Regret, Pride, and the Disposition E ect

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Regret, Pride, and the Disposition E ect"

Transcription

1 Regret, Pride, and the Disposition E ect Alexander Muermann y Jacqueline M. Volkman z October 27 Abstract Seeking pride and avoiding regret has been put forward as a rationale for the disposition e ect, the tendency of investors to sell winning stocks and hold on to losing stocks. We develop a dynamic portfolio choice model that incorporates anticipated regret and pride in individual s preferences to formally investigate this explanation. We specify a setting for which this rationale is satis ed, but show that it is not robust to variations in the underlying assumptions. JEL Classi cation D8, G Keywords disposition e ect, regret theory, dynamic portfolio choice We wish to thank Neil Doherty, Olivia Mitchell, and Harris Schlesinger for their valuable comments. Muermann gratefully acknowledges nancial support of the National Institutes of Health National Institute on Aging, Grant number P3 AG2836, the Boettner Center for Pensions and Retirement Security at the University of Pennsylvania, and National Institutes of Health National Institute of Child Health and Development Population Research Infrastructure Program R24 HD-44964, all at the University of Pennsylvania. Volkman gratefully acknowledges nancial support from the Insurance and Risk Management Department at the Wharton School through a Bradley Foundation Scholarship. y Muermann: Institute of Risk Management and Insurance, Vienna University of Economics and Business Administration, Nordbergstraße 5, A-9 Wien, AUSTRIA, alexander.muermann@wu-wien.ac.at z Volkman: Schools of Business, Fordham University, 79 Broadway, Room 327, New York, NY 9, USA, volkman@fordham.edu

2 Introduction In nancial markets, there is a unique phenomenon where investors appear reluctant to realize losses and eager to realize gains; that is, investors seem to have a preference for selling winning stocks too early and holding losing stocks too long. This pattern has been labeled the disposition e ect by Shefrin and Statman (985) and cannot be explained by traditional trading theories. For instance, Odean (998) found this e ect even after accounting for portfolio rebalancing and trading costs. Similarly, Lakonishok and Smidt (986) and Ferris et al. (987) consider trading volume and nd that the disposition e ect dominates tax-related motives for selling stocks at a loss. The disposition e ect has also been discovered in the Finnish stock market (Grinblatt and Keloharju 2), the Finnish apartment market (Einio and Puttonen 26), the Taiwanese stock market (Barber et al. 26), in the exercise of company stock options (Heath, Huddart, and Lang 999), and in the sale of residential housing (Genesove and Mayer 2). Furthermore, it has been found for professional investors at an Israeli brokerage house (Shapira and Venezia 2) and for professional futures traders (Locke and Mann 2); although, Shapira and Venezia (2) and Dhar and Zhu (26) nd that investors with less trading experience exhibit a stronger disposition e ect. Experimental evidence has further supported the disposition e ect (Weber and Camerer 998, Andreassen 988). We refer to Barber and Odean (25) for a more in-depth review of this phenomenon. Shefrin and Statman (985) proposed several explanations for the disposition e ect, including loss aversion, mental accounting, seeking pride and avoiding regret, and self control. Much of the literature to date on the disposition e ect has focused on loss aversion as an explanation. Hens and Vlcek (25) and Barberis and Xiong (26) recently formally analyzed this reasoning and found that loss aversion mostly does not predict the disposition e ect. We describe their ndings in further detail below. In this paper, we formally model the anticipation of regret and pride in a dynamic setting to see if it can cause investors to optimally follow a strategy in which they sell winning stocks and hold losing stocks; that is, we examine if seeking pride and avoiding regret can explain the disposition e ect. In addition to Shefrin and Statman (985), several empirical papers documenting the disposition e ect argue that loss aversion explains this phenomenon (Odean 998, Lakonishok and Smidt 986, Ferris et al. 987, Grinblatt and Keloharju 2, Shapira and Venezia 2, Coval and Shumway 22, Dhar and Zhu 26). Kahneman and Tversky (979) rst proposed loss aversion as part of prospect theory, arguing that people make decisions considering gains and losses relative to some reference point rather than to wealth levels. Individuals who are loss-averse have preferences that are risk-seeking over losses and risk-averse over gains, and are more sensitive to losses than to equivalent gains. The intuition behind why loss aversion can explain the disposition e ect is as follows. Since a winning stock is considered a gain, and individuals are risk-averse in this domain, they will sell the stock. On the other hand, a losing stock is considered a loss, and being risk-seeking in this domain, investors will hold the stock. Most previous studies that consider the disposition e ect are empirical and list loss aversion 2

3 as an explanation for the e ect. preferences in portfolio choice problems. More recently, a few papers have formally modeled loss averse loss-averse investors would be consistent with the disposition e ect. Gomes (25) nds that the optimal portfolio choice for Kyle et al. (26) examine the liquidation decision of a project with loss-averse preferences and also nd optimal behavior that is consistent with the disposition e ect. Yet, neither paper considers the initial decision. That is, the investor is endowed with the stock or the project and whether or not a loss-averse investor would initially buy the stock or invest in the project is not considered. In contrast, Hens and Vlcek (25) and Barberis and Xiong (26) take the initial decision into consideration and mostly nd that loss aversion cannot explain the disposition e ect with short time horizons. The equity premium must be so high for loss-averse investors to initially invest in the stock that subsequent optimal behavior is not consistent with the disposition e ect. In fact, Barberis and Xiong (26) show that this often implies momentum trading by the investor, which is the opposite of the disposition e ect: keeping winning and selling losing stocks. Furthermore, Barberis and Xiong (26) demonstrate that investors are only willing to invest initially in the stock and exhibit optimal behavior that is consistent with the disposition e ect when stock returns are negatively skewed and/or the curvature of the value function is su ciently smaller than suggested by Tversky and Kahneman (992) and/or the number of trading periods is large and the equity premium is su ciently low. As the literature illustrates, it is only under speci c conditions that loss averse preferences imply investment behavior consistent with the disposition e ect. Another explanation for the disposition e ect suggested by Shefrin and Statman (985) and formally examined in this paper is the feeling of regret and pride, which has recently been supported with experimental evidence (O Curry Fogel and Berry 26). The intuition is that an investor who regrets an investment in a stock that has lost value will hold the stock because he hopes that the stock price will rise in the next period, enabling him to avoid regret. If the stock has risen in value, however, the investor wants to feel pride in having made such a good investment and therefore sells the stock; if he had held it and then the price fell, he would have foregone feeling pride. Wanting to feel pride and delay regret is what causes investors to realize gains more quickly than losses. 2 Although the explanation seems intuitive, as it seems with loss aversion, it is not as straightforward to argue that preferences including regret and pride would give rise to the disposition e ect in a dynamic setting. For instance, an investor may sell a stock after it rises over one period, but if the stock rises again over the following period, he will feel regret from having sold the stock too early. Therefore, anticipating regret over both periods, in this instance, could cause the investor to hold the stock after the rst period, or to not invest in the stock in the rst place. To the best of our knowledge, to date there has been no formal analysis of whether preferences including regret and pride can predict the disposition e ect. In this paper, we develop such a Hens and Vlcek (25) consider a two-period model with a myopic investor whereas Barberis and Xiong (26) examine a general multi-period model with a dynamically optimizing investor. 2 Barber et al. (24) nd empirical evidence and Weber and Welfens (26) nd experimental evidence of an investor s tendency to repurchase or purchase additional shares of stocks that have recently lost value. In both papers, the authors argue that repurchase decisions could be driven by counterfactuals which might give rise to feelings of regret. 3

4 model. Considering a dynamic setting with regret and pride raises some interesting questions and thus requires certain assumptions to be made. For instance, does the investor experience future regret or pride only for the current investment decision or do such feelings result from all decisions made in the past? When does the investor experience regret at the nal period or during intermediate periods? In a dynamic setting, some decisions will elicit regret and others pride. How do these feelings interact and compound over time? Furthermore, if the investor does not hold the stock, does he know how it performs, and can he experience regret then from not holding it if it does well (or pride if it performs poorly)? In what follows, we will state and explain the assumptions that underlie the model for how anticipation of regret and pride causes individuals to sell stocks that have gained recently and hold stocks that have lost. We conclude that, in a speci c setting, the disposition e ect can occur if investors experience regret and pride over their investment decisions; yet, as with loss aversion, this result is not robust to numerous variations of this setting. The paper is structured as follows. In the next section, we introduce the model, the assumptions, and preferences that allow individuals to consider regret and pride. In Section 3, we examine the optimal portfolio choice problem and provide su cient conditions for the investor s optimal strategy to be consistent with the disposition e ect. In Section 4, we discuss the robustness of our assumptions. Finally, we conclude in Section 5. 2 Model and Preferences Regret is an individual s ex-post feeling that his ex-ante decision turned out to be suboptimal with respect to the resolved uncertainty; that is, the individual s ex-post level of wealth could have been higher had he made a foregone alternative decision. Equivalently, pride is the ex-post feeling that the ex-ante decision turned out to be better than some foregone alternative decision. In this setting, an individual makes a decision considering the anticipated disutility or additional utility derived from regret or pride. Regret theory was initially formulated by Bell (982) and Loomes and Sugden (982) and has been shown in both the theoretical and experimental literature to explain individual behavior. Bell (982) depicted how regret could explain preferences for both insurance and gambling. More recently, the impact of regret on decision making has been examined in a static framework for di erent scenarios, including the demand for insurance (Braun and Muermann 24), portfolio choice (Muermann et al. 26), asset pricing and portfolio choice in an Arrow-Debreu economy (Gollier and Salanié 26), currency hedging (Michenaud and Solnik 26), and rst price auctions (Filiz and Ozbay 27). We contribute to this literature by considering a dynamic portfolio choice problem. This framework allows us to capture an investor s dynamically optimal response to realized portfolio returns and feelings of regret and pride implied by such realized returns. In the following, we introduce a model that is simple yet rich enough to capture these issues. There are two assets: a risk-free asset (bond) with a zero normalized return and a risky asset 4

5 (stock) with a stochastic return ~x t per period. In this paper, we consider only one risky asset in order to be consistent with the mental accounting framework noted by Thaler (985) and supported by Gross (982): the idea is that decision makers di erentiate gambles into separate accounts, applying their preferences to each account, and ignoring the interaction between them. In this manner, investors would view each stock they hold individually, and therefore, we only consider one. We assume that the risky returns are independent and identically distributed across periods and take the two values x + > > x with probability p and p in each period. The individual is endowed with initial wealth w and can only invest all of his wealth in one of the two assets. There are two periods. At t = the investor decides whether to invest his wealth, w, in the stock or bond. At t = the investor observes his realized level of wealth, w, and decides again whether to invest it in the stock or bond. At t = 2 all assets are liquidated and the investor observes and consumes his nal level of wealth, w 2. The restriction that the individual cannot split his wealth between the two assets is consistent with the discussion and analysis in Shefrin and Statman (985) and Odean (998), which are based on stock trading records of individual investors. Alternative settings include the purchase and sale of an indivisible asset such as housing, or the investment in and liquidation of a project (e.g., Kyle et al. 26, who consider such decisions with loss-averse preferences). Our model thus speaks to the empirical evidence of the disposition e ect in the real estate market provided by Genesove and Mayer (2) and Einio and Puttonen (26). We follow Bell (982, 983) and Loomes and Sugden (982) by implementing the following two-attribute utility function to incorporate regret and pride in investors preferences v (w) = u (w) kg(u(w alt ) u (w)). () The rst attribute represents the individual s level of risk-aversion and is characterized by the individual s utility function of actual level of wealth, w. We assume that the utility function u () exhibits CRRA preferences, i.e. u (w) = w (2) for 6= and u (w) = ln (w) for =, where is the coe cient of relative risk aversion. This implies that the time horizon has no e ect on the optimal portfolio allocation of an individual who does not consider regret and pride in his decision. That is, the individual makes his decision as if he was myopic. Additionally, we assume that stock returns satisfy p ( + x + ) + ( p) ( + x ) > if < p ( + x + ) + ( p) ( + x ) < if > ( + x + ) p ( + x ) p > if = (3) This assumption implies that the risk premium is high enough such that an individual who does not consider regret and pride nds it optimal to invest in the stock in all periods. Thereby we 5

6 exclude portfolio rebalancing as an explanation for the disposition e ect which allows us to focus on how regret and pride in uence the optimal portfolio allocation. The second attribute represents the individual s feeling of regret or pride toward the ctitious level of wealth, w alt, the individual would have obtained from a foregone alternative. If the actual level of wealth, w, falls below the alternative level of wealth, w alt, the individual regrets his decision; otherwise the individual feels pride. The function g () measures the amount of regret and pride that the investor experiences, and we assume that it is increasing and convex with g () = ; that is, the individual weighs the disutility incurred from regret relatively more than the additional utility derived from pride. This assumption is supported in the literature (Thaler 98, Kahneman and Tversky 982) and has recently found experimental support (Bleichrodt et al. 26). The parameter k measures the relative importance of the second attribute, regret, to the rst attribute of the utility function. We assume that the individual incurs the disutility or additional utility from regret or pride only in the nal period. Similar to the assumption that there is no intermediate consumption, we assume that the individual does not incur regret or pride in intermediate periods. The investor thus makes his portfolio choice by maximizing his expected utility of terminal wealth using the value function v () given in equation (). We make the following two additional assumptions, which turn out to be crucial for predicting that regret and pride cause individuals to behave according to the disposition e ect. In Section 4, we will discuss how deviations from these assumptions impact our results. Assumption The individual only observes the realized stock return if he holds the stock. This assumption is relevant for regret-averse individuals as foregone alternatives and their resolution can impact decisions. In our setting, this assumption implies that the individual has the option to avoid regret or forego pride by investing in the bond and not observing the realized return of the stock (by not reading the newspaper). This relates to Bell (983), who shows that it can be optimal for a regret-averse individual to not have a foregone alternative lottery resolved. In fact, we will show in Section 4 that observing stock returns after selling the stock yields a lower level of expected utility for the investor. This implies that if the individual has the choice to observe or not observe stock returns, then it is optimal in our setting for him not to observe them. Assumption 2 If the individual s decisions turn out to be ex-post optimal (i.e., they imply the maximum level of wealth with respect to the realized returns), then he experiences pride toward the foregone worst alternative (FWA), the lowest level of wealth he could have obtained with respect to the realized returns. If the individual s choices turn out to be ex-post suboptimal, then he incurs regret toward the foregone best alternative (FBA), the level of wealth he would have obtained from the ex-post optimal choices. We assume the investor feels regret/pride for all past decisions including the current one; that is, the FWA and FBA are derived with respect to all decisions up to and including the current one. 6

7 This assumption addresses the issue of how the feeling of regret and pride interact and accumulate over time. A decision rule might turn out to be optimal over the rst period but suboptimal over the second period. Here, we assume that the feeling of regret is stronger than pride in the sense that the individual incurs regret as long as one decision turns out to be ex-post sub-optimal; put di erently, the individual incurs pride only if all decisions turn out to be ex-post optimal. In that case, we assume that his additional utility from pride is measured in reference to the FWA. 3 Optimal Portfolio Choice and the Disposition E ect In this section, we examine how an individual who is prone to feelings of regret and pride makes decisions in a dynamic portfolio choice problem. In the rst subsection, we investigate the optimal decision at t = under the assumption that the individual invested in the stock at t =. show that, under certain conditions, the disposition e ect can emerge as the optimal strategy: conditional on the stock gaining value over the rst period, it is optimal to sell the stock at t =, and conditional on the stock losing value over the rst period, it is optimal to hold the stock over the second period. In the second subsection, we solve for the dynamically optimal choice including the initial decision at t = and show that, under the same conditions, the disposition e ect can emerge as an optimal strategy. That is, it can be optimal for the investor to buy the stock at t =, and then sell it at t = if it went up or hold it if it went down over the rst period. 3. Portfolio Choice at t = We assume that the investor bought the stock at t =, i.e. his level of wealth at t = is given by ~w = w ( + ~x ), which can take the two values w + = w ( + x + ) > w or w = w ( + x ) < w depending on whether the stock went up or down over the rst period. The following proposition determines the condition under which it is optimal for the individual to follow the disposition strategy. Proposition Suppose the individual bought the stock at t =. We It is then optimal for the individual with 6= at t = to sell the stock if it went up and to keep the stock if it went down over the rst period if and only if stock returns satisfy the following two conditions < pkg (w ( + x + )) w p + x + + ( p) + x + kg + x + 2( )! + ( p) kg (w ( + x + )) w + x +! + x! (4) 7

8 and > pkg (w ( + x )) (w ( + x + )) p + x + + ( p) + x + kg + x! + ( p) kg For =, i.e. u (w) = ln (w), the conditions are ln and ln w w + x! + x 2( )!. (5) + x + p + x p +kg ln + x + < pkg 2 ln + x + +( p) kg ln + x + x + p + x p +kg ln + x > pkg ln + x +( p) kg 2 ln + x. Proof. See Appendix A.. Condition (4) implies that selling the stock after it went up over the rst period is optimal. depends on the equity premium and the relative strength of the certain feeling of pride when selling the stock versus the uncertain feeling of additional pride or regret when holding the stock over the second period. period is optimal. Condition (5) assures that keeping the stock after it goes down over the rst Again, this condition depends on the equity premium and the relative strength of the certain feeling of regret when selling the stock versus the uncertain feeling of additional or less regret when holding the stock over the second period. with the disposition e ect if both conditions hold. (6) (7) Optimal behavior is thus consistent In the following lemma we show that condition 3 on stock returns does not further restrict the set of stock returns that are consistent with the disposition e ect. It Lemma Suppose that stock returns satisfy condition 5. Then condition 3 holds. Proof. See Appendix A.2. We provide intuition for why both conditions can hold by focusing on the e ects of the following two interrelated changes to the optimal choice: increasing the equity premium and adding anticipated regret and pride to the decision making, i.e. the second attribute of the utility function v () in equation (). Considering the rst attribute of the utility function, u (), increasing the equity premium makes keeping the stock at t = more attractive, independent of the stock s movement over the rst period. For a xed equity premium, adding the second attribute, kg(u(w alt ) u (w)), makes selling the stock at t = more attractive, again independent of the stock s movement over the rst period. This is due to the convexity of g (), as the individual prefers a certain level of regret and pride by selling the stock to an uncertain exposure to regret and pride by keeping the stock. In other words, an individual who considers anticipated regret and pride in his decision 8

9 making requires a higher equity premium for keeping the stock than an individual whose preferences do not include these psychological factors. The crucial e ect that implies di erent behavioral responses to the stock s movement over the rst period arises from the di erent e ects that a marginal increase in the equity premium has on regret and pride, i.e. on the second attribute of the utility function. If the stock went down over the rst period, then the individual will always feel regret and never pride, as he already made a suboptimal decision at t = (see Assumption 2). If the stock went up, however, the individual will either only feel pride if he sells the stock or he will expose himself to either regret or even greater pride if he keeps the stock. Marginally increasing the equity premium will impact the di erences in the marginal e ects between selling and keeping the stock. If this di erence is larger after an up-move of the stock over the rst period than after a down-move, then selling the stock would be marginally more attractive after an up-move, which can imply optimal behavior consistent with the disposition e ect. To focus on those e ects, suppose that =, i.e. u (w) = ln (w), p = =2, and that we increase the equity premium by marginally increasing the positive return, x +, while keeping the negative return, x, xed. 3 If the stock went down over the rst period, there is no e ect on the impact of the second attribute, as it solely depends on x (see lower limit in condition (7)). Conversely, if the stock went up, the convexity of g () implies that the marginal increase in pride when selling the stock is larger than the potential marginal increase in pride when keeping the stock (see condition (6)). Thus, increasing the equity premium makes selling more attractive than buying when the stock has gone up over the rst period, while it has no e ect when the stock has gone down. As a result, there arises a situation in which anticipated regret and pride induces behavior that is consistent with the disposition e ect. These marginal e ects on the psychological factors have to be traded-o against the marginal e ect that an increase in the equity premium has on the rst attribute, i.e. the increased attractiveness of keeping the stock. Condition (4) implies that the risk premium is low enough such that the bene t of securing pride at t = by selling the stock outweighs the risky prospect of feeling even more pride at the cost of potentially incurring regret when keeping the stock. Condition (5) implies that the risk premium is high enough to compensate the individual for the risky prospect of feeling less regret at the cost of feeling even more regret when keeping the stock. In Section 3.3, we will show with an illustrative example that both conditions (4) and (5) can be satis ed and how they vary with the degrees of risk aversion and regret. 3.2 Dynamic Portfolio Choice In this section, we examine the dynamically optimal behavior of the individual with the preferences speci ed above. We thus endogenize the decision at t =. Let us emphasize again that this proved to be crucial for explaining the disposition e ect by loss aversion. Although loss aversion 3 Equivalent results obtain for 6= and/or increasing the equity premium by marginally increasing x while keeping x + xed. 9

10 can explain the disposition e ect conditional on having bought the stock at t = (Gomes 25, Kyle et al. 26), it can only explain the disposition e ect when the initial purchasing decision is endogenized for certain settings (Hens and Vlcek 25, Barberis and Xiong 26). We show in the following proposition that regret and pride can explain dynamic trading behavior which is consistent with the disposition e ect; that is, buying the stock at t = and selling (keeping) the stock after it went up (down) over the rst period. Furthermore, the necessary and su cient conditions on stock returns for the disposition e ect to hold in this dynamic setting are equivalent to the necessary and su cient conditions, (4) and (5), derived in the previous section. Proposition 2 It is optimal for the individual at t = to buy the stock and at t = to sell the stock if it went up and to keep the stock if it went down over the rst period if and only if stock returns satisfy conditions (4) and (5) when 6=. Proof. See Appendix A.3. For =, conditions (6) and (7) must hold. Therefore, in a dynamic portfolio choice problem, for a certain range of stock returns, i.e. under conditions (4) and (5), it is optimal for an investor who is prone to feeling regret and pride to follow the disposition e ect strategy. Note that the individual s behavior is time-consistent as he optimally plans at t = to follow the disposition e ect strategy at t = (Proposition 2) and at t = optimally executes this strategy (Proposition ). 3.3 Illustrative Example The objective of providing an illustrative example is to show how the set of stock returns that satisfy the necessary and su cient conditions (4) and (5) varies with the degrees of risk aversion and regret. Suppose that returns are not skewed, i.e. p = 2, w =, and that the function g () is given by g(x) = exp(x). Figure plots for k = three pairs of lines associated with three levels of coe cient of relative risk aversion: = thin lines, = 2 dashed lines, = 3 thick lines. Figure 2 plots for = three pairs of lines associated with three levels of degree of regret: k = thin lines, k = 2 dashed lines, k = 3 thick lines. 4 The lower line of each pair represents all levels of stock returns y = x + and x = x such that the lower constraint is binding. Analogously, the upper line of each pair represents the upper constraint. Thus, for any pair of stock returns (y; x) that falls between those two lines, the individual optimally follows the disposition strategy. 5 Otherwise, for any pair of stock returns (y; x) that is below the lower line it is optimal at t = to sell the stock independent of the stock s movement over the rst period. Equivalently, for any pair of stock returns (y; x) that is above the upper line it is optimal at t = to buy the stock independent of the stock s movement over the rst period. 4 Alternatively, the intensity of regret can be varied by the convexity of g. We obtain similar results for the less convex function g (x) = x 2. 5 We did not plot condition 3 as it does not further restrict the set of stock returns that are consistent with the disposition e ect (see Lemma ).

11 We note that increasing the degree of risk aversion and the intensity of regret has opposing e ects on the necessary and su cient conditions (4) condition (5). Condition (4) for selling the stock after it went up becomes less stringent while condition (5) for keeping the stock after it went down becomes more stringent. The intuition is that increasing the degree of risk aversion increases the risk premium required for keeping the stock and increasing the intensity of regret increases the compensation for the risky prospect of regret and/or pride when keeping the stock. Therefore, selling the stock becomes more attractive x y Figure : This graph plots for p = =2, w =, k =, g(x) = exp(x), and various coe cients of relative risk aversion ( = thin lines, = 2 dashed lines, = 3 thick lines) the constraints on stock returns in conditions (4) and (5) which are neccesary and su cient for the disposition e ect to hold.

12 x y Figure 2: This graph plots for p = =2, w =, =, g(x) = exp(x), and various degrees of regret (k = thin lines, k = 2 dashed lines, k = 3 thick lines) the constraints on stock returns in conditions (4) and (5) which are neccesary and su cient for the disposition e ect to hold. 4 Discussion of Assumptions In this section, we discuss the importance of the assumptions made to explain the disposition e ect and give intuition about why deviations from those assumptions change the predictions. We focus on the portfolio choice at t =, as this is a necessary step in explaining the disposition e ect in a dynamic setting. The disposition e ect at t = would be reinforced by those changes in the assumptions that make selling the stock more attractive after it went up and make holding the stock more attractive after it went down over the rst period. Assumption The rst assumption considers whether the individual observes a stock s returns even if he does not hold it in his portfolio. By comparing the levels of expected utility as in the proof of Proposition, it can be shown that observing stock returns implies the opposite optimal decision after the stock went up, i.e. it 2

13 becomes optimal for the individual to keep the stock. This holds for any deviations in Assumption 2 that we discuss below. The intuition behind this result is as follows. Suppose the individual observes stock returns after selling the stock. Since he will observe the realization of the foregone alternative, he is exposed to a spread in feelings of regret and pride over the next period. As the function g () is convex, the individual s level of expected utility is lower when he is exposed to this spread compared to the situation in which he does not observe stock returns after selling and is thereby not exposed to this spread. Note that when holding the stock, the individual necessarily observes stock returns as they impact his level of wealth. Hence, observing stock returns makes selling less attractive and leads to the opposite optimal decision after the stock went up over the rst period, i.e. it is not optimal to follow the disposition strategy. This also implies that if the individual has the choice to observe stock returns or not, then it is optimal in our setting for him to not observe them and follow the disposition strategy under conditions (4) and (5). This relates to the result of Bell (983), who shows that it can be optimal for a regret-averse individual, i.e. with a convex function g (), to not have a foregone alternative lottery resolved. Remark 3 The importance of Assumption implies an interesting empirical prediction. Since it is more di cult to avoid news about the performance of stocks that receive media attention, our model predicts that the disposition e ect is more pronounced in the trading of stocks that receive little media coverage compared to those that receive a lot of media coverage, such as major stock market indices. Assumption 2 The second assumption relates to the reference level of wealth, w alt, toward which the individual feels regret or pride. In a dynamic setting, some decisions will elicit regret and others pride. This raises the interesting question how those feelings interact and aggregate. We assume that the individual only incurs feelings of pride if he has made choices that are all optimal after the fact. He then feels pride toward the FWA, which includes all decisions in the past and the current one. If one decision, either in the past or the current one, is sub-optimal, then the individual incurs regret toward the FBA. We discuss the following two deviations from Assumption 2 under both Assumption and its deviation. First, suppose the individual only considers regret in his decision making but not pride. Sugden (993) and Quiggin (994) provide an axiomatic foundation for regret in which the individual s disutility from regret depends only on the actual level of wealth and the level of wealth associated with the FBA. This change in assumption only potentially e ects the decision after the stock went up over the rst period as it is only then that the individual can incur pride. By comparing the levels of expected utility, it can be shown that by not considering pride, selling the stock becomes relatively less attractive compared to keeping the stock. Furthermore, this e ect implies that it is then never optimal to follow the disposition strategy at t =. 3

14 The intuition is that when keeping the stock, the individual only incurs pride if the stock went up over the second period. When selling the stock the individual incurs a certain level of pride (if he does not observe returns) or he incurs pride if the stock goes down over the second period (if he observes returns). In both cases, the convexity of g () implies that the ex-ante value of foregone pride is smaller when keeping the stock compared to the ex-ante value when selling the stock. Note that in the latter case in which the individual observes all stock returns, it is more valuable to incur pride when the stock goes down compared to when it goes up over the second period. Therefore, not considering pride makes selling the stock relatively less attractive compared to keeping it. Second, suppose that past decisions do not matter with respect to the anticipated feeling of regret or pride, i.e. at t = the individual only considers the current decision when evaluating those feelings and not his decision at t =. By comparing the levels of expected utility, it can be shown that if the individual only considers the current decision, selling the stock becomes relatively less attractive after it goes up but relatively more attractive after it goes down over the rst period compared to keeping the stock. Furthermore, this e ect implies that it is then never optimal to follow the disposition strategy at t =. The intuition behind this result is similar to above. After the stock goes up over the rst period, if not considering the pride from the initial decision at t =, relatively more pride is taken away when selling the stock compared to keeping it. As argued above, this is implied by the convexity of g (). However, after the stock goes down, the disutility from regret is larger when keeping the stock compared to selling it. Not considering regret from the initial decision at t = thus makes selling relatively more attractive. We conclude that these deviations from Assumptions and 2 make selling the stock less attractive after it goes up and potentially make keeping the stock less attractive after it goes down over the rst period. Those e ects work against the disposition strategy and imply its non-optimality. Assumptions and 2 are thus crucial for explaining the disposition e ect with investors feelings of regret and pride. Furthermore, the convexity of g () is also a crucial assumption in explaining how anticipated regret and pride can lead to the disposition e ect. 5 Conclusion Prior empirical analyses have shown that trading patterns in capital markets exhibit the disposition e ect, and current theoretical work has shown that loss aversion can only provide a rationale for this e ect in particular settings. In this paper, we formally investigate whether the avoidance of regret and the quest for pride leads to trading behavior that is consistent with the disposition e ect. As with loss aversion, we do nd speci c conditions under which the feelings of regret and pride are compatible with the disposition e ect; yet, this result is not robust to variations of the model. Extensions of this model include considering multiple time periods and/or divisible assets. Doing so, we believe, will add other e ects, but we argue that even with such extensions, investors e orts to avoid regret and seek pride will only explain the disposition e ect under certain conditions. 4

15 Understanding how regret and pride a ect investors trading behavior and possibly, the disposition e ect enables us to learn more about the potential costs these investors may incur, which is especially relevant for the current debate surrounding the introduction of Personal Retirement Accounts (PRAs) to the Social Security system. Shapira and Venezia (2) and Dhar and Zhu (26) have shown that investors with less trading experience and/or lower income exhibit a stronger disposition e ect, which may lead to lower after-tax returns. The introduction of PRAs would thus lead to a much more pronounced disposition e ect in capital markets and provides a rationale for policymakers to protect investors with such demographic characteristics. It is important to understand individuals trading behavior and the extent to which di erent factors a ect it, which we do here with regard to regret and pride. 5

16 References [] Andreassen, P. B Explaining the price-volume relationship: the di erence between price changes and changing prices. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes [2] Barber, B. M., Y. Lee, Y. Liu, and T. Odean. 26. Is the aggregate investor reluctant to realize losses? Evidence from Taiwan. Working paper. [3] Barber, B. M. and T. Odean. 25. Individual investors. In Advances in Behavioral Finance Volume II. Ed. Richard H. Thaler. New York: Princeton UP, [4] Barber, B., T. Odean, and M. Strahilevitz. 24. Once burned, twice shy: naive learning, counterfactuals, and the repurchase of stocks previously sold. Working paper. [5] Barberis, N. and W. Xiong. 26. What drives the disposition e ect? An analysis of a long-standing preference-based explanation. Working paper. [6] Bell, D. E Regret in decision making under uncertainty. Operations Research 3(5) [7] Bell, D. E Risk premiums for decision regret. Management Science 29() [8] Bleichrodt, H., A. Cillo, and E. Diecidue. 26. A quantitative measurement of regret theory. Working paper. [9] Braun, M. and A. Muermann. 24. The impact of regret on the demand for insurance. Journal of Risk and Insurance 7(4) [] Coval, J. and T. Shumway. 25. Do behavioral biases a ect prices? Journal of Finance 6() -34. [] Dhar, R. and N. Zhu. 26. Up close and personal: investor sophistication and the disposition e ect. Management Science 52(5) [2] Einio, M. and V. Puttonen. 26. Disposition e ect in the apartment market. Working Paper. [3] Ferris, S. P., R. Haugen, and A. Makhija Predicting contemporary volume with historic volume at di erential price levels: evidence supporting the disposition e ect. Journal of Finance 43(3) [4] Filiz, E. and E.Y. Ozbay. 27. Auctions with anticipated regret: theory and experiment. American Economic Review 97(4) [5] Genesove, D. and C. Mayer. 2. Loss aversion and seller behavior: evidence from the housing market. Quarterly Journal of Economics [6] Gollier, C. and B. Salanié. 26. Individual decisions under risk, risk sharing, and asset prices with regret. Working paper. 6

17 [7] Gomes, F. 25. Portfolio choice and trading volume with loss-averse investors. Journal of Business 78(2) [8] Grinblatt, M. and M. Keloharju. 2. What makes investors trade? Journal of Finance 56(2) [9] Gross, L The art of selling intangibles: how to make your million ($) by investing other people s money. New York Institute of Finance, New York. [2] Heath, C., S. Huddart, and M. Lang Psychological factors and stock option exercise. Quarterly Journal of Economics 4(2) [2] Hens, T. and M. Vlcek. 25. Does prospect theory explain the disposition e ect? Working paper. [22] Kahneman, D. and A. Tversky Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica [23] Kahneman, D. and A. Tversky The psychology of preferences. Scienti c American [24] Kyle, A., H. Ou-Yang, and W. Xiong. 26. Prospect theory and liquidation decisions. Journal of Economic Theory 29() [25] Locke, P. and S. Mann. 2. Do professional traders exhibit loss realization aversion? Working paper. [26] Lakonishok, J. and S. Smidt Volume for winners and losers: taxation and other motives for stock trading. Journal of Finance 4(4) [27] Loomes, G. and R. Sugden Regret theory: an alternative theory of rational choice under uncertainty. Economic Journal 92(368) [28] Michenaud, S. and B. Solnik. 26. Applying regret theory to investment choices: currency hedging decisions. Working paper. [29] Muermann, A., O. S. Mitchell, and J. Volkman. 26. Regret, portfolio choice, and guarantees in de ned contribution schemes. Insurance: Mathematics and Economics 39(2) [3] O Curry Fogel, S. and T. Berry. 26. The disposition e ect and individual investor decisions: the roles of regret and counterfactual alternatives. Journal of Behavioral Finance 7(2) 7-6. [3] Odean, T Are investors reluctant to realize their losses? Journal of Finance 53(5) [32] Quiggin, J Regret theory with general choice sets. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 8(2) [33] Shapira, Z. and I. Venezia. 2. Patterns of behavior of professionally managed and independent investors. Journal of Banking and Finance 25(8)

18 [34] Shefrin, H. and M. Statman The disposition to sell winners too early and ride losers too long: theory and evidence. Journal of Finance 4(3) [35] Sugden, R An axiomatic foundation of regret. Journal of Economic Theory 6() [36] Thaler, R. 98. Toward a positive theory of consumer choice. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization [37] Thaler, R Mental accounting and consumer choice. Marketing Science 4(3) [38] Tversky, A. and D. Kahneman Advances in prospect theory: cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 5(4) [39] Weber, M. and C. F. Camerer The disposition e ect in securities trading: an experimental analysis. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization [4] Weber, M. and F. Welfens. 26. The repurchase behavior of individual investors: an experimental investigation. Working Paper. 8

19 A Appendix: Proofs A. Proof of Proposition Suppose the stock went up over the rst period such that the individual s level of wealth at t = is w + = w ( + x + ) > w. If he sells the stock then Assumptions and 2 imply that the individual incurs additional utility at t = 2 from pride about his decision at t =. Note that Assumption implies that the individual does not observe the realization of the stock at t = 2 and thereby foregoes potential regret or additional pride over the second period. The FWA would have been to not invest in the stock at t = which yields w alt = w. His nal level of utility from selling the stock is thus (w ( + x + )) kg w! (w ( + x + )). If the individual keeps the stock at t = he either incurs additional pride if the stock went up again over the second period or regret if it went down. In the rst case, Assumption 2 implies that the individual incurs pride towards the FWA which is not to have invested at all, i.e. w alt = w. individual made the optimal choice at t = but the sub-optimal choice at t =. In the latter case, the Assumption 2 implies that, in aggregate, the individual incurs regret towards the FBA which is to have invested in the stock at t = and sold it at t = yielding w alt = w ( + x + ). w ( + x + ) 2 B + ( p) B w (w ( + x + ) ( + x )) His nal level of expected utility is then w ( + x + ) 2 kg CC AA (w ( + x + )) Selling the stock at t = is preferred by the individual if and only if < pkg (w ( + x + )) w p + x + + ( p) + x + kg + x + 2( )! + ( p) kg (w ( + x + ))!! (w ( + x + ) ( + x )) w + x +! + x!. (8) Now suppose the stock went down over the rst period. If the individual sells the stock at t = he incurs regret about his decision at t = which leads to a nal level of utility (w ( + x )) kg w! (w ( + x )). 9

20 If he keeps the stock then Assumption 2 implies that he will incur regret independent of the stock movement over the second periods as he made a sub-optimal choice once at t =. The level of expected utility is then!! (w ( + x + ) ( + x )) (w ( + x + )) (w ( + x + ) ( + x )) p kg w ( + x ) 2 w ( + x ) 2 B + ( B w CC AA. Keeping the stock at t = is preferred to selling it if and only if > pkg (w ( + x )) (w ( + x + )) p + x + + ( p) + x + kg + x! + ( p) kg w w + x! + x 2( )!. (9) Note that the right-hand side of inequality (9) is positive as g is increasing. Both conditions (8) and (9) must be satis ed for the disposition strategy to be optimal at t =. For =, the proof is equivalent. A.2 Proof of Lemma Suppose 6=. Condition 5 is equivalent to > pkg (w ( + x )) kg (w ( + x + )) w p + x + + ( p) + x + x! + ( p) kg + x!. The right-hand side of this inequality is positive as > g > g pkg w (w ( + x + )) w + x! + ( p) kg w w + x p + x + + ( p) + + x! + x!. The rst inequality holds as g is convex and the second inequality holds since p + x + + ( p) + + x > + x 2( )! + x 2( )! 2

21 for all 6=. Therefore, the left-hand side of the above inequality must be positive, i.e. p ( + x + ) + ( p) ( + x ) > which is equivalent to condition 3. For =, the proof is equivalent. A.3 Proof of Proposition 2 Following the disposition strategy yields a level of expected utility!! p (w ( + x + )) w (w ( + x + )) kg!! +p ( p) (w ( + x + ) ( + x )) (w ( + x + )) (w ( + x + ) ( + x )) kg w ( + x ) 2 w ( + x ) 2 + ( p) 2 B w CC AA. Next, examine all possible other strategies and compare their level of expected utility with the one derived from the disposition strategy.. The individual invests in the stock only once which yields a level of expected utility p (w ( + x + )) + ( p) kg (w ( + x )) w kg!! (w ( + x + )) w The disposition strategy is preferred to this strategy if and only if > pkg (w ( + x )) (w ( + x + )) which is equivalent to condition (5). p + x + + ( p) + x + kg + x! + ( p) kg!! (w ( + x )). w w + x! + x 2( )! () 2

22 2. The individual invests twice into the stock which yields a level of expected utility p 2 w ( + x + ) 2 + ( p) 2 +2p ( p) w ( + x ) 2 B w (w ( + x + ) ( + x )) B w w ( + x + ) 2 kg CC AA w ( + x ) 2 (w ( + x + )) The disposition strategy is preferred to this strategy if and only if < pkg (w ( + x + )) w which is equivalent to condition (4). p + x + + ( p) + x + kg + x + 2( )! + ( p) kg (w ( + x + )) CC AA!! (w ( + x + ) ( + x )). w 3. The individual does not invest in the stock at all which yields a level of utility w. The disposition strategy is preferred to this strategy if and only if w > pkg + x +! + x! () + ( p) + x p + x + + ( p) + x w +p ( p) kg + x +! + ( p) 2 kg (w ( + x + )) w + x 2( )! + x! (2) which is equivalent to (w ( + x )) > + x k "pg +p ( p) g + ( p) + x p + x + + ( p) + x w (w ( + x + )) + x +! + ( p) 2 g + x!#. w + x 2( )! 22

23 Condition () is equivalent to > (w ( + x )) + ( p) + x p + x + + ( p) + x + ( p) + x " (w ( + x + )) k pg + x! + ( p) g w + x 2( )! g w + x!# Condition () implies condition (2) if + ( p) + x " pg + ( p) g w > + x "pg +p ( p) g which is equivalent to pg (w ( + x + )) + x 2( )! g w (w ( + x + )) (w ( + x + )) + ( p) + x g w + x +! + ( p) 2 g + x!# + x! + ( p) g w + x! + x!# w w + x! + x 2( )! + x 2( )! > p + x w g + x +!. (3) 23

24 The right-hand side of this inequality is negative. For the left-hand side, we deduce pg (w ( + x + )) + ( p) + x g > g p (w ( + x + )) + ( p) + x g + x! + ( p) g w w + x! + x 2( )! + x + ( p) w + x! 2( ) w + x! = g p w + x + + x > g > + + ( p) + x w + x! + ( p) + x g w + x! + ( p) + x w + x! + ( p) + x g w + x! The rst inequality follows from the convexity of g. The second inequality holds since p w and g is increasing. The last inequality holds since and + x + + x > + ( p) + x > w + x >, and since g (ab) > ag (b) for all a >, b >, and g convex. 6 The left-hand side of inequality (3) is therefore positive and thus satis ed which implies that condition () implies condition (2). 4. The individual invests in the stock at t = and at t = keeps the stock if it went up or sells the stock 6 Proof. De ne h (b) = g (ab) ag (b). Then h () = (as g () = ) and h (b) = a (g (ab) g (b)) > for all a >, b >, and g convex. Thus h (b) > for all a >, b >, and g convex. 24

INVESTORS DECISION TO TRADE STOCKS AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY. Sharon Shafran, Uri Ben-Zion and Tal Shavit. Discussion Paper No. 07-08.

INVESTORS DECISION TO TRADE STOCKS AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY. Sharon Shafran, Uri Ben-Zion and Tal Shavit. Discussion Paper No. 07-08. INVESTORS DECISION TO TRADE STOCKS AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY Sharon Shafran, Uri Ben-Zion and Tal Shavit Discussion Paper No. 07-08 July 2007 Monaster Center for Economic Research Ben-Gurion University of

More information

Investors decision to trade stocks. An experimental study

Investors decision to trade stocks. An experimental study Investors decision to trade stocks An experimental study Sharon Shafran, Uri Benzion and Tal Shavit Sharon Shafran. Department of Management and Economics, The Open University of Israel, 108 Rabutzki,

More information

Regret and Rejoicing Effects on Mixed Insurance *

Regret and Rejoicing Effects on Mixed Insurance * Regret and Rejoicing Effects on Mixed Insurance * Yoichiro Fujii, Osaka Sangyo University Mahito Okura, Doshisha Women s College of Liberal Arts Yusuke Osaki, Osaka Sangyo University + Abstract This papers

More information

PROSPECT THEORY AND INVESTORS TRADING BEHAVIOUR MARKET. Philip Brown Gary Smith * Kate Wilkie. Abstract

PROSPECT THEORY AND INVESTORS TRADING BEHAVIOUR MARKET. Philip Brown Gary Smith * Kate Wilkie. Abstract PROSPECT THEORY AND INVESTORS TRADING BEHAVIOUR IN THE AUSTRALIAN STOCK MARKET by Philip Brown Gary Smith * Kate Wilkie Abstract What, apart from taxation incentives and information arrival, explains inter-temporal

More information

Hidden Regret in Insurance Markets

Hidden Regret in Insurance Markets Hidden Regret in Insurance Markets Rachel J. Huang y Alexander Muermann z Larry Y. Tzeng x This version: September 2014 Abstract We examine insurance markets with two-dimensional asymmetric information

More information

Information Asymmetry, Price Momentum, and the Disposition Effect

Information Asymmetry, Price Momentum, and the Disposition Effect Information Asymmetry, Price Momentum, and the Disposition Effect Günter Strobl The Wharton School University of Pennsylvania October 2003 Job Market Paper Abstract Economists have long been puzzled by

More information

Papier Papier LARGE. n 2008-09. Are French Individual Investors reluctant to realize their losses?

Papier Papier LARGE. n 2008-09. Are French Individual Investors reluctant to realize their losses? Laboratoire de Recherche en Gestion & Economie LARGE Papier Papier n 2008-09 Are French Individual Investors reluctant to realize their losses? Shaneera Boolell-Gunesh / Marie-Hélène Broihanne / Maxime

More information

Optimal insurance contracts with adverse selection and comonotonic background risk

Optimal insurance contracts with adverse selection and comonotonic background risk Optimal insurance contracts with adverse selection and comonotonic background risk Alary D. Bien F. TSE (LERNA) University Paris Dauphine Abstract In this note, we consider an adverse selection problem

More information

Prospect Theory and the Disposition Effect

Prospect Theory and the Disposition Effect Prospect Theory and the Disposition Effect Markku Kaustia Abstract This paper shows that prospect theory is unlikely to explain the disposition effect. Prospect theory predicts that the propensity to sell

More information

Rolling Mental Accounts. Cary D. Frydman* Samuel M. Hartzmark. David H. Solomon* This Draft: November 17th, 2015

Rolling Mental Accounts. Cary D. Frydman* Samuel M. Hartzmark. David H. Solomon* This Draft: November 17th, 2015 Rolling Mental Accounts Cary D. Frydman* Samuel M. Hartzmark David H. Solomon* This Draft: November 17th, 2015 Abstract: When investors sell one asset and quickly buy another, their trades are consistent

More information

Prospect Theory and the Demand for Insurance

Prospect Theory and the Demand for Insurance Prospect Theory and the emand for Insurance avid L. Eckles and Jacqueline Volkman Wise ecember 211 Abstract We examine the effect of prospect theory preferences on the demand for insurance to determine

More information

Corporate Income Taxation

Corporate Income Taxation Corporate Income Taxation We have stressed that tax incidence must be traced to people, since corporations cannot bear the burden of a tax. Why then tax corporations at all? There are several possible

More information

Lecture Notes: Basic Concepts in Option Pricing - The Black and Scholes Model

Lecture Notes: Basic Concepts in Option Pricing - The Black and Scholes Model Brunel University Msc., EC5504, Financial Engineering Prof Menelaos Karanasos Lecture Notes: Basic Concepts in Option Pricing - The Black and Scholes Model Recall that the price of an option is equal to

More information

Mental-accounting portfolio

Mental-accounting portfolio Portfolios for Investors Who Want to Reach Their Goals While Staying on the Mean Variance Efficient Frontier SANJIV DAS is a professor of finance at the Leavey School of Business, Santa Clara University,

More information

Behavior in a Simplified Stock Market: The Status Quo Bias, the Disposition Effect and the Ostrich Effect

Behavior in a Simplified Stock Market: The Status Quo Bias, the Disposition Effect and the Ostrich Effect Behavior in a Simplified Stock Market: The Status Quo Bias, the Disposition Effect and the Ostrich Effect Alexander L. Brown Division of Humanities and Social Sciences California Institute of Technology

More information

1 Uncertainty and Preferences

1 Uncertainty and Preferences In this chapter, we present the theory of consumer preferences on risky outcomes. The theory is then applied to study the demand for insurance. Consider the following story. John wants to mail a package

More information

Are Investors Reluctant to Realize Their Losses?

Are Investors Reluctant to Realize Their Losses? THE JOURNAL OF FINANCE VOL. LIII, NO. 5 OCTOBER 1998 Are Investors Reluctant to Realize Their Losses? TERRANCE ODEAN* ABSTRACT I test the disposition effect, the tendency of investors to hold losing investments

More information

The Equity Premium in India

The Equity Premium in India The Equity Premium in India Rajnish Mehra University of California, Santa Barbara and National Bureau of Economic Research January 06 Prepared for the Oxford Companion to Economics in India edited by Kaushik

More information

4. Only one asset that can be used for production, and is available in xed supply in the aggregate (call it land).

4. Only one asset that can be used for production, and is available in xed supply in the aggregate (call it land). Chapter 3 Credit and Business Cycles Here I present a model of the interaction between credit and business cycles. In representative agent models, remember, no lending takes place! The literature on the

More information

CHAPTER 1: INTRODUCTION, BACKGROUND, AND MOTIVATION. Over the last decades, risk analysis and corporate risk management activities have

CHAPTER 1: INTRODUCTION, BACKGROUND, AND MOTIVATION. Over the last decades, risk analysis and corporate risk management activities have Chapter 1 INTRODUCTION, BACKGROUND, AND MOTIVATION 1.1 INTRODUCTION Over the last decades, risk analysis and corporate risk management activities have become very important elements for both financial

More information

The Stock Market, Monetary Policy, and Economic Development

The Stock Market, Monetary Policy, and Economic Development The Stock Market, Monetary Policy, and Economic Development Edgar A. Ghossoub University of Texas at San Antonio Robert R. Reed University of Alabama July, 20 Abstract In this paper, we examine the impact

More information

On Compulsory Per-Claim Deductibles in Automobile Insurance

On Compulsory Per-Claim Deductibles in Automobile Insurance The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, 28: 25 32, 2003 c 2003 The Geneva Association On Compulsory Per-Claim Deductibles in Automobile Insurance CHU-SHIU LI Department of Economics, Feng Chia

More information

Interlinkages between Payment and Securities. Settlement Systems

Interlinkages between Payment and Securities. Settlement Systems Interlinkages between Payment and Securities Settlement Systems David C. Mills, Jr. y Federal Reserve Board Samia Y. Husain Washington University in Saint Louis September 4, 2009 Abstract Payments systems

More information

The E ect of Trading Commissions on Analysts Forecast Bias

The E ect of Trading Commissions on Analysts Forecast Bias The E ect of Trading Commissions on Analysts Forecast Bias Anne Beyer and Ilan Guttman Stanford University September 2007 Abstract The paper models the interaction between a sell-side analyst and a risk-averse

More information

Day Trader Behavior and Performance: Evidence from the Taiwan Futures Market

Day Trader Behavior and Performance: Evidence from the Taiwan Futures Market Day Trader Behavior and Performance: Evidence from the Taiwan Futures Market Teng Yuan Cheng*, Hung Chih Li, Nan-Ting Chou, Kerry A. Watkins ABSTRACT Using data from the Taiwan futures market, a closer

More information

Hedging Using Forward Contracts

Hedging Using Forward Contracts 10 CHAPTER 1 Business Snapshot1.1 Hedge Funds Hedge funds have become major users of derivatives for hedging, speculation, and arbitrage. A hedge fund is similar to a mutual fund in that it invests funds

More information

The Term Structure of Interest Rates, Spot Rates, and Yield to Maturity

The Term Structure of Interest Rates, Spot Rates, and Yield to Maturity Chapter 5 How to Value Bonds and Stocks 5A-1 Appendix 5A The Term Structure of Interest Rates, Spot Rates, and Yield to Maturity In the main body of this chapter, we have assumed that the interest rate

More information

Insurance Demand and Prospect Theory. by Ulrich Schmidt

Insurance Demand and Prospect Theory. by Ulrich Schmidt Insurance Demand and Prospect Theory by Ulrich Schmidt No. 1750 January 2012 Kiel Institute for the World Economy, Hindenburgufer 66, 24105 Kiel, Germany Kiel Working Paper No. 1750 January 2012 Insurance

More information

Life Cycle Asset Allocation A Suitable Approach for Defined Contribution Pension Plans

Life Cycle Asset Allocation A Suitable Approach for Defined Contribution Pension Plans Life Cycle Asset Allocation A Suitable Approach for Defined Contribution Pension Plans Challenges for defined contribution plans While Eastern Europe is a prominent example of the importance of defined

More information

1 Volatility Trading Strategies

1 Volatility Trading Strategies Brunel University Msc., EC5504, Financial Engineering Prof Menelaos Karanasos Lecture Notes: Volatility Trading Strategies 1 Volatility Trading Strategies As previously explained, volatility is essentially

More information

Spot Market Power and Futures Market Trading

Spot Market Power and Futures Market Trading Spot Market Power and Futures Market Trading Alexander Muermann and Stephen H. Shore The Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania March 2005 Abstract When a spot market monopolist participates in the

More information

The relationship between exchange rates, interest rates. In this lecture we will learn how exchange rates accommodate equilibrium in

The relationship between exchange rates, interest rates. In this lecture we will learn how exchange rates accommodate equilibrium in The relationship between exchange rates, interest rates In this lecture we will learn how exchange rates accommodate equilibrium in financial markets. For this purpose we examine the relationship between

More information

Quality differentiation and entry choice between online and offline markets

Quality differentiation and entry choice between online and offline markets Quality differentiation and entry choice between online and offline markets Yijuan Chen Australian National University Xiangting u Renmin University of China Sanxi Li Renmin University of China ANU Working

More information

Online Appendix Feedback Effects, Asymmetric Trading, and the Limits to Arbitrage

Online Appendix Feedback Effects, Asymmetric Trading, and the Limits to Arbitrage Online Appendix Feedback Effects, Asymmetric Trading, and the Limits to Arbitrage Alex Edmans LBS, NBER, CEPR, and ECGI Itay Goldstein Wharton Wei Jiang Columbia May 8, 05 A Proofs of Propositions and

More information

Do Losses Linger? Evidence from Proprietary Stock Traders. Ryan Garvey, Anthony Murphy, and Fei Wu *,** Revised November 2005

Do Losses Linger? Evidence from Proprietary Stock Traders. Ryan Garvey, Anthony Murphy, and Fei Wu *,** Revised November 2005 Do Losses Linger? Evidence from Proprietary Stock Traders Ryan Garvey, Anthony Murphy, and Fei Wu *,** Revised November 2005 * Ryan Garvey is assistant professor of finance at the A.J. Palumbo School of

More information

Rank dependent expected utility theory explains the St. Petersburg paradox

Rank dependent expected utility theory explains the St. Petersburg paradox Rank dependent expected utility theory explains the St. Petersburg paradox Ali al-nowaihi, University of Leicester Sanjit Dhami, University of Leicester Jia Zhu, University of Leicester Working Paper No.

More information

Futures Price d,f $ 0.65 = (1.05) (1.04)

Futures Price d,f $ 0.65 = (1.05) (1.04) 24 e. Currency Futures In a currency futures contract, you enter into a contract to buy a foreign currency at a price fixed today. To see how spot and futures currency prices are related, note that holding

More information

11 Option. Payoffs and Option Strategies. Answers to Questions and Problems

11 Option. Payoffs and Option Strategies. Answers to Questions and Problems 11 Option Payoffs and Option Strategies Answers to Questions and Problems 1. Consider a call option with an exercise price of $80 and a cost of $5. Graph the profits and losses at expiration for various

More information

CAPM, Arbitrage, and Linear Factor Models

CAPM, Arbitrage, and Linear Factor Models CAPM, Arbitrage, and Linear Factor Models CAPM, Arbitrage, Linear Factor Models 1/ 41 Introduction We now assume all investors actually choose mean-variance e cient portfolios. By equating these investors

More information

Do capital adequacy requirements reduce risks in banking?

Do capital adequacy requirements reduce risks in banking? Journal of Banking & Finance 23 (1999) 755±771 Do capital adequacy requirements reduce risks in banking? Jurg Blum * Institut zur Erforschung der wirtschaftlichen Entwicklung, University of Freiburg, D-79085

More information

Market Power, Forward Trading and Supply Function. Competition

Market Power, Forward Trading and Supply Function. Competition Market Power, Forward Trading and Supply Function Competition Matías Herrera Dappe University of Maryland May, 2008 Abstract When rms can produce any level of output, strategic forward trading can enhance

More information

Derivative Users Traders of derivatives can be categorized as hedgers, speculators, or arbitrageurs.

Derivative Users Traders of derivatives can be categorized as hedgers, speculators, or arbitrageurs. OPTIONS THEORY Introduction The Financial Manager must be knowledgeable about derivatives in order to manage the price risk inherent in financial transactions. Price risk refers to the possibility of loss

More information

Fixed odds bookmaking with stochastic betting demands

Fixed odds bookmaking with stochastic betting demands Fixed odds bookmaking with stochastic betting demands Stewart Hodges Hao Lin January 4, 2009 Abstract This paper provides a model of bookmaking in the market for bets in a British horse race. The bookmaker

More information

Returns Achieved by International and Local Investors in Stock Markets: Comparative Study using Evidence from the MENA Region Conceptual Framework

Returns Achieved by International and Local Investors in Stock Markets: Comparative Study using Evidence from the MENA Region Conceptual Framework Returns Achieved by International and Local Investors in Stock Markets: Comparative Study using Evidence from the MENA Region Conceptual Framework 1 st May 2016 1 RETURNS ACHIEVED BY INTERNATIONAL AND

More information

IS MORE INFORMATION BETTER? THE EFFECT OF TRADERS IRRATIONAL BEHAVIOR ON AN ARTIFICIAL STOCK MARKET

IS MORE INFORMATION BETTER? THE EFFECT OF TRADERS IRRATIONAL BEHAVIOR ON AN ARTIFICIAL STOCK MARKET IS MORE INFORMATION BETTER? THE EFFECT OF TRADERS IRRATIONAL BEHAVIOR ON AN ARTIFICIAL STOCK MARKET Wei T. Yue Alok R. Chaturvedi Shailendra Mehta Krannert Graduate School of Management Purdue University

More information

Exact Nonparametric Tests for Comparing Means - A Personal Summary

Exact Nonparametric Tests for Comparing Means - A Personal Summary Exact Nonparametric Tests for Comparing Means - A Personal Summary Karl H. Schlag European University Institute 1 December 14, 2006 1 Economics Department, European University Institute. Via della Piazzuola

More information

Financial Markets. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Financial Markets. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Financial Markets Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania 1 Trading and Price Formation This line of the literature analyzes the formation of prices in financial markets in a setting

More information

Debiasing the disposition effect by reducing the saliency of information about a stock s purchase price. Cary Frydman 1 and Antonio Rangel 2

Debiasing the disposition effect by reducing the saliency of information about a stock s purchase price. Cary Frydman 1 and Antonio Rangel 2 Debiasing the disposition effect by reducing the saliency of information about a stock s purchase price Cary Frydman 1 and Antonio Rangel 2 Abstract. The disposition effect refers to the empirical fact

More information

How to Win the Stock Market Game

How to Win the Stock Market Game How to Win the Stock Market Game 1 Developing Short-Term Stock Trading Strategies by Vladimir Daragan PART 1 Table of Contents 1. Introduction 2. Comparison of trading strategies 3. Return per trade 4.

More information

How credit analysts view and use the financial statements

How credit analysts view and use the financial statements How credit analysts view and use the financial statements Introduction Traditionally it is viewed that equity investment is high risk and bond investment low risk. Bondholders look at companies for creditworthiness,

More information

Rethinking Fixed Income

Rethinking Fixed Income Rethinking Fixed Income Challenging Conventional Wisdom May 2013 Risk. Reinsurance. Human Resources. Rethinking Fixed Income: Challenging Conventional Wisdom With US Treasury interest rates at, or near,

More information

General Risk Disclosure

General Risk Disclosure General Risk Disclosure Colmex Pro Ltd (hereinafter called the Company ) is an Investment Firm regulated by the Cyprus Securities and Exchange Commission (license number 123/10). This notice is provided

More information

Low-Volatility Investing: Expect the Unexpected

Low-Volatility Investing: Expect the Unexpected WHITE PAPER October 2014 For professional investors Low-Volatility Investing: Expect the Unexpected David Blitz, PhD Pim van Vliet, PhD Low-Volatility Investing: Expect the Unexpected 1 Expect the unexpected

More information

Distribution-Based Pricing Formulas. Are Not Arbitrage-Free

Distribution-Based Pricing Formulas. Are Not Arbitrage-Free Author s Response To Michael G. Wacek s Discussion Of a Paper Published In Proceedings Volume XC Distribution-Based Pricing Formulas Are Not Arbitrage-Free By David L. Ruhm Author s reply to discussion

More information

10. Fixed-Income Securities. Basic Concepts

10. Fixed-Income Securities. Basic Concepts 0. Fixed-Income Securities Fixed-income securities (FIS) are bonds that have no default risk and their payments are fully determined in advance. Sometimes corporate bonds that do not necessarily have certain

More information

Using Behavioral Economics to Improve Diversification in 401(k) Plans: Solving the Company Stock Problem

Using Behavioral Economics to Improve Diversification in 401(k) Plans: Solving the Company Stock Problem Using Behavioral Economics to Improve Diversification in 401(k) Plans: Solving the Company Stock Problem Shlomo Benartzi The Anderson School at UCLA Richard H. Thaler The University of Chicago Investors

More information

The Disposition Effect of Taiwanese Open-end Mutual Fund. Investors: Recursive Threshold Model in Variable

The Disposition Effect of Taiwanese Open-end Mutual Fund. Investors: Recursive Threshold Model in Variable The Disposition Effect of Taiwanese Open-end Mutual Fund Investors: Recursive Threshold Model in Variable Chi-Lu Peng a, Jen-Sin Lee b, Jau-Rong Li c a Graduate School of Management, I-Shou University,

More information

On the Interconnection of Networks and Gains from Trade in Business Services

On the Interconnection of Networks and Gains from Trade in Business Services Toru Kikuchi / Journal of Economic Research 8 (2003) 69{76 69 On the Interconnection of Networks and Gains from Trade in Business Services Toru Kikuchi 1 Kobe University Received 1 April 2003; accepted

More information

Adverse Selection. Chapter 3

Adverse Selection. Chapter 3 Chapter 3 Adverse Selection Adverse selection, sometimes known as The Winner s Curse or Buyer s Remorse, is based on the observation that it can be bad news when an o er is accepted. Suppose that a buyer

More information

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Nathaniel Hendren January, 2014 Abstract Both Akerlof (1970) and Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976) show that

More information

Tiered and Value-based Health Care Networks

Tiered and Value-based Health Care Networks Tiered and Value-based Health Care Networks Ching-to Albert Ma Henry Y. Mak Department of Economics Department of Economics Boston Univeristy Indiana University Purdue University Indianapolis 270 Bay State

More information

Can a Lump-Sum Transfer Make Everyone Enjoy the Gains. from Free Trade?

Can a Lump-Sum Transfer Make Everyone Enjoy the Gains. from Free Trade? Can a Lump-Sum Transfer Make Everyone Enjoy te Gains from Free Trade? Yasukazu Icino Department of Economics, Konan University June 30, 2010 Abstract I examine lump-sum transfer rules to redistribute te

More information

Introduction to Futures Contracts

Introduction to Futures Contracts Introduction to Futures Contracts September 2010 PREPARED BY Eric Przybylinski Research Analyst Gregory J. Leonberger, FSA Director of Research Abstract Futures contracts are widely utilized throughout

More information

1 Present and Future Value

1 Present and Future Value Lecture 8: Asset Markets c 2009 Je rey A. Miron Outline:. Present and Future Value 2. Bonds 3. Taxes 4. Applications Present and Future Value In the discussion of the two-period model with borrowing and

More information

Portfolio Choice and Trading Volume with Loss-Averse Investors

Portfolio Choice and Trading Volume with Loss-Averse Investors Portfolio Choice and Trading Volume with Loss-Averse Investors Francisco J. Gomes 1 London Business School March 2003 Abstract This paper presents a model of portfolio choice and stock trading volume with

More information

A Simpli ed Axiomatic Approach to Ambiguity Aversion

A Simpli ed Axiomatic Approach to Ambiguity Aversion A Simpli ed Axiomatic Approach to Ambiguity Aversion William S. Neilson Department of Economics University of Tennessee Knoxville, TN 37996-0550 wneilson@utk.edu March 2009 Abstract This paper takes the

More information

EMPIRICAL ANALYSES OF THE DOGS OF THE DOW STRATEGY: JAPANESE EVIDENCE. Received July 2012; revised February 2013

EMPIRICAL ANALYSES OF THE DOGS OF THE DOW STRATEGY: JAPANESE EVIDENCE. Received July 2012; revised February 2013 International Journal of Innovative Computing, Information and Control ICIC International c 2013 ISSN 1349-4198 Volume 9, Number 9, September 2013 pp. 3677 3684 EMPIRICAL ANALYSES OF THE DOGS OF THE DOW

More information

UCLA. Department of Economics Ph. D. Preliminary Exam Micro-Economic Theory

UCLA. Department of Economics Ph. D. Preliminary Exam Micro-Economic Theory UCLA Department of Economics Ph. D. Preliminary Exam Micro-Economic Theory (SPRING 2011) Instructions: You have 4 hours for the exam Answer any 5 out of the 6 questions. All questions are weighted equally.

More information

Volatility: A Brief Overview

Volatility: A Brief Overview The Benefits of Systematically Selling Volatility July 2014 By Jeremy Berman Justin Frankel Co-Portfolio Managers of the RiverPark Structural Alpha Fund Abstract: A strategy of systematically selling volatility

More information

Margin Requirements and Equilibrium Asset Prices

Margin Requirements and Equilibrium Asset Prices Margin Requirements and Equilibrium Asset Prices Daniele Coen-Pirani Graduate School of Industrial Administration, Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh, PA 15213-3890, USA Abstract This paper studies

More information

DECISIONS IN FINANCIAL ECONOMICS: AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY OF DISCOUNT RATES. Uri Benzion* and Joseph Yagil** ABSTRACT

DECISIONS IN FINANCIAL ECONOMICS: AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY OF DISCOUNT RATES. Uri Benzion* and Joseph Yagil** ABSTRACT DECISIONS IN FINANCIAL ECONOMICS: AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY OF DISCOUNT RATES Uri Benzion* and Joseph Yagil** ABSTRACT Using three subsamples of subjects that differ in their level of formal education and

More information

Capital budgeting & risk

Capital budgeting & risk Capital budgeting & risk A reading prepared by Pamela Peterson Drake O U T L I N E 1. Introduction 2. Measurement of project risk 3. Incorporating risk in the capital budgeting decision 4. Assessment of

More information

Using Currency Futures to Hedge Currency Risk

Using Currency Futures to Hedge Currency Risk Using Currency Futures to Hedge Currency Risk By Sayee Srinivasan & Steven Youngren Product Research & Development Chicago Mercantile Exchange Inc. Introduction Investment professionals face a tough climate.

More information

A Behavioural Explanation Of Six Finance. puzzle. Solution

A Behavioural Explanation Of Six Finance. puzzle. Solution A Behavioural Explanation Of Six Finance Puzzles Solution Developed from Investor Psychology: A Behavioural Explanation Of Six Finance Puzzles, Henriëtte Prast, Research Series - De Nederlandsche Bank,

More information

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS EXPLAINING THE ANOMALIES OF THE EXPONENTIAL DISCOUNTED UTILITY MODEL

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS EXPLAINING THE ANOMALIES OF THE EXPONENTIAL DISCOUNTED UTILITY MODEL DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS EXPLAINING THE ANOMALIES OF THE EXPONENTIAL DISCOUNTED UTILITY MODEL Ali al-nowaihi, University of Leicester, UK Sanjit Dhami, University of Leicester, UK Working Paper No. 07/09

More information

Mathematics. Rosella Castellano. Rome, University of Tor Vergata

Mathematics. Rosella Castellano. Rome, University of Tor Vergata and Loans Mathematics Rome, University of Tor Vergata and Loans Future Value for Simple Interest Present Value for Simple Interest You deposit E. 1,000, called the principal or present value, into a savings

More information

Web Appendix for Reference-Dependent Consumption Plans by Botond Kőszegi and Matthew Rabin

Web Appendix for Reference-Dependent Consumption Plans by Botond Kőszegi and Matthew Rabin Web Appendix for Reference-Dependent Consumption Plans by Botond Kőszegi and Matthew Rabin Appendix A: Modeling Rational Reference-Dependent Behavior Throughout the paper, we have used the PPE solution

More information

Finance 400 A. Penati - G. Pennacchi Market Micro-Structure: Notes on the Kyle Model

Finance 400 A. Penati - G. Pennacchi Market Micro-Structure: Notes on the Kyle Model Finance 400 A. Penati - G. Pennacchi Market Micro-Structure: Notes on the Kyle Model These notes consider the single-period model in Kyle (1985) Continuous Auctions and Insider Trading, Econometrica 15,

More information

Bonds, in the most generic sense, are issued with three essential components.

Bonds, in the most generic sense, are issued with three essential components. Page 1 of 5 Bond Basics Often considered to be one of the most conservative of all investments, bonds actually provide benefits to both conservative and more aggressive investors alike. The variety of

More information

Moral Hazard. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Moral Hazard. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Moral Hazard Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania 1 Principal-Agent Problem Basic problem in corporate finance: separation of ownership and control: o The owners of the firm are typically

More information

The Returns to Currency Speculation in Emerging Markets

The Returns to Currency Speculation in Emerging Markets The Returns to Currency Speculation in Emerging Markets Craig Burnside, Martin Eichenbaum y, and Sergio Rebelo z February 2007 Abstract The carry trade strategy involves selling forward currencies that

More information

We show that prospect theory offers a rich theory of casino gambling, one that captures several features

We show that prospect theory offers a rich theory of casino gambling, one that captures several features MANAGEMENT SCIENCE Vol. 58, No. 1, January 2012, pp. 35 51 ISSN 0025-1909 (print) ISSN 1526-5501 (online) http://dx.doi.org/10.1287/mnsc.1110.1435 2012 INFORMS A Model of Casino Gambling Nicholas Barberis

More information

THE POWER OF FOREX OPTIONS

THE POWER OF FOREX OPTIONS THE POWER OF FOREX OPTIONS TOPICS COVERED Option basics Call options Put Options Why trade options? Covered call Covered put Hedging your position using options How to repair a trading position THE POWER

More information

Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zurich. Working Paper Series ISSN 1424-0459. Working Paper No. 229

Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zurich. Working Paper Series ISSN 1424-0459. Working Paper No. 229 Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zurich Working Paper Series ISSN 1424-0459 Working Paper No. 229 On the Notion of the First Best in Standard Hidden Action Problems Christian

More information

Four Derivations of the Black Scholes PDE by Fabrice Douglas Rouah www.frouah.com www.volopta.com

Four Derivations of the Black Scholes PDE by Fabrice Douglas Rouah www.frouah.com www.volopta.com Four Derivations of the Black Scholes PDE by Fabrice Douglas Rouah www.frouah.com www.volopta.com In this Note we derive the Black Scholes PDE for an option V, given by @t + 1 + rs @S2 @S We derive the

More information

Choice under Uncertainty

Choice under Uncertainty Choice under Uncertainty Part 1: Expected Utility Function, Attitudes towards Risk, Demand for Insurance Slide 1 Choice under Uncertainty We ll analyze the underlying assumptions of expected utility theory

More information

The Role of Alternative Investments in a Diversified Investment Portfolio

The Role of Alternative Investments in a Diversified Investment Portfolio The Role of Alternative Investments in a Diversified Investment Portfolio By Baird Private Wealth Management Introduction Traditional Investments Domestic Equity International Equity Taxable Fixed Income

More information

Optimal demand management policies with probability weighting

Optimal demand management policies with probability weighting Optimal demand management policies with probability weighting Ana B. Ania February 2006 Preliminary draft. Please, do not circulate. Abstract We review the optimality of partial insurance contracts in

More information

Investments 2: Creating a Personal Investment Plan. Assignments

Investments 2: Creating a Personal Investment Plan. Assignments Financial Plan Assignments Assignments Open your copy of Learning Tool 5A: Investment Plan Example. Make sure you understand the terminology related to investment plans. I will discuss many aspects of

More information

LOSS AVERSION AND SELLER BEHAVIOR: EVIDENCE FROM THE HOUSING MARKET*

LOSS AVERSION AND SELLER BEHAVIOR: EVIDENCE FROM THE HOUSING MARKET* LOSS AVERSION AND SELLER BEHAVIOR: EVIDENCE FROM THE HOUSING MARKET* DAVID GENESOVE AND CHRISTOPHER MAYER Data from downtown Boston in the 1990s show that loss aversion determines seller behavior in the

More information

Lecture 15. Ranking Payoff Distributions: Stochastic Dominance. First-Order Stochastic Dominance: higher distribution

Lecture 15. Ranking Payoff Distributions: Stochastic Dominance. First-Order Stochastic Dominance: higher distribution Lecture 15 Ranking Payoff Distributions: Stochastic Dominance First-Order Stochastic Dominance: higher distribution Definition 6.D.1: The distribution F( ) first-order stochastically dominates G( ) if

More information

Retirement Investing: Analyzing the Roth Conversion Option*

Retirement Investing: Analyzing the Roth Conversion Option* Retirement Investing: Analyzing the Roth Conversion Option* Robert M. Dammon Tepper School of Bsiness Carnegie Mellon University 12/3/2009 * The author thanks Chester Spatt for valuable discussions. The

More information

The Design and Efficiency of Loyalty Rewards Ramon Caminal This version: October 2010 October 2009

The Design and Efficiency of Loyalty Rewards Ramon Caminal This version: October 2010 October 2009 The Design and Efficiency of Loyalty Rewards Ramon Caminal This version: October 010 October 009 Barcelona GSE Working Paper Series Working Paper nº 408 The design and e ciency of loyalty rewards Ramon

More information

Behavioral Aspects of Dollar Cost Averaging

Behavioral Aspects of Dollar Cost Averaging Behavioral Aspects of Dollar Cost Averaging By Scott A. MacKillop, President, Frontier Asset Management, LLC The Traditional View Dollar-cost averaging is used by many financial advisors to help their

More information

A Better Approach to Target Date Strategies

A Better Approach to Target Date Strategies February 2011 A Better Approach to Target Date Strategies Executive Summary In 2007, Folio Investing undertook an analysis of Target Date Funds to determine how these investments might be improved. As

More information

A BEHAVIORAL FINANCE MODEL OF THE EXCHANGE RATE WITH MANY FORECASTING RULES

A BEHAVIORAL FINANCE MODEL OF THE EXCHANGE RATE WITH MANY FORECASTING RULES A BEHAVIORAL FINANCE MODEL OF THE EXCHANGE RATE WITH MANY FORECASTING RULES PAUL DE GRAUWE PABLO ROVIRA KALTWASSER CESIFO WORKING PAPER NO. 1849 CATEGORY 6: MONETARY POLICY AND INTERNATIONAL FINANCE NOVEMBER

More information

Lesson 5. Risky assets

Lesson 5. Risky assets Lesson 5. Risky assets Prof. Beatriz de Blas May 2006 5. Risky assets 2 Introduction How stock markets serve to allocate risk. Plan of the lesson: 8 >< >: 1. Risk and risk aversion 2. Portfolio risk 3.

More information

Employee Stock Options, Financing Constraints, and Real Investment

Employee Stock Options, Financing Constraints, and Real Investment Employee Stock Options, Financing Constraints, and Real Investment Ilona Babenko Michael Lemmon Yuri Tserlukevich Hong Kong University of Science and Technology and University of Utah March 2009 Our goals

More information

A Welfare Criterion for Models with Distorted Beliefs

A Welfare Criterion for Models with Distorted Beliefs A Welfare Criterion for Models with Distorted Beliefs Markus Brunnermeier, Alp Simsek, Wei Xiong August 2012 Markus Brunnermeier, Alp Simsek, Wei Xiong () Welfare Criterion for Distorted Beliefs August

More information