 337/B 395). According to Kant, we know that these are the most comprehensive and universal principles there are because, as we have already seen above, they are derived by universalizing the forms of principles in which reasoning itself occurs. Beyond these most fundamental explanatory principles, Kant thinks, there are no further principles that might subsume them. Just as experience defines the limits of understanding, the ideas of God, freedom and immortality define the limits of reason. C. Hypothesis Construction According to Kant, we embark on the ascending series of Vernunftschlüsse in our search for eventual theoretical completeness by formulating and testing general hypotheses that are intended to explain an increasing variety of particular events. This process of theory-building, the prototype of Hempel's covering-law theory of scientific explanation, 28 Kant describes as the hypothetical employment of reason: If reason is a faculty of deducing the particular from the universal, then either the universal is already certain in itself and given, and so requires only judgment for subsumption, and the particular is thereby necessarily determined; or else the universal is given only problematically, and is a mere idea. Here the particular is certain, but the universality of the rule from which it follows is still a problem. Then more particular instances, each of which are certain, try on the rule for size to see whether they follow from it. In this case, if it appears that all particular instances assigned do follow from it, then we conclude to the universality of the rule, and thence to all instances, even those not themselves given (A 646/B 674). The procedure is clear. We begin with a universalization we rationally suppose to be true, and a firmly established particular case we rationally suppose might instantiate it. We scrutinize several relevantly similar particular cases in order to ascertain whether they do, indeed, instantiate the universalization, such that the formulation of the universalization allows the derivation of the particular instances from it: Does

15 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 15 universalizing over the particular instances yield the universal from which they are supposed to be derived? Does the resulting rule apply not only to these cases, but also to all relevantly similar ones? If the relevant instances, and other citable ones, can be derived from the universalization, we are then justified in regarding it as a valid universal principle that will predict and subsume future instances of that kind. 29 The example Kant offers combines the ideas of God, freedom, and immortality in the idea of rational personhood as a substance with causal power. This is a particularly apt example in light of Kant's project of establishing metaethical foundations in the first Critique for the substantive moral theory he first invokes to illustrate moral reasoning in the Groundwork. There he argues that "because moral laws should be valid for every rational being as such, to derive them from the universal concept of a rational being in general is thereby to explicate all moral philosophy, which needs anthropology for its application to human beings, first independently from this as pure philosophy, i.e. entirely as metaphysics (which can very well be done in this kind of wholly abstract knowledge)" (Ak. 412). The concept of a rational being in general is thus both the highest-level idea of reason that unifies the ideas of God, freedom and immortality; and also the most fundamental concept of morality. Beginning with various established mental dispositions "sensation, consciousness, memory, wit, power of discrimination, inclination (Lust), desire, etc." (A 649/B 677) Kant directs us to employ the "logical maxim through which we reduce, so far as possible, this seeming diversity, so that through comparison one might discover hidden identity." By sorting them into nonredundant groups and universalizing over them we collect them under higher-level principles such as imagination plus consciousness; then under the more general headings of understanding and reason; then under the yet more general explanatory principle of a fundamental power, i.e. a substance with causality, which each such disposition instantiates. Notice that this is one example of the reduction of a hypothetical judgment to a categorical one, i.e. through the ascription of causal properties to substances. But this is a very particular kind of causal substance, namely one that has mental powers with causal efficacy. Finally, Kant says, we may subsume all such causally powerful substances under the principle of an absolutely fundamental power that underlies all relative ones (A 649/B 677). But he cautions us, "This unity of reason is merely hypothetical. It is not claimed that such 30 must in fact be encountered, but that we seek it for the benefit of

16 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 16 reason, that is, of establishing certain principles for the many rules which experience may offer us" (A 649/B A 650/B 678; see also A 682/B 710). The concept of the soul as a self-identical and unchanging entity with the causal powers of understanding and reason can be invoked to explain the diverse manifestations of consciousness. And the concept of God can be invoked to explain the existence of such causally powerful substances. But these are only concepts (or ideas), not empirical experiences. Therefore they are not themselves susceptible to empirical confirmation. They are merely regulative ideas of reason that unify the diversity of our particular experiences. On the one hand, this employment of reason itself remains hypothetical because the ideas of God, freedom and immortality are merely hypotheses that explain our experience rather than statements of fact about our experience. As Kant later remarks about the idea of immortality, "one posits (sich setzen) an idea merely as the one and only point of view from which one can extend that unity which is so essential to reason and so beneficial to the understanding" (A 681/B 709; italics added). To say, however, that ideas of reason are regulative hypotheses is not thereby to underestimate their foundational necessity in human thought. Kant makes it quite clear that the validity of any such regulative hypothesis turns on its ability to unify our experience, our thought, and finally our selves in accordance with the demands of logical necessity. 31 So to the formula for Kant's account of objectivity earlier adduced conceptual a priority, logical necessity, and universality of judgment, reason adds something more, namely theoretical coherence. A higher-level theoretical principle of reason is objectively valid if it subsumes its lower-level principles, concepts, and representations, both intuitional and nonintuitional, under it, such that it allows the systematic inference of those lowerlevel principles, concepts, and representations as logically necessary syllogistic conclusions. Only then can the self be fully unified and the rules of understanding be true. III. Action In this section I apply the conclusions of the preceding account of Kant's models of understanding and reason to the special case of action, following Kant's claim in the Preface to the Groundwork that the unity of practical with speculative reason simultaneously in a common principle must be able to be delineated, since in the end there can be only one and the

17 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 17 same reason, which must be differentiated solely in its application (Ak. 391; italics added). A. Maxims Earlier, in Section I.C, we saw that intuitional representations are synthesized by the categories of the understanding first and foremost into categorical indicatives that claim a certain degree of objectivity in virtue of their form. We also saw that these are then further synthesized into hypothetical indicatives, that is, descriptive causal judgments that are, from the perspective of one's own experience, even more objective. The objectivity of this causal relation holds as much for human actions and consequences as it does for other causally linked events. Action and passion, according to Kant, are pure derivative concepts, or predicables of the pure understanding, derived from the category of cause and effect (A 82/B 108). Since action and passion are transcendental concepts, they, too, synthesize intuitional representations into objects and events. 32 This means that as agents and patients of action, we experience ourselves as genuine empirical causes and effects, and our actions as causally effective events in the world. To me, the causal link between my action and its consequences is as objective and lawlike as any other causal regularity I perceive. The descriptions by which we encode our actions conceptually are no different in form than those by which we encode other causally linked events. They are reducible to categorical indicatives that ascribe causal properties, namely actions, to agents. 33 The "accordion effect" 34 of action-descriptions makes it possible to ascribe a range of such properties, depending on the causal scope of the action the description is intended to capture. So, for example, "I (will) answer the telephone" captures a more restricted causal scope than "I (will) stop the ringing of the telephone." 35 Each expresses a different intention but both may describe the same physical action. Kant's primary concern is with action-descriptions that capture a more restricted causal scope and so a narrower intention, for two reasons. First, he is concerned primarily with our immediate intentions, regardless of their further actual causal consequences, because our intentions are for him the primary locus of moral value. On Kant's view, the rightness or wrongness of actions are derivative from the goodness or badness of our intentions. 36 And second, he thinks that only the immediate objects of our intentions,

18 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 18 and certain basic actions 37 (i.e. the "exerting of every means so far as they are in our power" (Ak. 394)), are under our direct control (Ak. 401). 38 A maxim is a first-person categorical indicative judgment that ascribes a causal property, namely an act, to the subject. It thus both expresses an intention and describes an action. For this reason it may function as a resolution or as a prediction respectively or both simultaneously. It may also describe a mental or a physical act. Kant derives the term "maxim" from the notion of a maximum as the rational idea of what is "greatest and absolutely complete... in the division and unification of the knowledge of the understanding under one principle" (A 665/B 693). We have already seen in Sections II.B and C that the role of reason is to unify the knowledge of understanding under fewer, increasingly abstract and comprehensive higher-level principles. We have also seen above that Kant includes among the objects of knowledge of the understanding knowledge of our actions and of ourselves as agents. Kant defines maxims of reason as all subjective principles which are derived, not from the constitution of the object but from the [speculative] interest of reason in respect of a certain possible perfection of the knowledge of the object (A 666/B 694). Maxims may include principles of thought (such as "I will gather as much relevant information as possible before drawing any conclusions") as well as of action. What all maxims have in common is that they are guided by reason's interest in theoretical completeness. In the case of action, then, we seek an idea of reason a highest-level comprehensive explanatory principle that enables us to understand all of our intentions and resolutions as theoretically coherent principles of action derivable from it and therefore, as we have seen in Section II.C, as objectively valid in light of it. When Kant moves from a formal analysis of how reason operates in general to the content of a particular idea of reason, he moves from rational procedure in general to its application to a substantive theory. In the Canon of Pure Reason Kant describes the idea of reason that guides the formulation of maxims. It is the idea of a world ruled by moral law a necessary idea of reason (A 812/B 840) that has objective reality (A 808/B 836) "in the concept of which we abstract from all the hindrances to morality (the inclinations)" (A 809/B 837). Kant's idea of a moral world comprises two elements: an entire world as a theoretical entity; and a system of operative principles moral law that is universally binding on it. Since in this world moral law is fully operative in the

19 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 19 behavior of its inhabitants, it explains and describes their behavior. And since it consciously guides their actions as well, it also prescribes it. Finally, since the moral law is authored by those inhabitants themselves, it describes and prescribes action that is rationally self-determining. The concept of rationally self-determining action, uncoerced by empirical antecedents, is an application of the principle of self-caused causation, i.e. of transcendental freedom, to the special case of rational agency. 39 Kant's conception of unconditioned moral freedom, that is, as freedom to act in accordance with moral selfdetermination, is not different or separate from the highest-level unconditioned idea of freedom, but instead an instantiation of it in a particular kind of cause. 40 Between the Resolution of the Third Antinomy and the Groundwork Kant preserves the consistency of his conception of unconditioned moral freedom with his accounts of God, freedom and immortality as furnishing highest-level regulative ideas that govern and unify our patterns of thought. All lower-level principles describing causally connected experience of any kind, whether action, desire, free association, or external events, must terminate in the unconditioned idea of freedom. So the criteria of objectivity remain the same for all of them. The unconditioned speculative idea of freedom as autonomous and operative moral law in turn provides the practical foundation for moral conduct. For from the interest of reason in the idea of a perfect world governed by moral law (which for Kant is also "a mere idea" (A 813/B 841); also see Groundwork, Ak. 407, 409, 412, 433, 434, 436 n., 439), we then derive the subjective principles that actually govern our moral agency: Practical laws, in so far as they become at the same time subjective grounds of actions, that is, subjective principles, are entitled maxims. The judgment of morality, regarding its purity and consequences, happens in accordance with ideas, the adherence to its laws in accordance with maxims (A 812/B 840). So we evaluate moral law as a speculative idea of reason; and we follow moral law by deriving practicable maxims from it. To the extent that moral laws are antecedents of a subject's actions, they are maxims; and the entire course of our lives are necessarily subject to them (A 812/B 840). Maxims of action such as "I (will) answer the telephone" or "I (will) return borrowed books" are lower-level conceptualized intentions, derivable as conclusions from higher-level moral principles, and finally from the highest-level unconditioned idea of a world governed by autonomous moral law, i.e. from the idea of

20 Adrian M. S. Piper: Kant on the Objectivity of the Moral Law (1994) 20 freedom. The relationship between maxims and moral ideas, then, is the relation between particular intentional action-descriptions and the more universal and comprehensive principles that explain them. B. Universalization By now it should be clear how we get from one to the other. To move from practicable maxims to the highest-level theoretical principle of operative, universal moral law from which those maxims are derived, we enact exactly the same procedure we use in any rational inquiry, namely hypothesis-construction of the sort described in Section II.C and exemplified in the idea of a causally powerful substance. In the case of action, we begin with both a prereflective rational idea of moral law (Ak ), and also an established particular intention to act. In light of this prereflective conception, we consider several such relevantly similar intentions. These are ex hypothesi certain, whereas "the universal is admitted as... a mere idea,... [and]... the universality of the rule of which [the intention's maxim] is a consequence is still a problem" (A 646/B 674). 41 So we scrutinize these intentions in order to ascertain whether they do, indeed, instantiate the moral law, such that the formulation of the moral law allows the derivation of the particular intentions from it. Again we deploy the "logical maxim through which to reduce, so far as possible, this seeming diversity, so that through comparison one might discover hidden identity" (A 649/B 677). That is, we ascertain whether universalizing over the maxims yields the rule from which they are to be derived, such that the resulting rule applies not only to these established cases, but to all relevantly similar ones. If the relevant intentions, and other citable ones, can be derived from this formulation of the moral law, we are then justified in regarding it as a universal principle that may predict and subsume future instances of that kind. Kant's remarks about hypothesis-construction in the first Critique provides a more complete account of his universalization procedure for moral maxims than is to be found anywhere in the Groundwork. As we have already seen in Section II.B, universalizing a principle that functions as a major premise in a Vernunftschluß results in a categorical indicative that ascribes a predicate to all subjects of a certain kind. And we have also seen in Section II.C that in the Groundwork, Kant tells us to ascend in the series to the most universal and comprehensive principle of action from which lower-level maxims can be derived,

ON EXTERNAL OBJECTS By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

ON EXTERNAL OBJECTS By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) ON EXTERNAL OBJECTS By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) General Observations on The Transcendental Aesthetic To avoid all misapprehension, it is necessary to explain, as clearly as possible,

More information

Kant s Dialectic. Lecture 3 The Soul, part II John Filling jf582@cam.ac.uk

Kant s Dialectic. Lecture 3 The Soul, part II John Filling jf582@cam.ac.uk Kant s Dialectic Lecture 3 The Soul, part II John Filling jf582@cam.ac.uk Overview 1. Re-cap 2. Second paralogism 3. Third paralogism 4. Fourth paralogism 5. Summing-up Critique of Pure Reason Transcendental

More information

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals G. J. Mattey Winter, 2015/ Philosophy 1 The Division of Philosophical Labor Kant generally endorses the ancient Greek division of philosophy into

More information

How To Understand The Moral Code Of A God (For Men)

How To Understand The Moral Code Of A God (For Men) Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.0 Richard Baron 27 February 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4

More information

Inner sense and time

Inner sense and time Inner sense and time Ralf M. Bader Merton College, University of Oxford 1 Introduction According to Kant, inner and outer sense have different forms. Whereas space is the form of outer sense, time is the

More information

Phil 420: Metaphysics Spring 2008. [Handout 4] Hilary Putnam: Why There Isn t A Ready-Made World

Phil 420: Metaphysics Spring 2008. [Handout 4] Hilary Putnam: Why There Isn t A Ready-Made World 1 Putnam s Main Theses: 1. There is no ready-made world. Phil 420: Metaphysics Spring 2008 [Handout 4] Hilary Putnam: Why There Isn t A Ready-Made World * [A ready-made world]: The world itself has to

More information

Kant s theory of the highest good

Kant s theory of the highest good Kant s theory of the highest good Ralf M. Bader Merton College, University of Oxford 1 Introduction e highest good is the culmination of Kant s ethical theory. It systematically combines all objects of

More information

Quine on truth by convention

Quine on truth by convention Quine on truth by convention March 8, 2005 1 Linguistic explanations of necessity and the a priori.............. 1 2 Relative and absolute truth by definition.................... 2 3 Is logic true by convention?...........................

More information

Kant on Time. Diana Mertz Hsieh (diana@dianahsieh.com) Kant (Phil 5010, Hanna) 28 September 2004

Kant on Time. Diana Mertz Hsieh (diana@dianahsieh.com) Kant (Phil 5010, Hanna) 28 September 2004 Kant on Time Diana Mertz Hsieh (diana@dianahsieh.com) Kant (Phil 5010, Hanna) 28 September 2004 In the Transcendental Aesthetic of his Critique of Pure Reason, Immanuel Kant offers a series of dense arguments

More information

In Defense of Kantian Moral Theory Nader Shoaibi University of California, Berkeley

In Defense of Kantian Moral Theory Nader Shoaibi University of California, Berkeley In Defense of Kantian Moral Theory University of California, Berkeley In this paper, I will argue that Kant provides us with a plausible account of morality. To show that, I will first offer a major criticism

More information

Kant s deontological ethics

Kant s deontological ethics Michael Lacewing Kant s deontological ethics DEONTOLOGY Deontologists believe that morality is a matter of duty. We have moral duties to do things which it is right to do and moral duties not to do things

More information

Hume on identity over time and persons

Hume on identity over time and persons Hume on identity over time and persons phil 20208 Jeff Speaks October 3, 2006 1 Why we have no idea of the self........................... 1 2 Change and identity................................. 2 3 Hume

More information

Sense-certainty and the this-such

Sense-certainty and the this-such //FS2/CUP/3-PAGINATION/MQP/2-PROOFS/3B2/9780521874540C04.3D 63 [63 75] 1.12.2007 8:53PM CHAPTER 4 Sense-certainty and the this-such Willem A. devries Hegel s Phenomenology of Spirit is knowledge s voyage

More information

JOHN STUART MILL. John Skorupski. m London and New York

JOHN STUART MILL. John Skorupski. m London and New York JOHN STUART MILL John Skorupski m London and New York Contents Preface Abbreviations xi xv 1 THE MILLIAN PHILOSOPHY 1 1 Philosophy and its past 1 2 Logic and metaphysics 5 3 Ethics and politics 12 4 The

More information

Honours programme in Philosophy

Honours programme in Philosophy Honours programme in Philosophy Honours Programme in Philosophy The Honours Programme in Philosophy offers students a broad and in-depth introduction to the main areas of Western philosophy and the philosophy

More information

Introduction. Hegel s Trinitarian Claim

Introduction. Hegel s Trinitarian Claim Hegel s Trinitarian Claim G. W. F. Hegel is one of the greatest thinkers of the Greek-Western trinitarian tradition. He said that the theologians of his day had effective ly abandoned the doctrine of the

More information

The basic principle is that one should not think of the properties of the process by means of the properties of the product

The basic principle is that one should not think of the properties of the process by means of the properties of the product Bergson Class Notes 1/30/08 Time and Free Will (Chapter 2) Reiterations The basic principle is that one should not think of the properties of the process by means of the properties of the product In general:

More information

I. Thinking and Thinking About Thinking A. Every human being thinks and thinks continually, but we do little thinking about our thinking.

I. Thinking and Thinking About Thinking A. Every human being thinks and thinks continually, but we do little thinking about our thinking. Philosophy 3304 Introduction to Logic Logic and World Views I. Thinking and Thinking About Thinking A. Every human being thinks and thinks continually, but we do little thinking about our thinking. B.

More information

Psychology has been considered to have an autonomy from the other sciences (especially

Psychology has been considered to have an autonomy from the other sciences (especially THE AUTONOMY OF PSYCHOLOGY Tim Crane, University College London Psychology has been considered to have an autonomy from the other sciences (especially physical science) in at least two ways: in its subject-matter

More information

Reality in the Eyes of Descartes and Berkeley. By: Nada Shokry 5/21/2013 AUC - Philosophy

Reality in the Eyes of Descartes and Berkeley. By: Nada Shokry 5/21/2013 AUC - Philosophy Reality in the Eyes of Descartes and Berkeley By: Nada Shokry 5/21/2013 AUC - Philosophy Shokry, 2 One person's craziness is another person's reality. Tim Burton This quote best describes what one finds

More information

Skepticism about the external world & the problem of other minds

Skepticism about the external world & the problem of other minds Skepticism about the external world & the problem of other minds So far in this course we have, broadly speaking, discussed two different sorts of issues: issues connected with the nature of persons (a

More information

Last time we had arrived at the following provisional interpretation of Aquinas second way:

Last time we had arrived at the following provisional interpretation of Aquinas second way: Aquinas Third Way Last time we had arrived at the following provisional interpretation of Aquinas second way: 1. 2. 3. 4. At least one thing has an efficient cause. Every causal chain must either be circular,

More information

Plato gives another argument for this claiming, relating to the nature of knowledge, which we will return to in the next section.

Plato gives another argument for this claiming, relating to the nature of knowledge, which we will return to in the next section. Michael Lacewing Plato s theor y of Forms FROM SENSE EXPERIENCE TO THE FORMS In Book V (476f.) of The Republic, Plato argues that all objects we experience through our senses are particular things. We

More information

Title: Duty Derives from Telos: The Teleology behind Kant s Categorical Imperative. Author: Micah Tillman

Title: Duty Derives from Telos: The Teleology behind Kant s Categorical Imperative. Author: Micah Tillman Title: Duty Derives from Telos: The Teleology behind Kant s Categorical Imperative Author: Micah Tillman Word Count: 3,358 (3,448, including content notes) Abstract: This paper argues that Kant s view

More information

Phenomenological Research Methods

Phenomenological Research Methods Phenomenological Research Methods Clark Moustakas, Sage Publications, Thousand Oaks California, 1994 I Human Science Perspectives and Models Moustakas starts with discussing different human science perspectives

More information

College of Arts and Sciences: Social Science and Humanities Outcomes

College of Arts and Sciences: Social Science and Humanities Outcomes College of Arts and Sciences: Social Science and Humanities Outcomes Communication Information Mgt/ Quantitative Skills Valuing/Ethics/ Integrity Critical Thinking Content Knowledge Application/ Internship

More information

The Meta-Problem of Change

The Meta-Problem of Change NOÛS 43:2 (2009) 286 314 The Meta-Problem of Change THOMAS HOFWEBER University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill 1. Introduction One of the central problems in metaphysics over the last so many centuries

More information

1/9. Locke 1: Critique of Innate Ideas

1/9. Locke 1: Critique of Innate Ideas 1/9 Locke 1: Critique of Innate Ideas This week we are going to begin looking at a new area by turning our attention to the work of John Locke, who is probably the most famous English philosopher of all

More information

PsyD Psychology (2014 2015)

PsyD Psychology (2014 2015) PsyD Psychology (2014 2015) Program Information Point of Contact Marianna Linz (linz@marshall.edu) Support for University and College Missions Marshall University is a multi campus public university providing

More information

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican, Hertford College. Lecture 3: Induction

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican, Hertford College. Lecture 3: Induction General Philosophy Dr Peter Millican, Hertford College Lecture 3: Induction Hume s s Fork 2 Enquiry IV starts with a vital distinction between types of proposition: Relations of ideas can be known a priori

More information

The Slate Is Not Empty: Descartes and Locke on Innate Ideas

The Slate Is Not Empty: Descartes and Locke on Innate Ideas The Slate Is Not Empty: Descartes and Locke on Innate Ideas René Descartes and John Locke, two of the principal philosophers who shaped modern philosophy, disagree on several topics; one of them concerns

More information

Methodological Issues for Interdisciplinary Research

Methodological Issues for Interdisciplinary Research J. T. M. Miller, Department of Philosophy, University of Durham 1 Methodological Issues for Interdisciplinary Research Much of the apparent difficulty of interdisciplinary research stems from the nature

More information

Contradictory Freedoms? Kant on Moral Agency and Political Rights

Contradictory Freedoms? Kant on Moral Agency and Political Rights Philosophy Study, ISSN 2159-5313 August 2012, Vol. 2, No. 8, 538-546 D DAVID PUBLISHING Contradictory Freedoms? Kant on Moral Agency and Political Rights Aaron James Wendland University of Oxford This

More information

Philosophical argument

Philosophical argument Michael Lacewing Philosophical argument At the heart of philosophy is philosophical argument. Arguments are different from assertions. Assertions are simply stated; arguments always involve giving reasons.

More information

PSYCHOLOGY PROGRAM LEARNING GOALS, LEARNING OUTCOMES AND COURSE ALLIGNMENT MATRIX. 8 Oct. 2010

PSYCHOLOGY PROGRAM LEARNING GOALS, LEARNING OUTCOMES AND COURSE ALLIGNMENT MATRIX. 8 Oct. 2010 PSYCHOLOGY PROGRAM LEARNING GOALS, LEARNING OUTCOMES AND COURSE ALLIGNMENT MATRIX 8 Oct. 2010 Departmental Learning Goals and Outcomes LEARNING GOAL 1: KNOWLEDGE BASE OF PSYCHOLOGY Demonstrate familiarity

More information

Boonin on the Future-Like-Ours Argument against Abortion. Pedro Galvão Centro de Filosofia da Universidade de Lisboa

Boonin on the Future-Like-Ours Argument against Abortion. Pedro Galvão Centro de Filosofia da Universidade de Lisboa Boonin on the Future-Like-Ours Argument against Abortion Pedro Galvão Centro de Filosofia da Universidade de Lisboa David Boonin s recent book 1 is an impressively deep and detailed attempt to establish

More information

#HUMN-104 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY

#HUMN-104 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY Coffeyville Community College #HUMN-104 COURSE SYLLABUS FOR INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY Mike Arpin Instructor COURSE NUMBER: HUMN-104 COURSE TITLE: Introduction to Philosophy CREDIT HOURS: 3 INSTRUCTOR:

More information

Program Level Learning Outcomes for the Department of Philosophy Page 1

Program Level Learning Outcomes for the Department of Philosophy Page 1 Page 1 PHILOSOPHY General Major I. Depth and Breadth of Knowledge. A. Will be able to recall what a worldview is and recognize that we all possess one. B. Should recognize that philosophy is most broadly

More information

PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES

PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES Philosophical Perspectives, 26, Philosophy of Mind, 2012 FIRST PERSON ILLUSIONS: ARE THEY DESCARTES, OR KANT S? Christopher Peacocke Columbia University and University College,

More information

JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS By John Rawls (1971)

JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS By John Rawls (1971) JUSTICE AS FAIRNESS By John Rawls (1971) The Main Idea of The Theory of Justice My aim is to present a conception of justice which generalizes and carries to a higher level of abstraction the familiar

More information

In an article titled Ethical Absolutism and the

In an article titled Ethical Absolutism and the Stance Volume 3 April 2010 A Substantive Revision to Firth's Ideal Observer Theory ABSTRACT: This paper examines Ideal Observer Theory and uses criticisms of it to lay the foundation for a revised theory

More information

One natural response would be to cite evidence of past mornings, and give something like the following argument:

One natural response would be to cite evidence of past mornings, and give something like the following argument: Hume on induction Suppose you were asked to give your reasons for believing that the sun will come up tomorrow, in the form of an argument for the claim that the sun will come up tomorrow. One natural

More information

Research in the cognitive sciences is founded on the assumption

Research in the cognitive sciences is founded on the assumption Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Conceptual Parallels Between Philosophy of Science and Cognitive Science: Artificial Intelligence, Human Intuition, and Rationality Research in the cognitive sciences is founded

More information

[Draft Do not cite] General Practical Philosophy in Kant s Groundwork

[Draft Do not cite] General Practical Philosophy in Kant s Groundwork [Draft Do not cite] General Practical Philosophy in Kant s Groundwork In a little discussed passage of the Groundwork, Kant distinguishes his own metaphysics of morals (the topic of the Groundwork itself)

More information

In this essay, I will first outline my understanding of the basis for Kant's categorical

In this essay, I will first outline my understanding of the basis for Kant's categorical I ought never to act except in such a way that I can also will that my maxim should become a universal law. What does Kant mean by this, and does it give the right kind of guidance when we are choosing

More information

CREDIT TRANSFER: GUIDELINES FOR STUDENT TRANSFER AND ARTICULATION AMONG MISSOURI COLLEGES AND UNIVERSITIES

CREDIT TRANSFER: GUIDELINES FOR STUDENT TRANSFER AND ARTICULATION AMONG MISSOURI COLLEGES AND UNIVERSITIES CREDIT TRANSFER: GUIDELINES FOR STUDENT TRANSFER AND ARTICULATION AMONG MISSOURI COLLEGES AND UNIVERSITIES With Revisions as Proposed by the General Education Steering Committee [Extracts] A. RATIONALE

More information

Some Pragmatist Themes in Hegel s Idealism: Negotiation and Administration in Hegel s Account of the Structure and Content of Conceptual Norms

Some Pragmatist Themes in Hegel s Idealism: Negotiation and Administration in Hegel s Account of the Structure and Content of Conceptual Norms Some Pragmatist Themes in Hegel s Idealism: Negotiation and Administration in Hegel s Account of the Structure and Content of Conceptual Norms Robert B. Brandom This paper could equally well have been

More information

Course Syllabus Department of Philosophy and Religion Skidmore College. PH 101: Introduction to Philosophy TUTH 3:40-5:30 Spring, 2011

Course Syllabus Department of Philosophy and Religion Skidmore College. PH 101: Introduction to Philosophy TUTH 3:40-5:30 Spring, 2011 Course Syllabus Department of Philosophy and Religion Skidmore College PH 101: Introduction to Philosophy Reg Lilly TUTH 3:40-5:30 Spring, 2011 COURSE DESCRIPTION: This course is designed to introduce

More information

Lecture notes on Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. Delivered by Peter Rickman during Autumn 1995

Lecture notes on Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. Delivered by Peter Rickman during Autumn 1995 Lecture notes on Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason Delivered by Peter Rickman during Autumn 1995 Preface Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason introduces his critical philosophy. His philosophical

More information

Morals and Kant s doctrine of transcendental idealism

Morals and Kant s doctrine of transcendental idealism ORIGINAL ARTICLE Volume 4, Issue, 1 pp. 8-25 Exorcising the Spectre of Illusions: The deduction of freedom in the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals and Kant s doctrine of transcendental idealism

More information

NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS

NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS Michael Lacewing Personal identity: Physical and psychological continuity theories A FIRST DISTINCTION In order to understand what is at issue in personal identity, it is important to distinguish between

More information

Locke s psychological theory of personal identity

Locke s psychological theory of personal identity Locke s psychological theory of personal identity phil 20208 Jeff Speaks October 3, 2006 1 Identity, diversity, and kinds............................. 1 2 Personal identity...................................

More information

Existence Is Not a Predicate by Immanuel Kant

Existence Is Not a Predicate by Immanuel Kant Existence Is Not a Predicate by Immanuel Kant Immanuel Kant, Thoemmes About the author.... Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) studied in Königsberg, East Prussia. Before he fully developed an interest in philosophy,

More information

[THIS IS A PRE-PRINT VERSION OF THE PAPER. THE PUBLISHED VERSION IS AVAILABLE ONLINE AT http://mind.oxfordjournals.org/cgi/reprint/116/464/1083]

[THIS IS A PRE-PRINT VERSION OF THE PAPER. THE PUBLISHED VERSION IS AVAILABLE ONLINE AT http://mind.oxfordjournals.org/cgi/reprint/116/464/1083] Book Review Jason Bridges The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and Substance of Rationality, by Robert Audi. New York: Oxford University Press, 2001. Pp. xvi + 286. H/b $65.00, P/b $29.95 [THIS IS

More information

The John Locke Lectures 2009. Being Realistic about Reasons. T. M. Scanlon. Lecture 3: Motivation and the Appeal of Expressivism

The John Locke Lectures 2009. Being Realistic about Reasons. T. M. Scanlon. Lecture 3: Motivation and the Appeal of Expressivism The John Locke Lectures 2009 Being Realistic about Reasons T. M. Scanlon Lecture 3: Motivation and the Appeal of Expressivism The cognitivist view I have been defending has two important features in common

More information

Convention: An interdisciplinary study

Convention: An interdisciplinary study Convention: An interdisciplinary study Luca Tummolini Institute of Cognitive Sciences and Technologies Via San Martino della Battaglia 44 00185 Roma Italy luca.tummolini@istc.cnr.it In our lives we are

More information

PSYCHOLOGY PROGRAM LEARNING GOALS AND OUTCOMES BY COURSE LISTING

PSYCHOLOGY PROGRAM LEARNING GOALS AND OUTCOMES BY COURSE LISTING PSYCHOLOGY PROGRAM LEARNING GOALS AND OUTCOMES BY COURSE LISTING Psychology 1010: General Psychology Learning Goals and Outcomes LEARNING GOAL 1: KNOWLEDGE BASE OF PSYCHOLOGY Demonstrate familiarity with

More information

Subject area: Ethics. Injustice causes revolt. Discuss.

Subject area: Ethics. Injustice causes revolt. Discuss. Subject area: Ethics Title: Injustice causes revolt. Discuss. 1 Injustice causes revolt. Discuss. When we explain phenomena we rely on the assertion of facts. The sun rises because the earth turns on its

More information

Does rationality consist in responding correctly to reasons? John Broome Journal of Moral Philosophy, 4 (2007), pp. 349 74.

Does rationality consist in responding correctly to reasons? John Broome Journal of Moral Philosophy, 4 (2007), pp. 349 74. Does rationality consist in responding correctly to reasons? John Broome Journal of Moral Philosophy, 4 (2007), pp. 349 74. 1. Rationality and responding to reasons Some philosophers think that rationality

More information

Kant on Geometry and Spatial Intuition

Kant on Geometry and Spatial Intuition Kant on Geometry and Spatial Intuition Michael Friedman Kant s philosophy of geometry can only be properly understood against the background of two more general features of his philosophical position:

More information

MS 102- PROFESSIONAL & BUSINESS ETHICS 2 MARKS QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS UNIT I

MS 102- PROFESSIONAL & BUSINESS ETHICS 2 MARKS QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS UNIT I 1. Define Ethics? MS 102- PROFESSIONAL & BUSINESS ETHICS 2 MARKS QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS UNIT I * Study of right or wrong. * Good and evil. * Obligations & rights. * Justice. * Social & Political deals.

More information

Introduction. My thesis is summarized in my title, No. God, No Laws : the concept of a law of Nature cannot be

Introduction. My thesis is summarized in my title, No. God, No Laws : the concept of a law of Nature cannot be No God, No Laws Nancy Cartwright Philosophy LSE and UCSD Introduction. My thesis is summarized in my title, No God, No Laws : the concept of a law of Nature cannot be made sense of without God. It is not

More information

PHILOSOPHY 101: CRITICAL THINKING

PHILOSOPHY 101: CRITICAL THINKING PHILOSOPHY 101: CRITICAL THINKING [days and times] [classroom] [semester] 20YY, [campus] [instructor s name] [office hours: days and times] [instructor s e-mail] COURSE OBJECTIVES AND OUTCOMES 1. Identify

More information

Are Skill Selective Immigration Policies Just?

Are Skill Selective Immigration Policies Just? Are Skill Selective Immigration Policies Just? Douglas MacKay c 2014 Douglas MacKay Are Skill Selective Immigration Policies Just? Many high income countries have skill selective immigration policies,

More information

GLOBAL GOAL 1: THE STUDENT WILL ACQUIRE CRITICAL THINKING SKILLS. Instructional Learning objectives: The student will be able to...

GLOBAL GOAL 1: THE STUDENT WILL ACQUIRE CRITICAL THINKING SKILLS. Instructional Learning objectives: The student will be able to... A B C D E F G H I PHL 100*#^ PHL 125#^ PHL 203 PHL 209 1 2 3 Philosophy Major Program Applied Ethics Concentration Philosophy of Art & Culture Concentration Intro. to Philosophy Critical Reasoning Business

More information

7 Bachelor s degree programme in the Philosophy of a Specific Scientific Discipline

7 Bachelor s degree programme in the Philosophy of a Specific Scientific Discipline 7 Bachelor s degree programme in the Philosophy of a Specific Scientific Discipline 7.1 General introduction to degree programmes in the Philosophy of a Specific Scientific Discipline This chapter contains

More information

MILD DILEMMAS. Keywords: standard moral dilemmas, mild dilemmas, blame

MILD DILEMMAS. Keywords: standard moral dilemmas, mild dilemmas, blame MILD DILEMMAS Gregory Mellema Department of Philosophy Calvin College Grand Rapids, MI mell@calvin.edu Abstract. This paper argues that, while the existence of strong moral dilemmas is notoriously controversial,

More information

The Separability of Free Will and Moral Responsibility

The Separability of Free Will and Moral Responsibility 254 Free Will: The Scandal in Philosophy Illusionism Determinism Hard Determinism Compatibilism Soft Determinism Hard Incompatibilism Impossibilism Valerian Model Soft Compatibilism The Separability of

More information

Is there a problem about nonconceptual content?

Is there a problem about nonconceptual content? Is there a problem about nonconceptual content? Jeff Speaks (forthcoming in the Philosophical Review) 1 Two understandings of nonconceptual content.................. 1 2 The case for nonconceptual content..........................

More information

The Learning Skills Pyramid

The Learning Skills Pyramid The Learning Skills Pyramid Brett A. Brosseit, 2013 To develop strong critical thinking and legal analysis skills, students need to: Develop new patterns of thinking Understand the mental processes they

More information

GEORGIA STANDARDS FOR THE APPROVAL OF PROFESSIONAL EDUCATION UNITS AND EDUCATOR PREPARATION PROGRAMS

GEORGIA STANDARDS FOR THE APPROVAL OF PROFESSIONAL EDUCATION UNITS AND EDUCATOR PREPARATION PROGRAMS GEORGIA STANDARDS FOR THE APPROVAL OF PROFESSIONAL EDUCATION UNITS AND EDUCATOR PREPARATION PROGRAMS (Effective 9/01/08) Kelly Henson Executive Secretary Table of Contents Standard 1: Candidate Knowledge,

More information

PSYCHOLOGICAL BULLETIN

PSYCHOLOGICAL BULLETIN Vol. I. No. i. January 15, 1904. THE PSYCHOLOGICAL BULLETIN THE CHICAGO SCHOOL,. 1 BY PROFESSOR WILLIAM JAMES. The rest of the world has made merry over the Chicago man's legendary saying that ' Chicago

More information

BA Psychology (2014 2015)

BA Psychology (2014 2015) BA Psychology (2014 2015) Program Information Point of Contact Marianna Linz (linz@marshall.edu) Support for University and College Missions Marshall University is a multi campus public university providing

More information

TIPS FOR WRITING LEARNING OBJECTIVES

TIPS FOR WRITING LEARNING OBJECTIVES TIPS FOR WRITING LEARNING OBJECTIVES N ational ACEP receives numerous requests from chapters for assistance on how to write good learning objectives. The information presented in this section has been

More information

Is a Single-Bladed Knife Enough to Dissect Human Cognition? Commentary on Griffiths et al.

Is a Single-Bladed Knife Enough to Dissect Human Cognition? Commentary on Griffiths et al. Cognitive Science 32 (2008) 155 161 Copyright C 2008 Cognitive Science Society, Inc. All rights reserved. ISSN: 0364-0213 print / 1551-6709 online DOI: 10.1080/03640210701802113 Is a Single-Bladed Knife

More information

Kant and Aquinas on the Grounds of Moral Necessity

Kant and Aquinas on the Grounds of Moral Necessity CONGRESSO TOMISTA INTERNAZIONALE L UMANESIMO CRISTIANO NEL III MILLENNIO: PROSPETTIVA DI TOMMASO D AQUINO ROMA, 21-25 settembre 2003 Pontificia Accademia di San Tommaso Società Internazionale Tommaso d

More information

... methodology and two kinds of ethics

... methodology and two kinds of ethics I N T R O D U C T I O N... methodology and two kinds of ethics Kant s theory of moral motivation is notoriously controversial. Indeed, few areas of Kant scholarship have drawn as much attention or prompted

More information

Professional Ethics PHIL 3340. Today s Topic Absolute Moral Rules & Kantian Ethics. Part I

Professional Ethics PHIL 3340. Today s Topic Absolute Moral Rules & Kantian Ethics. Part I Professional Ethics PHIL 3340 Today s Topic Absolute Moral Rules & Kantian Ethics Part I Consequentialism vs. Deontology Consequentialism: A type of ethical theory stating that to act morally we must base

More information

THE LIMITS OF WELL-BEING

THE LIMITS OF WELL-BEING Social Philosophy & Policy, vol. 9, no. 2 (1992), pp. 169-189 THE LIMITS OF WELL-BEING BY SHELLY KAGAN I. THE DIALECTIC What are the limits of well-being? This question nicely captures one of the central

More information

The Double Lives of Objects: An Essay in the Metaphysics of the Ordinary World

The Double Lives of Objects: An Essay in the Metaphysics of the Ordinary World 252 The Double Lives of Objects: An Essay in the Metaphysics of the Ordinary World, by Thomas Sattig. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015, 288 pages, ISBN 9780199683017 (hbk). In The Double Lives of

More information

A Brief Guide to Writing the Philosophy Paper

A Brief Guide to Writing the Philosophy Paper HARVARD COLLEGE Writing Center WRITING CENTER BRIEF GUIDE SERIES A Brief Guide to Writing the Philosophy Paper The Challenges of Philosophical Writing The aim of the assignments in your philosophy classes

More information

The Ontology of Cyberspace: Law, Philosophy, and the Future of Intellectual Property by

The Ontology of Cyberspace: Law, Philosophy, and the Future of Intellectual Property by The Ontology of Cyberspace: Law, Philosophy, and the Future of Intellectual Property by David R. Koepsell, Peru, Illinois: Open Court Publishing, 2000, ISBN 0-8126-9423-6, (Price $26.95); Paper: ISBN 0-8126-9537-2,

More information

How does the problem of relativity relate to Thomas Kuhn s concept of paradigm?

How does the problem of relativity relate to Thomas Kuhn s concept of paradigm? How does the problem of relativity relate to Thomas Kuhn s concept of paradigm? Eli Bjørhusdal After having published The Structure of Scientific Revolutions in 1962, Kuhn was much criticised for the use

More information

Humanities new methods Challenges for confirmation theory

Humanities new methods Challenges for confirmation theory Datum 15.06.2012 Humanities new methods Challenges for confirmation theory Presentation for The Making of the Humanities III Jan-Willem Romeijn Faculty of Philosophy University of Groningen Interactive

More information

Christine M. Korsgaard. calls goodness as rationality. Officially, the theory is first presented to reinforce

Christine M. Korsgaard. calls goodness as rationality. Officially, the theory is first presented to reinforce The Unity of the Right and the Good in John Rawls s Thought This symposium is on the Legacy of John Rawls, but, in a way, my own contribution concerns the legacy that Rawls did not have. Part Three of

More information

PHIL 341: Ethical Theory

PHIL 341: Ethical Theory PHIL 341: Ethical Theory Student data (on cards) Contact info: name, address, phone number, university ID, etc. Background: especially data on satisfaction of the prerequisite (two prior courses in philosophy).

More information

Some key arguments from Meditations III-V

Some key arguments from Meditations III-V Some key arguments from Meditations III-V I. THIRD MEDITATION: The existence of God A. Cosmological proof of the Existence of God In the 3rd Meditation, Descartes attempts to prove that God (i) exists,

More information

The Refutation of Relativism

The Refutation of Relativism The Refutation of Relativism There are many different versions of relativism: ethical relativism conceptual relativism, and epistemic relativism are three. In this paper, I will be concerned with only

More information

Influenced by - Alfred Binet intelligence testing movement

Influenced by - Alfred Binet intelligence testing movement SA1 Trait Psychology Influenced by - Alfred Binet intelligence testing movement Origins - Psychologists became interested in seeing whether the success achieved with mental measurement might be repeated

More information

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send email to: permissions@press.princeton.edu

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send email to: permissions@press.princeton.edu COPYRIGHT NOTICE: Richard Raatzsch: The Apologetics of Evil is published by Princeton University Press and copyrighted, 2009, by Princeton University Press. All rights reserved. No part of this book may

More information

The Ambiguity of Kant s Concept of Happiness

The Ambiguity of Kant s Concept of Happiness The Ambiguity of Kant s Concept of Happiness Thomas Marshall Neumann College My analysis of Kant s concept of happiness is motivated by a concern with the role it plays in his ethical system. Typically

More information

Argument Mapping 2: Claims and Reasons

Argument Mapping 2: Claims and Reasons #2 Claims and Reasons 1 Argument Mapping 2: Claims and Reasons We ll start with the very basics here, so be patient. It becomes far more challenging when we apply these basic rules to real arguments, as

More information

MILL. The principle of utility determines the rightness of acts (or rules of action?) by their effect on the total happiness.

MILL. The principle of utility determines the rightness of acts (or rules of action?) by their effect on the total happiness. MILL The principle of utility determines the rightness of acts (or rules of action?) by their effect on the total happiness. Mill s principle of utility Mill s principle combines theories of the right

More information

Exhibit memory of previously-learned materials by recalling facts, terms, basic concepts, and answers. Key Words

Exhibit memory of previously-learned materials by recalling facts, terms, basic concepts, and answers. Key Words The Six Levels of Questioning Level 1 Knowledge Exhibit memory of previously-learned materials by recalling facts, terms, basic concepts, and answers. who what why when where which omit choose find how

More information

Hypothetical Syllogisms 1

Hypothetical Syllogisms 1 Phil 2302 Intro to Logic Dr. Naugle Hypothetical Syllogisms 1 Compound syllogisms are composed of different kinds of sentences in their premises and conclusions (not just categorical propositions, statements

More information

Please find below some views on the issues raised by the EMA Senior Medical Officer's Reflections on the legal basis for EMA/CHMP opinions.

Please find below some views on the issues raised by the EMA Senior Medical Officer's Reflections on the legal basis for EMA/CHMP opinions. Jacques Ropers Afssaps Pierre Demolis Afssaps (French CHMP Member) Philippe Lechat Afssaps (French Alternate CHMP Member) Dear Colleagues, Please find below some views on the issues raised by the EMA Senior

More information

Cosmological Arguments for the Existence of God S. Clarke

Cosmological Arguments for the Existence of God S. Clarke Cosmological Arguments for the Existence of God S. Clarke [Modified Fall 2009] 1. Large class of arguments. Sometimes they get very complex, as in Clarke s argument, but the basic idea is simple. Lets

More information

TREK 201. Core Christian Beliefs

TREK 201. Core Christian Beliefs TREK 201 Core Christian Beliefs Work hard to show the results of your salvation, obeying God with deep reverence and fear. Philippians 2:12b (NLT) TREK is a Discipleship Ministry of Rockpointe Church 1

More information

Concept Formation. Robert Goldstone. Thomas T. Hills. Samuel B. Day. Indiana University. Department of Psychology. Indiana University

Concept Formation. Robert Goldstone. Thomas T. Hills. Samuel B. Day. Indiana University. Department of Psychology. Indiana University 1 Concept Formation Robert L. Goldstone Thomas T. Hills Samuel B. Day Indiana University Correspondence Address: Robert Goldstone Department of Psychology Indiana University Bloomington, IN. 47408 Other

More information

1 Must the universe have a cause?

1 Must the universe have a cause? 1 Must the universe have a cause? Nothing will come of nothing. William Shakespeare, King Lear THE MYSTERIES OF EXISTENCE Why does the universe exist? Why do living things exist? Why do intelligent beings

More information