Bayesian reconstruction of traffic accidents



Similar documents
Using Bayesian Networks to Identify the Causal Effect of Speeding in Individual Vehicle/Pedestrian Collisions

Chapter 14 Managing Operational Risks with Bayesian Networks

FORENSIC COLLISION INVESTIGATION REPORT

DRIVER ATTRIBUTES AND REAR-END CRASH INVOLVEMENT PROPENSITY

Pedestrian/Car Accident

A report on the accident that occurred on Cromarty Road, South Lanark, on the 24th of May Regina -v- Craig Foster

A Road Crash Reconstruction Technique

Another Look at Sensitivity of Bayesian Networks to Imprecise Probabilities

Model-based Synthesis. Tony O Hagan

How To Write A Crash Reconstruction

Forensic Engineering Determination of the Angle of Lean of a Cycle-Rider System Negotiating a Turn

Accident Investigation

Bayesian Statistics: Indian Buffet Process

IN THE HIGH COURT OF AUSTRALIA -T-UL-L-Y-

SENSITIVITY ANALYSIS AND INFERENCE. Lecture 12

Compression algorithm for Bayesian network modeling of binary systems

CURRICULUM-VITAE. Stephen Alan Irwin 5746 Richmond Avenue Dallas, Texas (214)

The Basics of Graphical Models

Review. Bayesianism and Reliability. Today s Class

Title: A Day in the Life of John Henry, Traffic Cop. Keywords: car accident, conservation of momentum, forces, friction

BASIC STATISTICAL METHODS FOR GENOMIC DATA ANALYSIS

Vehicles travelling in the same direction on the same roadway. Vehicles travelling in the same direction in 2 different lanes of traffic

Curriculum Vitae. Member of the Phoenix Police Department's Traffic Investigations Unit ( / ) Homicide Unit ( )

$ Completed Speed From Skids and Skid Mark Analysis Course by the University of California at Riverside (Riverside County Sheriff s Office),1996.

Lecture 8 The Subjective Theory of Betting on Theories

Last time we had arrived at the following provisional interpretation of Aquinas second way:

Bayesian Analysis for the Social Sciences

Legal view of digital evidence

Investigating the Aggravated Vehicular Homicide Case

PUBLIC HEALTH OPTOMETRY ECONOMICS. Kevin D. Frick, PhD

CRIME SCENE INVESTIGATION THROUGH DNA TRACES USING BAYESIAN NETWORKS

1 Nonzero sum games and Nash equilibria

SYSM 6304: Risk and Decision Analysis Lecture 5: Methods of Risk Analysis

European New Car Assessment Program (EuroNCAP) and Crash Test Ratings of New Vehicles

Introduction to. Hypothesis Testing CHAPTER LEARNING OBJECTIVES. 1 Identify the four steps of hypothesis testing.

Time, Position & Visibility in Disputed Auto Versus Pedestrian Accident Cases

Real Time Traffic Monitoring With Bayesian Belief Networks

Explore 3: Crash Test Dummies

Supplement to Call Centers with Delay Information: Models and Insights

Engineering Malpractice: Avoiding Liability through Education

ECON20310 LECTURE SYNOPSIS REAL BUSINESS CYCLE

Traffic Accident Reconstruction

Mathematical Modeling and Engineering Problem Solving

The Optimality of Naive Bayes

WHAT SHOULD I DO IF I HAVE AN AUTO ACCIDENT? 1. If I have an auto accident, do I have to stop? 2. What should I do if someone is injured?

Optimal Stopping in Software Testing

Prentice Hall Algebra Correlated to: Colorado P-12 Academic Standards for High School Mathematics, Adopted 12/2009

A Coefficient of Variation for Skewed and Heavy-Tailed Insurance Losses. Michael R. Powers[ 1 ] Temple University and Tsinghua University

Is a Single-Bladed Knife Enough to Dissect Human Cognition? Commentary on Griffiths et al.

Nonparametric adaptive age replacement with a one-cycle criterion

Credal Networks for Operational Risk Measurement and Management

CURRICULUM VITAE BUSINESS INFORMATION: Website:

I have been the on-scene investigator of approximately 3500 crashes. I have reconstructed 20 crashes.

A Fuel Cost Comparison of Electric and Gas-Powered Vehicles

Aachen Summer Simulation Seminar 2014

Characteristics of High Injury Severity Crashes on km/h Rural Roads in South Australia

Risk Analysis of Development Programs

Analysis of intersection accidents - An accident causation and prevention perspective

Incorporating Evidence in Bayesian networks with the Select Operator

RULES OF THE ROAD BY LWTL Staff Writer

Computer Forensics using Bayesian Network: A Case Study

Modeling and Analysis of Call Center Arrival Data: A Bayesian Approach

Why Taking This Course? Course Introduction, Descriptive Statistics and Data Visualization. Learning Goals. GENOME 560, Spring 2012

Getting it Right PEDESTRIAN/VEHICLE COLLISIONS COLLISION INVESTIGATION IN THE 21 ST CENTURY

WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT?

Learning outcomes. Knowledge and understanding. Competence and skills

Comparison of frequentist and Bayesian inference. Class 20, 18.05, Spring 2014 Jeremy Orloff and Jonathan Bloom

PEDESTRIAN ACCIDENTS: A DISCUSSION. Presented by: Frank S.M. Devito

better off than the subjective Bayesian or vice versa

PROJECT RISK MANAGEMENT

COMPUTATIONAL METHODS FOR A MATHEMATICAL THEORY OF EVIDENCE

A Non-Linear Schema Theorem for Genetic Algorithms

MILWAUKEE POLICE DEPARTMENT

CONTENTS OF DAY 2. II. Why Random Sampling is Important 9 A myth, an urban legend, and the real reason NOTES FOR SUMMER STATISTICS INSTITUTE COURSE

This chapter is all about cardinality of sets. At first this looks like a

What roundabout design provides the highest possible safety?

LOGNORMAL MODEL FOR STOCK PRICES

Alok Gupta. Dmitry Zhdanov

Statistics in Geophysics: Introduction and Probability Theory

COMMONWEALTH OF PUERTO RICO OFFICE OF THE COMMISSIONER OF INSURANCE RULE 71

Using simulation to calculate the NPV of a project

Physics Kinematics Model

POLICE TRAFFIC CRASH INVESTIGATION Identify and report on causative and/or related events in a traffic crash

Analysis of Load Frequency Control Performance Assessment Criteria

COLLISION DYNAMICS P.O. BOX 1877 GLENDORA, CALIFORNIA CD-XPRT ( )

Bayesian probability theory

Highway Loss Data Institute Bulletin

PREDICTING THROW DISTANCE VARIATIONS IN BICYCLE CRASHES

Speed, velocity and acceleration

ACCELERATION CHARACTERISTICS OF VEHICLES IN RURAL PENNSYLVANIA

Algebra Academic Content Standards Grade Eight and Grade Nine Ohio. Grade Eight. Number, Number Sense and Operations Standard

What Every Driver Must Know Review Assignment

Fairfield Public Schools

Plaintiff s Interrogatories Directed To Defendant(S)

Decision Trees and Networks

Model Fleet Safety Program Short

The Method of Least Squares

THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF ARBITRAGE PRICING

Chapter 21: The Discounted Utility Model

Statistics I for QBIC. Contents and Objectives. Chapters 1 7. Revised: August 2013

Transcription:

Law, Probability and Risk (2003) 2, 69 89 Bayesian reconstruction of traffic accidents GARY A. DAVIS Department of Civil Engineering, University of Minnesota, 122 CivE, 500 Pillsbury Drive SE, Minneapolis, MN 55455, USA [Received on 20 January 2003; revised on 17 April 2003; accepted on 9 May 2003] Traffic accident reconstruction has been defined as the effort to determine, from whatever evidence is available, how an accident happened. Traffic accident reconstruction can be treated as a problem in uncertain reasoning about a particular event, and developments in modeling uncertain reasoning for artificial intelligence can be applied to this problem. Physical principles can usually be used to develop a structural model of the accident and this model, together with an expert assessment of prior uncertainty regarding the accident s initial conditions, can be represented as a Bayesian network. Posterior probabilities for the accident s initial conditions, given evidence collected at the accident scene, can then be computed by updating the Bayesian network. Using a possible worlds semantics, truth conditions for counterfactual claims about the accident can be defined and used to rigorously implement a but for test of whether or not a speed limit violation could be considered a cause of an accident. The logic of this approach is illustrated for a simplified version of a vehicle/pedestrian accident, and then the approach is applied to four actual accidents. Keywords: possible worlds; accident reconstruction; Bayes networks; Markov chain Monte Carlo; forensic inference. Limited creatures that we are, we often find ourselves having to base decisions on less than complete information. This is particularly true of many forensic problems, and at the First International Conference on Forensic Statistics Lindley (1991) argued that the probability calculus should be applied not only to statistical problems, but to forensic inference more generally. Lindley focused on a class of problems for which the hypotheses of interest were the guilt or innocence of a defendant, and the task was to weigh the plausibility of these alternatives in the light of evidence. His proposed solution was Bayesian, where one first determines a prior assignment of probability to the alternative hypotheses, along with the probability of the evidence given each alternative, and then uses Bayes theorem to compute posterior probabilities for the hypotheses. This approach has since been applied to increasingly more complicated problems in forensic identification (e.g. Balding, 2000; Dawid & Mortera, 1998), in part due to an intense interest in interpreting DNA evidence. E-mail: drtrips@umn.edu c Oxford University Press 2003, all rights reserved

70 G. A. DAVIS 1. Forensic inference and traffic accidents Lindley also referred briefly to a different class of problems, exemplified by the case of a motorist charged with dangerous driving.... Here the possible criminal is known; what is in doubt is whether there was a crime (1991, p. 86). Such problems are most prominent when a traffic accident has resulted in death or serious injury, and it must be determined if a driver should be subjected to criminal or civil penalties. The specific conditions which define this liability vary somewhat across jurisdictions, but it is generally possible to identify two basic issues, pertaining to the quality of driving, and to the causal relation between the driving and the accident s outcome. For example, in Great Britain causing death by dangerous driving occurs when a person causes the death of another person by driving a mechanically propelled vehicle dangerously while dangerous driving is in turn defined as driving that falls far below what would be expected of a competent and careful driver (Road Traffic Act, 1991). In the United States, the Uniform Vehicle Code states that homicide by vehicle occurs when a driver is engaged in the violation of any state law or municipal ordinance applying to the operation or use of a vehicle and when such violation is the proximate cause of said death (NCUTLO, 1992). (Italics have been added for emphasis.) For some accidents, eyewitness testimony may be reliable enough, and the driving egregious enough, that questions concerning the quality of driving and its relation to the accident are readily resolved. In other cases, however, the evidence can be entirely circumstantial, collected by accident investigators after the event. The connections between the evidence and the basic legal issues can then be less clear, and over the past 70 years the practice of accident investigation and reconstruction has developed primarily to assist the legal system in resolving such questions (Traffic Institute, 1946; Rudram & Lambourn, 1981). Baker & Fricke (1990, p. 50-3) define accident reconstruction as the effort to determine, from whatever information is available, how the accident occurred. Typical questions which a reconstructionist can be called on to address include ascertaining the initial speeds and locations of the involved parties, identifying the actions taken by these parties, and determining the degree to which avoidance actions might have been effective. Rarely however will direct observations alone be sufficient to answer these questions, and the reconstructionist may need to supplement the information collected at the accident s scene. These issues can be illustrated by considering an instructional example used by Greatrix (2002). On a summer afternoon in Carlisle, England, a seven year-old boy attempted to cross a road ahead of an oncoming vehicle, and although the driver braked to a stop, the child was struck. Measurements made at the scene yielded a skidmark 22 meters long, with the point of collision being 12 meters from the start of the skid. It was also noted that the speed limit on the road was 30 mph (13.4 meters/sec). A standard practice in accident reconstruction is to use, as additional premises, variants of the kinematic formula s = vt + (at 2 )/2 (1) which gives the distance s travelled during time interval t by an object with initial velocity v while undergoing a constant acceleration of a.inthis case, test skids conducted after the accident suggested that a braking deceleration a = 7 24 meters/sec 2 was plausible, and this value together with the measured skidmark of 22 meters gives the speed of the vehicle

BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS 71 at the start of the skid as 17 8 meters/sec. Citing statistical evidence on the distribution of driver reaction times (denoted here by t p ), Greatrix used a representative value of 1 33 seconds to deduce that the vehicle was 35 7 meters from the collision point when the driver noticed the pedestrian. If the vehicle has been travelling instead at the posted speed of 30 mph (13 4 meters/sec), the driver would have needed only 30 2 meters to stop and so, other things being equal, would not have hit the child. Thus the evidence could be taken as supporting claims that the driver was speeding, and that had the driver not been speeding, the accident would not have happened. At this point though a different expert could argue that no one knows for certain either the actual braking deceleration or the driver s actual reaction time. The alternative values of a = 5 5 meters/sec 2 and t p = 1 0 s imply that the magnitude of the speed limit violation was only about 5 mph, and that the vehicle would not have stopped before reaching the collision point, even if the initial speed had been 30 mph. It could then be claimed that both the degree to which the driver s speed violated the speed limit, and the causal connection between that violation and the result, are open to doubt. One way to view this example is as an attempt to answer three types of questions. The first type, which can be called factual questions, concerns the actual conditions associated with this particular accident. These include the paths of the pedestrian and vehicle, the initial speed of the vehicle, and the relation between this speed and the posted speed limit. Answering this type of question is what Baker and Fricke consider the role of accident reconstruction proper. The second type, which can be called counterfactual questions, starts with a stipulation of the facts, but then goes beyond these and attempts to determine what would have happened had certain specific conditions been different. In the example, determining whether or not the vehicle would have stopped before reaching the pedestrian, had the initial speed been equal to the posted limit, is a question of this type. Counterfactual questions usually arise in accident reconstruction when attempting to identify what Baker called causal factors, which are circumstances contributing to a result without which the result could not have occurred (Baker, 1975, p. 274). Posing and answering counterfactual questions has been referred to as avoidance analysis (Limpert, 1989), or sequence of events analysis (Hicks, 1989) in the accident reconstruction literature. Finally, the third type of question arises because of uncertainty regarding the conditions of the accident, which leads to uncertainty concerning the answers to the first two types of question. How best to account for uncertainty in an accident reconstruction is currently an unresolved issue. A common recommendation has been to perform sensitivity analyses, in which the values of selected input variables are changed and estimates recomputed (Schockenhoff et al., 1985; Hicks, 1989; Niederer, 1991). When the conclusions of the reconstruction (e.g. that the driver was speeding) are insensitive to this variation they can be regarded as well-supported, but if different yet plausible combinations of input values produce differing results, this approach is inconclusive. This limitation has been recognized, and has motivated several authors to apply probabilistic methods. Brach (1994) has illustrated how the method of statistical differentials can be used to compute the variance of an estimate, given a differentiable expression for the desired estimate and a specification of the means and variances of distributions characterizing the uncertainty in the expression s arguments. Kost & Werner (1994) and Wood & O Riordain (1994) have suggested that Monte Carlo simulation can be used for more complicated models where tractable solutions are not at hand. The Monte Carlo methods also produce

72 G. A. DAVIS approximate probability distributions characterizing the uncertainty of estimates, rather than just means and variances. Particularly interesting are the examples used by Wood and O Riordain, where simulated outcomes inconsistent with measurements were rejected, in effect producing posterior conditional distributions for the quantities of interest. These posterior distributions were then used to compute the probability of a counterfactual claim, that the accident would not have occurred had a vehicle s initial speed been different. More recently, Rose et al. (2001) have employed a Monte Carlo approach similar to that of Wood and O Riordain. A weakness of this approach, rooted in the appearance of the Borel paradox when making inferences using deterministic simulation models, has been identified by Hoogstrate & Spek (2002), who used Bayesian melding (Poole & Raftery, 2000) to get around this problem. Roughly concomitant with the developing interest in probabilistic accident reconstruction has been an interest in using Bayesian networks to support more traditional forensic inference (Edwards, 1991; Aitken et al., 1996; Dawid & Evett, 1997; Curran et al., 1998). Bayesian networks can be used to represent an expert s knowledge concerning some class of systems, together with his or her uncertainty concerning the state of a particular system in that class. The system s state is characterized by the values taken on by a set of variables, and the dependences among the system variables are described by specifying a set of deterministic and/or stochastic relationships (Jensen, 1996). Davis (1999, 2001) has illustrated how Bayesian network methods and Markov chain Monte Carlo (MCMC) computational techniques can be combined to accomplish a Bayesian reconstruction of vehicle/pedestrian accidents. Despite this growing interest in using probabilistic reasoning in accident reconstruction, there appears to be some confusion about the relation between these applications and traditional statistical reasoning. Brach faulted sensitivity analyses because the statistical nature of the variations is not explicitly taken into account, (1994, p. 148), while Wood and O Riordain referred to an expression giving the coefficient of variation for an individual speed estimate as... a statistical approach, (1994, p. 130). Rose et al. recommended Monte Carlo simulation because it produces statistically relevant conclusions regarding the probable V experienced by a vehicle (2001, p. 2). These quotations suggest a tendency to view probabilistic accident reconstruction as an exercise in statistical inference. Lindley (1991), and more recently Schum (2000), have argued though that statistical inference problems are only a subset of the forensic problems to which probabilistic methods can be applied. Although reasonable people can disagree on how to define the discipline of statistics, statistical problems typically involve making inferences about how some characteristic is distributed over a population of entities, using measurements made on a sample from that population. Probabilities are used to express uncertainty about parameters characterizing the population distribution, and this uncertainty can in principle be reduced by increasing the sample s size. In contrast, the usual objective of an accident reconstruction is to make inferences about an individual event, and probabilities are assigned to statements about that event. When an individual accident can be regarded as exchangeable with the members of a reference population, pre-established characteristics of that population could be used to make these probability assignments, but once the characteristics of the reference distribution are known, information about additional accidents in the reference population reveals nothing more about the accident at hand. The confusion concerning the appropriate role of probability in accident reconstruction can at least in part be attributed to two fundamentally different meanings attached to

BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS 73 probability statements, on the one hand referring to expected relative frequencies in repeated trials of chance setups, Hacking (1965) and on the other referring to a degree of credibility assigned to propositions. This duality was apparently present in the initial development of probability theory in the seventeenth century (Hacking, 1975), recurs in philosophical treatments of probability (e.g. Carnap, 1945; Lewis, 1980), and has reappeared in the study of logics for artificial reasoning (Halpern, 1990). The view we shall adopt here is that an accident reconstruction produces expert opinion about a particular, past event. To quote Baker and Fricke: Opinions or conclusions are the products of accident reconstruction. To the extent that reports of direct observations are available and can be depended on as facts, reconstruction is unnecessary (1990, p. 50-4). Statements of opinion can be more or less certain however, depending on the certainty attached to their premises. If this uncertainty is graded using probabilities, then the probability calculus can be used as a logic to derive the uncertainty attached to conclusions. This approach is what Howson (1993) calls personalistic Bayesianism but before continuing it should be noted that it is by no means the only alternative available. Debate continues as to when or even if the probability calculus is the appropriate logic for uncertain reasoning, and the issue shows no signs of being resolved anytime in the near future. The development of logics to capture aspects of reasoning under uncertainty is an active area of research, and an overview of some of this work can be found in Dubois & Prade (1993). Summaries of the arguments for and against the Bayesian approach can be found in Howson (1993) and Earman (1992). 2. Accidents, probability, and possible worlds This use of probability can be brought into sharper focus by considering a simpler model of a vehicle/pedestrian collision, having just three Boolean variables. Variable v denotes the vehicle s initial speed, and takes on the value 0 if the vehicle was not speeding and the value 1 if it was. Variable x denotes the vehicle s initial distance, and takes on the value 0 if this distance was short and 1 if it was long (the problem of determining exactly what is meant by short and long will, for the time being, be ignored). Variable y denotes whether or not a collision takes place, with 0 being no collision and 1 being collision. y is assumed to be related to v and x via the structural equation y = (1 x) + x v (2) where + and denote Boolean addition and multiplication, respectively. In words, a collision occurs if either the initial distance is short (1 x = 1),orifthe initial distance is long but the vehicle is speeding (x v = 1). Since all variables are Boolean, the relationship between y, x and v can be tabulated as in Table 1. In Table 1 each assignment of values to v and x determines a possible way the vehicle/pedestrian encounter could have occurred. The rows of such tables have been variously referred to as states of affairs, scenarios or system states, but a longrunning practice in philosophical logic (e.g. Lewis, 1976), which is becoming increasingly common in research on artificial intelligence (e.g. Bacchus, 1990; Halpern, 1990), is to follow Leibniz, and call them possible worlds. Uncertainty can then arise in an accident reconstruction when the available evidence is not sufficient to determine which possible

74 G. A. DAVIS TABLE 1 Possible worlds and a probability distribution for the simple Boolean collision model World v x y y v=0 P 1 0 0 1 1 1/4 2 1 0 1 1 1/4 3 0 1 0 0 1/4 4 1 1 1 0 1/4 world was the actual one. For example, suppose one is interested in whether or not the vehicle was speeding, but the only evidence is that the accident occurred (y = 1). Table 1 shows that the condition y = 1 eliminates world 3 as a possibility, but of the remaining three worlds at least one has v = 0 and one has v = 1, so the best that can be said is that it is possible, but not necessary, that the vehicle was speeding. On the other hand, suppose that a reliable witness reported that the initial distance was long (x = 1) when the pedestrian entered the road. Only world 4 has x = 1 and y = 1, and in this world v = 1, so here the evidence implies that the vehicle was speeding. In any given possible world a statement is either true or false, so uncertainty about a statement arises when a set of possible worlds contains some members where that statement is true, and other members where it is false. Uncertainty can be modelled by placing a probability distribution on the set of possible worlds, so that the probability attached to a statement is simply the probability assigned to the set of possible worlds where that statement is true. For example, suppose that each of the possible worlds in Table 1 is regarded as a priori equally probable, so that each has a prior probability of 1/4. One then observes that a collision has occurred. The conditional probability of speeding given that the collision occurred is then P[v =1 y =1]=P[v =1 and y =1]/P[y = 1]=(1/4 + 1/4)/(1/4 + 1/4 + 1/4) = 2/3. (3) This possible worlds approach can also be used to specify truth conditions for counterfactual statements, such as if the vehicle had not been speeding, the collision would not have occurred, by considering what is the case in the closest possible world where the antecedent is true. That is, a counterfactual conditional is said to be true in this (the actual) world, if its consequent is true in the closest possible world where the antecedent is true. For instance, suppose the actual world is world 4 (v = 1, x = 1) and world 3 (v = 0, x = 1) is taken to be the world closest to world 4, but having v = 0. Letting y v=0 = 0stand for the counterfactual claim that had v been 0, y would have been 0, Table 1 shows that since y = 0istrue in the possible world 3, y v=0 = 0 should be taken as true in the actual world 4. On the other hand, y v=0 = 0 should not be taken as true in world 2 (v = 1, x = 0) if world 1 (v = 0, x = 0) is taken as the closest with v = 0. As with indicative statements, probabilities of counterfactual statements can be determined by computing the probability assigned to the set of possible worlds where that statement is true. For example, again treating the possible worlds as a priori equally probable, the

BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS 75 probability that speeding was a necessary cause of the collision can be evaluated as P[y v=0 = 0 y = 1] =P[y v=0 = 0 and y = 1]/P[y = 1] =1/3. (4) This simple example illustrates both a deterministic and a probabilistic approach to accident reconstruction, and these two approaches have a similar structure. The deterministic reconstruction started with a statement describing an observation (y = 1) and then added a structural premise stating the assumed causal relation between this outcome and the variables describing the initial conditions. Boolean algebra, supplemented with a possible worlds semantics for counterfactual conditionals, was then used to derive statements about the initial conditions, and about the causal connection between the initial conditions and the outcome. Ideally, the premises of a reconstruction argument should be strong enough to logically imply definite conclusions about the accident, but as often as not the appearance of deductive certitude is achieved by adding premises whose certainty is questionable. The probabilistic reconstruction also began with the observation and the structural premises, but then supplemented these with a probabilistic premise, in this case a prior probability distribution over the possible worlds. It was then possible to use the probability calculus to derive probabilistic conclusions about the accident s provenance. These ideas are not new. The distinction between probabilities as relative frequencies for actual world populations, and probabilities as measures on models of interpreted formal languages (what we are calling possible worlds) can be found in Carnap (1971) while Lewis (1973) and Stalnaker (1968) have developed the idea that the truth conditions for a counterfactual conditional are given by what is true in closest possible worlds. Lewis (1976) illustrates how these notions can be combined to define probabilities of counterfactual conditionals, and Balke & Pearl (1994) have shown how this approach can be applied to a wide class of inference problems using Bayesian network methods. Chapters 7 9 of Pearl (2000) describe a more detailed development of Balke and Pearl s approach, based on what Pearl calls causal models. To specify a causal model, one first identifies a set of background variables and a set of endogenous variables, and then for each endogenous variable specifies a structural equation describing how that variable changes in response to changes in the background or other endogenous variables. A possible world is then determined by an assignment of values to the model s background variables. In Greatrix s example, the vehicle s initial distance (x), its speed (v), the braking deceleration (a) and the driver s reaction time (t p ) can be taken as background variables, while the length of the skidmark (s) and a collision indicator (y) are endogenous. The structural equation for the skidmark would then be s(v, a) = v 2 /(2a), (5) while the structural equation of the collision indicator would be { 1, if x <vt p v 2 /2a y(x, t p,v,a) = 0, otherwise. (6) Structural models are especially useful in assessing the plausibility of causal claims because they allow one to give an unambiguous definition of truth conditions for a class of causal statements, along the lines of the closest possible world approach outlined above.

76 G. A. DAVIS For example, suppose that in the actual world v = 18 meters/sec, a = 7 meters/sec 2, x = 40 meters, and t p = 1 5 seconds. Then in the actual world x = 40 meters while vt p v 2 /2a = 50 1 meters, so by (6) y = 1 and the collision occurs. Previously, the causal effect of speeding was informally defined as whether or not, other things equal, the collision would not have occurred if the vehicle had not been speeding. This other things equal condition can be made explicit by defining the closest possible world as the one where all background variables have the same value except for v, which is set to v = 13 4 meters/sec. In this world x = 40 meters, while vt p v 2 /2a = 32 9 meters, implying y = 0. So in the actual world, y v=13 4 = 0istrue, and speeding could be considered a causal factor for the collision. In the Greatrix example, a deterministic assessment of whether or not obeying the speed limit would have prevented a pedestrian accident consisted of three steps: (a) estimating the vehicle s initial speed and location, using the measured skid marks and nominal values for a and t p, (b) setting the vehicle s initial speed to the counterfactual value, (c) using the same values of a and t p along with the counterfactual speed to predict if the vehicle would then have stopped before hitting the pedestrian. Each assignment of values to the background variables corresponds to a possible world, and placing a prior probability distribution over the possible worlds produces what Pearl calls a probabilistic causal model. As before, the probability assigned to a statement about the accident is determined by the probability assigned to the set of possible worlds in which that statement is true. This applies both to factual statements, such as the vehicle was speeding, and to counterfactual statements, such as if the vehicle had not been speeding, the collision would not have occurred. Steps (a) (c) correspond, in probabilistic causal models, to what Pearl calls abduction, action and prediction. For the problem of assessing the probability that y v=v = 0, given a measured skidmark s, these would involve (A) Abduction: compute P[x, t p,v,a s]; (B) Action: set v = v ; (C) Prediction: compute P[y v=v = 0 s]. In our simple Boolean example, where the number of possible worlds was finite and small, the abduction step could be carried out by a simple application of the definition of conditional probability, while the prediction step simply required summing the posterior probabilities over possible worlds. For more complicated models, however, this direct approach is not computationally feasible, but Balke & Pearl (1994) have shown that for models which can be represented as Bayesian networks, steps (A) (C) can be carried out by applying Bayesian updating to an appropriately constructed twin network, where the original Bayesian network has been augmented with additional nodes representing the closest possible world. In accident reconstruction the structural equations will often be nonlinear and involve several arguments, while many of the underlying variables will be represented as continuous quantities. This means that the exact updating methods developed for discrete or normal/linear Bayesian networks (Jensen, 1996) can be applied only after constructing a discrete approximation of the reconstruction model. Alternatively, Monte Carlo computational methods could be used to compute approximate

BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS 77 x s 2 d vt p x s s 1 FIG.1. Major variables appearing in the vehicle/pedestrian collision model. but asymptotically exact updates for the original reconstruction model, and this latter approach is used in what follows. 3. Bayesian reconstruction of actual accidents These ideas will be applied to four actual accidents, three involving a vehicle and a pedestrian, and one involving two vehicles at an intersection. The first of the vehicle/pedestrian accidents is Greatrix s example described above, while the other two are taken from a group of fatal accidents investigated by the University of Adelaide s Road Accident Research Unit (RARU) (McLean et al., 1994). The scenario for the pedestrian accidents runs as follows. The driver of a vehicle travelling at a speed of v notices an impending collision with a pedestrian, travelling at a speed v 2, when the front of the vehicle is a distance x from the potential point of impact. After a perception/reaction time of t p the driver locks the brakes, and the vehicle decelerates at a constant rate fg, where g denotes gravitational acceleration and f is the braking drag factor which, following a standard practice in accident reconstruction, expresses the deceleration as a multiple of g. After a transient time t s the tyres begin making skid marks, and the vehicle comes to a stop, leaving a skidmark of length s 1.Before stopping, the vehicle strikes the pedestrian at a speed of v i, and the pedestrian is thrown into the air and comes to rest a distance d from the point of impact. In addition, if the pedestrian was struck after the vehicle began skidding, it may be possible to measure a distance s 2 running from the point of impact to the end of the skidmark. Figure 1 illustrates the collision scenario (with x s denoting the distance travelled during the braking transient.) The abduction step of Pearl s three-step method involves computing the posterior distributions of the model s unobserved variables, given some subset of the measurements d, s 1, s 2. Figure 2 represents the collision model as a directed acyclic graph summarizing the conditional dependence structure, and including nodes to represent the counterfactual speed v and the counterfactual collision indicator y.tocomplete the model it is necessary to specify deterministic or stochastic relations for the arrows appearing in Figure 2, and prior distributions for the background variables x, v, t p, t s,v 2, and f. The structural equations for this model have been described elsewhere (Davis, 2001; Davis et al., 2002), and so the details will not be repeated. Roughly, the relationship between the expected skidmark lengths and the background variables is governed by

78 G. A. DAVIS v* y* v 2 s1 s 1 x t p t s t p t s v f f d v v i i s2 s 2 FIG.2. Directed acyclic graph representation of vehicle/pedestrian collision model. the kinematic equation (1), while the measured skidmark is the result of combining random measurement error with the expected length. The coefficient of variation for this measurement error was taken to be 10% (Garrott & Guenther, 1982). An empirical relationship between impact speed and throw distance was determined by fitting a model to the results of 55 crash tests between cars and pedestrian dummies, and is described in Davis et al. (2002). Finally, the counterfactual collision variable y was taken to be zero (i.e. the collision was avoided) if either the vehicle stopped before reaching the collision point, of if the pedestrian managed to travel an additional 3 0 meters before the vehicle arrived at the collision point. Selection of the prior probability distributions for the background variables was less straightforward. As indicated earlier, these distributions should be interpreted as expert opinions concerning plausible ranges of values, although statistical information might, in some cases, be used to inform these opinions. The strategy used for these examples was to identify priors that appeared on their face to be consistent with current reconstruction practice. In deterministic sensitivity analyses it is often possible to identify defensible prior ranges for background variables (Niederer, 1991), and Wood & O Riordain (1994, p. 137) argue that, in the absence of more specific information, uniform distributions restricted to these ranges offer a plausible extension of the deterministic sensitivity methods. Following these suggestions, the reconstructions described in this paper used uniform prior distributions. Specifically, the range for f was [0 55, 0 9], and was taken from Fricke (1990, p. 62), where 0 55 corresponds to the lower bound for a dry, travelled asphalt pavement and 0 9 is what Fricke considers a reasonable upper bound for most cases. The

BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS 79 TABLE 2 Features of three reconstructed pedestrian accidents: distances are in meters, speeds in meters/second Pedestrian characteristics Scene data Running speed Case s 1 s 2 d Sex Age Lower Upper Greatrix 22 10 - M 7 1 8 5 1 RARU 89-H002 23 5 8 1 14 8 M 5 2 5 4 5 RARU 91-H025 14 9 4 5 - F 9 3 3 5 6 range for the perception/reaction time, t p,was[0 5 seconds, 2 5 seconds], which brackets the values obtained by Fambro et al. (1998) in surprise braking tests, and the midpoint of which (1.5 seconds) equals a popular default value (Stewart-Morris, 1995). For the braking transient time, Neptune et al. (1995) reported values ranging between 0 1 and 0 35 seconds for a well-tuned braking system, while Reed & Keskin (1989) reported values in the range of 0 4 0 5 seconds, so the chosen range was [0 1 seconds, 0 5 seconds]. The bounds for the pedestrian speeds (v 2 )were different for the three cases, varying according to the age and sex of the pedestrian, and were selected to include the 15th and 85th percentile figures for children s running speeds tabulated in Eubanks & Hill (1998, pp. 82 86). The ranges for the initial distance and initial speed were chosen to be wide enough that no reasonable possibility would be excluded a priori. The range for v was [5meters/sec, 50 meters/sec], but initial attempts to apply MCMC methods revealed convergence problems when the initial distance was selected as a background variable. To remedy this the model was re-parameterized with the distance from the collision point to the start of braking as a background variable, and the prior for this initial braking distance was taken to be uniform with range [0 meters, 200 meters]. Note that the initial distance is then simply the sum of this initial braking distance and the distance travelled during the perception/reaction time. Table 2 displays information for each of the three vehicle/pedestrian accidents, including the age and sex of the pedestrian, the lower and upper bounds for the pedestrian s running speed used in the reconstruction, and the skidmark and throw distance measurements. The computer program WinBUGS (Spiegelhalter et al., 2000) was used to generate Monte Carlo samples of the quantities of interest. (Copies of the WinBUGS code for these examples are available from the author on request.) In each case a 5000 iteration burn-in was followed by 150 000 iterations, with the outcome of every 10th iteration being saved for the MCMC sample. Inspection of traces and autocorrelations indicated no obvious problems with nonstationarity or failure to converge. As noted earlier, determining liability involves addressing (at least) two basic issues, one concerning the actual driving, and one concerning the causal connection between that driving and the occurrence of the accident. With regard to the first issue, often an important concern is the speeds of the vehicles involved, and the relation of those speeds to any speed limits. With regard to the second issue, an important question is often whether or not an initial speed equal to the legal limit would, other things equal, have been sufficient to prevent the accident. Figures 3 5 display, for each of the three pedestrian accidents, a plot of the posterior probability density for the speed of the involved vehicle and a plot of the

80 G. A. DAVIS 1.1 1 0.8 Probabilities p1 i pdr i 0.6 0.4 0.2 0 0 15 20 25 30 35 40 45 50 55 60 18.645 speed mph i Speed (mph) P[v y=1&e] PA(v) 59.043 FIG. 3. Posterior density for vehicle s initial speed, and probability of avoidance as a function of initial speed: Greatrix s example. probability the accident would have been avoided, as a function of the counterfactual initial speed. Figure 3, which shows results for Greatrix s example, indicates that the posterior distribution of the vehicle s initial speed is centred at about 45 mph (72 km/h), and that a probable range for the initial speed is between 35 mph (56 km/h) and 55 mph (88 km/h). The posterior probability that the vehicle was travelling at or below the posted speed limit of 30 mph (48 km/h) is essentially zero. Figure 3 also indicates that had the initial speed been at or below the posted speed limit it is very probable that either the driver would have been able to stop before hitting the pedestrian, or the pedestrian would have been able to clear the vehicle s path before collision. So even after allowing for reasonable uncertainty in the vehicle s braking deceleration, in the driver s reaction time and for a fairly substantial measurement error in measuring the skidmarks, it appears highly probable that the driver was speeding, and that speeding was a causal factor in this accident. Figure 4 shows results for the RARU s case 89-H002, in which a 5 year-old boy ran into a road from behind a parked car, stopped briefly in the middle of the road, and was struck when he attempted to run across the far lane. The speed limit on this road was 60 km/h. In this case the posterior probability of the vehicle s initial speed is centred at about 73 km/h, with a probable range being between 60 km/h and 90 km/h. The posterior probability that the initial speed was greater than 60 km/h was about 0 985, and the probability the collision would have been avoided had the initial speed been equal to 60 km/h was equal to about 0 84. Although less obvious than in the Greatrix example, again it appears that the vehicle

BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS 81 1.1 1 0.8 Probabilities p1 i pdr i 0.6 0.4 0.2 0 0 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100 30 speed km/h i Speed (km/h) P[v y=1&e] PA(v) FIG. 4. Posterior density for vehicle s initial speed, and probability of avoidance as a function of initial speed: RARU case 89-H002. 95 1.1 1 0.8 Probabilities p1 i pdr i 0.6 0.4 0.2 0 0 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100 30 speed km/h i Speed (km/h) P[v y=1&e] PA(v) FIG. 5. Posterior density for vehicle s initial speed, and probability of avoidance as a function of initial speed: RARU case 91-H025. 95

82 G. A. DAVIS was probably speeding, and that speeding was probably a causal factor in this accident. Figure 5 shows similar results for the RARU s case 91-H025. For this case the posterior probability that the driver was exceeding the 60 km/h speed limit is only about 0 5, and the probability the accident would have been prevented had the initial speed been 60 km/h is only about 0 27. Unlike the first two cases, here it appears difficult to maintain that the driver should be held liable. The fourth illustrative accident involved a collision between two vehicles at a twoway stop-controlled intersection in the United States, and is described in Fricke (1990, p. 68). In this accident vehicle #1 attempted to turn left onto a state highway from a stopcontrolled approach, and was struck broadside by vehicle #2, which was westbound on the highway. Vehicle #2 left a skidmark of about 73 feet (22 3 meters) prior to impact, and after impact the two vehicles slid together in a northwesterly direction, across the concrete surface of the intersection and onto a grassy shoulder, before coming to a stop. Test skids indicated that drag factors of 0 75 and 0 45 were plausible for the concrete and grass surfaces, respectively. Because the two vehicles followed a common direction after the impact, a forward reconstruction, in which the conservation-of-momentum equations are used to predict the after-impact speeds and directions was not feasible, so a backward approach, where one estimates speeds working back from the point of rest, was used instead. WinBUGS was used to compute Monte Carlo estimates of the posterior distributions for the background variables, including the initial speed of vehicle #2, as well as estimates of the probability the collision would have been avoided as a function of different counterfactual initial speeds. The WinBUGS code used to generate these estimates has been listed in the Appendix. The collision was treated as having been avoided if either vehicle #2 managed to stop before reaching the point of collision or if vehicle #1 managed to travel an additional 20 feet (6 1 meters) before vehicle #2 arrived at the collision point. Because the objective for this example was to see if Bayesian reconstruction could produce results similar to Fricke s deterministic approach, relatively narrow uncertainty ranges were used. Skidmark measurement error was assumed to be normal with a standard deviation of five feet (1 5 meters), the uncertainty for measured angles was taken to be ±2 5 around Fricke s values, and the uncertainties in the drag factors were taken to be ±0 05. Figure 6 shows the posterior probability density for vehicle #2 s initial speed and the probability of avoidance as a function of initial speed. Inspection of this figure reveals that the initial speed of vehicle #2 was most probably around 92 mph (148 km/h), and the bounds of a 95% credible interval for this speed were 86 mph (141 km/h) and 99 mph (162 km/h). Also, for initial speeds below about 60 mph (97 km/h) it is almost certain, other things equal, that this accident would have been avoided. Taking the posted speed limit on the state highway as 55 mph (88 5 km/h), it can be concluded that vehicle #2 was quite probably speeding, and that speeding was quite probably a causal factor for this accident. 4. Conclusion Arguments can be usefully classified as deductive or inductive, deductive arguments being those where the truth of the premises guarantees the truth of the conclusion, while inductive arguments are those where the premises only make the conclusion more or less

BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS 83 1.1 1 0.8 Probabilities p1 i pdr i 0.6 0.4 0.2 0 0 40 60 80 100 120 140 50 speed mph i Speed (mph) P[v y=1&e] PA(v) FIG. 6. Posterior density for vehicle s initial speed, and probability of avoidance as a function of initial speed: vehicle 2 in Fricke 1990 two-vehicle example. 140 probable. Although deductive certainty is the standard expected in mathematics, in forensic inference nontrivial examples of deductive certainty are rare (Evett, 1996). Investigation and reconstruction of traffic accidents is often done to support criminal and civil legal proceedings, the objective being to use the evidence from an accident to identify or exclude possible causal factors, as rationally and objectively as is possible. It is often possible to identify an underlying causal structure for a reconstruction problem, but deductive certainty is not possible because the initial conditions of the accident cannot be measured, and are usually underdetermined by the available evidence. To a greater or lesser extent then, the reconstructionist must supplement the evidence with prior knowledge concerning the values taken on by unmeasured variables, and uncertainty in this prior knowledge induces uncertainty in the estimates and conclusions. At present there is no comprehensive or commonly accepted method for rationally accounting for this uncertainty but if, as Lindley (1991) argues, the probability calculus is an appropriate logic for reasoning about uncertainty, then an accident reconstruction problem can often be formulated as an example of processing information in a Bayesian network. The causal nature of the relations in a reconstruction model also means that results developed by Pearl and his associates can be used to rigorously pose and answer selected counterfactual questions about an accident. Because reconstruction models often contain continuous variables and deterministic relationships, the exact updating methods developed for finite Bayesian networks are not at present well-suited to accident reconstruction, but approximations using Monte Carlo methods are more promising. The focus of this paper has been on determining whether or not speeding should be

84 G. A. DAVIS considered a causal factor in road accidents. Causal factors are analogous to what Pearl (2000) calls necessary causes, since their absence is sufficient to prevent the accident. Road accidents usually result though from a particular combination of several causal factors, none of which was sufficient in and of itself to produce the accident. An intriguing extension of this Bayesian approach would be toward identifying what Baker calls the cause of an accident, that is, the complete set of causal factors which, if reproduced, would result in an identical accident (1975, p. 284). This however is a topic for future research. It is worth restating that probabilistic accident reconstruction should be viewed as uncertain reasoning about a particular, individual event, not as statistical reasoning about the aggregate properties of a population. The importance of this distinction is brought out clearly in recent attempts to construct artificial systems exemplifying these types of reasoning, where a semantics for statistical propositions can be defined for a population of entities existing in a single world, while a semantics for uncertain propositions about individual entities appears to require quantification, and hence probabilities, defined on a set of possible worlds (Halpern, 1990). Prior statements of probability concerning the conditions of an accident should then be interpreted as expressing an expert s degrees of belief concerning possible ways the accident might have transpired, while posterior statements of probability express how those degrees of belief should be modified in the light of evidence (or supposition). This view is consistent with recent thinking in other areas of forensic inference (Taroni et al., 2001). Finally, probabilistic accident reconstruction can also be viewed as an example of eliminative induction, where one begins with a set of possible hypotheses, and the effect of evidence is to raise the probabilities of some of these, while reducing the probability of others (Earman, 1992, chapter 7). Ideally, the available evidence should be sufficient to deductively entail one hypothesis to the exclusion of the others, as in an Agatha Christie story or the game of Clue. In practice this is rarely the case, and decisions must usually be made when the best that can be said is that the actual case is contained in some more or less probable set of possible cases. This suggests that the two problem types mentioned in Lindley (1991) are not as dissimilar as might have been thought. In both Bayesian accident reconstruction and in the Bayesian approach to forensic identification (e.g. Balding, 2000) one begins with a set of possibilities and a prior probability distribution over this set. In the former case the possibilities are assignments of values to background variables, while in the latter case they are possible suspects. In both cases one then uses Bayes theorem to compute posterior probabilities assigned to subsets of these possibilities, with the hope that a clear decision will emerge. Lindley (1991) also argues that when the appropriate legal decision is not clear, it should be determined as that which maximizes expected utility. How this idea might be applied to traffic accident cases is an interesting subject, but one that is beyond the scope of this paper. Acknowledgement This research was supported by the Intelligent Transportation Systems Institute at the University of Minnesota.

BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS 85 REFERENCES AITKEN, C., CONNOLLY, T.,GAMMERMAN, A., ZHANG, G., BAILEY, D., GORDON, R.& OLDFIELD, R. 1996 Statistical modeling in specific case analysis. Science and Justice, 36, 245 255. BACCHUS, F. 1990 Representing and Reasoning with Probabilistic Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. BAKER, J. 1975 Traffic Accident Investigation Manual. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Traffic Institute. BAKER, J. & FRICKE, L. 1990 Process of traffic accident reconstruction. Traffic Accident Reconstruction. (L. Fricke, ed.). Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Traffic Institute. BALDING, D.2000 Interpreting DNA evidence: Can probability theory help? Statistical Science in the Courtroom. (J. Gastwirth, ed.). New York: Springer, pp. 51 70. BALKE, A.&PEARL, J.1994 Probabilistic evaluation of counterfactual queries. Proceedings of 12th National Conference on Artificial Intelligence. Menlo Park, NJ: AAAI Press, pp. 230 237. BRACH, R. 1994 Uncertainty in accident reconstruction calculation. Accident Reconstruction: Technology and Animation IV. Warrendale, PA: SAE Inc., pp. 147 153. CARNAP, R.1945 The two concepts of probability. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 5, 513 532. CARNAP, R. 1971 A basic system of inductive logic, part I. Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability,Vol. I. (R. Carnap & R. Jeffrey, eds). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, pp. 33 166. CURRAN, J., TRIGGS, C., BUCKLETON, J., WALSH, K.&HICKS, T.1998 Assessing transfer probabilities in a Bayesian interpretation of forensic glass evidence. Science and Justice, 38, 15 21. DAVIS, G. 1999 Using graphical Markov models and Gibbs sampling to reconstruct vehicle/pedestrian accidents. Proceedings of the Conference Traffic Safety on Two Continents. Linkoping, Sweden: Swedish National Road and Transport Research Institute. DAVIS, G.2001 Using Bayesian networks to identify the causal effect of speeding in individual vehicle/pedestrian collisions. Proceedings of the 17th Conference on Uncertainty in Artificial Intelligence. (J. Breese & D. Koller, eds). San Francisco, CA: Morgan Kaufmann, pp. 105 111. DAVIS, G., SANDERSON, K. & DAVULURI, S. 2002 Development and Testing of a Vehicle/Pedestrian Collision Model for Neighborhood Traffic Control, Report 2002-23. St. Paul, MN: Minnesota Department of Transportation. DAWID, A.&EVETT, I.1997 Using a graphical method to assist the evaluation of complicated patterns of evidence. Journal of Forensic Science, 42, 226 231. DAWID, P.& MORTERA, J. 1998 Forensic identification with imperfect evidence. Biometrika, 85, 835 849. DUBOIS, D.&PRADE, H.1993 A glance at non-standard models and logics of uncertainty and vagueness. Philosophy of Probability. (J.-P. Dubucs, ed.). Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 169 222. EARMAN, J.1992 Bayes or Bust?. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. EDWARDS, W. 1991 Influence diagrams, Bayesian imperialism, and the Collins case: An appeal to reason. Cardozo Law Review, 13, 1025 1079. EUBANKS, J.& HILL, P. 1998 Pedestrian Accident Reconstruction and Litigation. Tuscon, AZ: Lawyers and Judges Publishing Co. EVETT, I. 1996 Expert evidence and forensic misconceptions of the nature of exact science. Science and Justice, 36, 118 122. FAMBRO, D., KOPPA, R., PICHA, D.& FITZPATRICK, K. 1998 Driver perception-brake response

86 G. A. DAVIS in stopping sight distance situations. Paper 981410 presented at 78th Annual Meeting of Transportation Research Board Washington, DC. FRICKE, L. 1990 Traffic Accident Reconstruction. Evanston, IL: Traffic Institute, Northwestern University. GARROTT, W.&GUENTHER, D.1982 Determination of precrash parameters from skid mark analysis. Transportation Research Record, 893, 38 46. GREATRIX, G. 2002 AI lecture notes 2: Analysis of a simple accident. Accident Investigation Lecture Notes, World Wide Website http://scratchy.spods.co.uk/~greatrix/ainotes. html, December 27, 2002. HACKING, I.1965 The Logic of Statistical Inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. HACKING, I.1975 The Emergence of Probability. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. HALPERN, J. 1990 An analysis of first-order logics of probability. Artificial Intelligence, 46, 311 350. HICKS, J. 1989 Traffic accident reconstruction. Forensic Engineering. (K. Carper, ed.). New York: Elsevier, pp. 101 129. HOOGSTRATE, A. & SPEK, A. 2002 Monte Carlo simulation and inference in accident reconstruction. presented at. 5th International Conference on Forensic Statistics. Venice. HOWSON, C. 1993 Personalistic Bayesianism. Philosophy of Probability. (J.-P. Dubucs, ed.). Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 1 12. JENSEN, F.1996 An Introduction to Bayesian Networks. New York: Springer. KOST, G. & WERNER, S. 1994 Use of Monte Carlo simulation techniques in accident reconstruction. SAE Technical Paper 940719,. Warrendale, PA: SAE Inc. LEWIS, D.1973 Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell. LEWIS, D. 1976 Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities. Philosophical Review, 85, 297 315. LEWIS, D. 1980 A subjectivist s guide to objective chance. Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability, Vol. II. (R. Jeffrey, ed.). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, pp. 263 294. LIMPERT, R. 1989 Motor Vehicle Accident Reconstruction and Cause Analysis, 3rd edn. Charlottesville, VA: Michie Co. LINDLEY, D. 1991 Subjective probability, decision analysis and their legal consequences. J. Roy. Statist. Soc. A, 154, 83 92. MCLEAN, J., ANDERSON, R., FARMER, M., LEE, B. & BROOKS, C. 1994 Vehicle Travel Speeds and the Incidence of Fatal Pedestrian Crashes, Road Accident Research Unit. Adelaide: University of Adelaide. NCUTLO, 1992 Uniform Vehicle Code and Model Traffic Ordinance. Evanston, IL: National Committee on Uniform Laws and Ordinances. NEPTUNE, J., FLYNN, J., CHAVEZ, P.& UNDERWOOD, H. 1995 Speed from skids: A modern approach. Accident Reconstruction: Technology and Animation V. Warrendale, PA: SAE Inc., pp. 189 204. NIEDERER, P. 1991 The accuracy and reliability of accident reconstruction. Automotive Engineering and Litigation, Vol. 4. (G. Peters & G. Peters, eds). New York: Wiley, pp. 257 303. PEARL, J. 2000 Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. POOLE, D.& RAFTERY, A. 2000 Inference for deterministic simulation models: The Bayesian melding approach. J. Amer. Statist. Assoc., 95, 1244 1255. REED, W.& KESKIN, A. 1989 Vehicular deceleration and its relationship to friction. SAE Technical Paper 890736. Warrendale, PA: SAE Inc.

BAYESIAN RECONSTRUCTION OF TRAFFIC ACCIDENTS 87 ROAD TRAFFIC ACT 1991 Her Majesty s Stationery Office. London. ROSE, N., FENTON, S.& HUGHES, C. 2001 Integrating Monte Carlo simulation, momentumbased impact modeling, and restitution data to analyze crash severity. SAE Technical Paper 2001-01-3347. Warrendale, PA: SAE Inc. RUDRAM, D.& LAMBOURN, R. 1981 The scientific investigation of road accidents. Journal of Occupational Accidents, 3, 177 185. SCHOCKENHOFF, G., APPEL, H. & RAU, H. 1985 Representation of actual reconstruction methods for car-to-car accidents as confirmed by crash tests. SAE Technical Paper 850066. Warrendale, PA: SAE Inc. SCHUM, D.2000 Singular evidence and probabilistic reasoning in judicial proof. Harmonisation in Forensic Expertise, Thela Thesis. (J. Nijboer & W. Sprangers, eds). pp. 587 603. SPIEGELHALTER, D., THOMAS, A.& BEST, N. 2000 WinBUGS Version 1.3 User Manual. Oxford: MRC Biostatistics Unit, Oxford University. STALNAKER, R. 1968 A theory of conditionals. American Philosophical Monograph Series #2. (N. Rescher, ed.). Oxford: Blackwell. STEWART-MORRIS, M. 1995 Real time, accurate recall, and other myths. Forensic Accident Investigation: Motor Vehicles. (T. Bohan & A. Damask, eds). Charlottesville, VA: Michie Butterworth, pp. 413 438. TARONI, F., AITKEN, C. & GARBOLINO, P. 2001 De Finetti s subjectivism, the assessment of probabilities and the evaluation of evidence: A commentary for forensic scientists. Science and Justice, 41, 145 150. TRAFFIC INSTITUTE 1946 Accident Investigation Manual. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Traffic Institute. WOOD, D. & O RIORDAIN, S. 1994 Monte Carlo simulation methods applied to accident reconstruction and avoidance analysis. Accident Reconstruction: Technology and Animation IV. Warrendale, PA: SAE Inc., pp. 129 136. Appendix A. WinBUGS code for Bayesian reconstruction of two-vehicle collision in Fricke (1990) model momentum #Fricke 1990 Momentum Example; English units { # counterfactual world(s) for (I in 1:M) { u2.star[i] <- u2.star.mph[i]*1.47 xbrake.star[i] <-pow(u2.star[i],2)/(2*ap2) xprt.star[i] <- u2.star[i]*tp xstop.star[i] <- xbrake.star[i]+xprt.star[i] stop.star[i] <- step(xinit2-xstop.star[i]) fullhit.star[i] <- step(xprt.star[i]-xinit2) tc1.star[i] <- xinit2/u2.star[i] xcrit.star[i] <- (1-stop.star[i])*max(xinit2-xprt.star[i],0) tc2.star[i] <- tp+(u2.star[i]-sqrt(pow(u2.star[i],2)-2*ap2*xcrit.star[i]))/ap2 tc.star[i] <- fullhit.star[i]*tc1.star[i] + (1-fullhit.star[i])*tc2.star[i] pass.star[i] <- step(tc.star[i]-(t.crit+20/v1))

88 G. A. DAVIS nohit.star[i] <- 1-(1-stop.star[i])*(1-pass.star[i]) } # estimate post-impact speeds from skidmarks ag <- mug*g*(wheels/4) vp <- sqrt(2*ag*skidg.bar) ap <- mup*g*(wheels/4) vfin <- sqrt(vp*vp+2*ap*skidp.bar) skidg dnorm(skidg.bar,.04) skidp dnorm(skidp.bar,.04) mug dunif(.4,.5) mup dunif(0.7,.8) skidg.bar dunif(20,60) skidp.bar dunif(60,100) # estimate pre-impact speeds using momentum conservation m1 <- wcar1 m2 <- wcar2 alpha1 dunif(a1low,a1up) alpha2 dunif(a2low,a2up) beta dunif(blow,bup) c <- 3.141592/180 v2 <- (vfin*m1*sin(beta*c)+vfin*m2*sin(beta*c))/(m2*sin(alpha2*c)) v1 <- (vfin*m1*cos(beta*c)+vfin*m2*cos(beta*c)-v2*m2*cos(alpha2*c))/(m1*cos(alpha1*c)) # estimate vehicle 2 initial speed and distance ap2 <- mup*g xx <- max(0,x) u2 <- sqrt((v2*v2+2*ap2*xx)) x.tran2 <- u2*ts-(ap2*pow(ts,2))/2 x.prt <- tp*u2 skid21.bar <- x-x.tran2 skid21 dnorm(skid21.bar,.04) xinit2 <-x+x.prt limit.fps <- limit*1.47 speeding <-step(u2-limit.fps) # estimate vehicle 1 s initial speed and critical time