Spring 2016 Ling 620 The Semantics of Control Infinitives: A First Introduction to De Se Attitudes

Similar documents
Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 3: Covert Movement vs. Type Shifting 1

Last time we had arrived at the following provisional interpretation of Aquinas second way:

Introduction to Semantics. A Case Study in Semantic Fieldwork: Modality in Tlingit

The Refutation of Relativism

TeachingEnglish Lesson plans. Conversation Lesson News. Topic: News

In Defense of Kantian Moral Theory Nader Shoaibi University of California, Berkeley

Relative truth and the first person

On the Paradox of the Question

CHAPTER 7 GENERAL PROOF SYSTEMS

RACE TO CLEAR THE MAT

Movement and Binding

Section 1.3 P 1 = 1 2. = P n = 1 P 3 = Continuing in this fashion, it should seem reasonable that, for any n = 1, 2, 3,..., =

Mathematical Induction

WRITING PROOFS. Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology

1. The Fly In The Ointment

5544 = = = Now we have to find a divisor of 693. We can try 3, and 693 = 3 231,and we keep dividing by 3 to get: 1

GOD S BIG STORY Week 1: Creation God Saw That It Was Good 1. LEADER PREPARATION

Linear Programming Notes VII Sensitivity Analysis

News Writing: Lead Paragraphs

Invalidity in Predicate Logic

Pascal is here expressing a kind of skepticism about the ability of human reason to deliver an answer to this question.

0.0.2 Pareto Efficiency (Sec. 4, Ch. 1 of text)

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 10

Polynomial Invariants

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces

Games of Incomplete Information

Iterated Dynamic Belief Revision. Sonja Smets, University of Groningen. website:

Socratic Questioning

3. Mathematical Induction

The fundamental question in economics is 2. Consumer Preferences

Practical Jealousy Management

Module 6.3 Client Catcher The Sequence (Already Buying Leads)

How does the problem of relativity relate to Thomas Kuhn s concept of paradigm?

WEB FORM E HELPING SKILLS SYSTEM

Writing Thesis Defense Papers

Active Listening. Learning Objectives. By the end of this module, the learner will have

STEP 5: Giving Feedback

ONLINE SAFETY TEACHER S GUIDE:

Current California Math Standards Balanced Equations

Lecture 8 The Subjective Theory of Betting on Theories

Point and Interval Estimates

of course the mean is p. That is just saying the average sample would have 82% answering

Writing = A Dialogue. Part I. They Say

BBC Learning English Talk about English Business Language To Go Part 12 - Business socialising

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2015

2. Argument Structure & Standardization

Complex Sentences. This icon indicates that detailed teacher s notes are available in the Notes Page.

Solutions to Math 51 First Exam January 29, 2015

Handout #1: Mathematical Reasoning

Book Review of Rosenhouse, The Monty Hall Problem. Leslie Burkholder 1

PEER PRESSURE TEACHER S GUIDE:

One natural response would be to cite evidence of past mornings, and give something like the following argument:

Boonin on the Future-Like-Ours Argument against Abortion. Pedro Galvão Centro de Filosofia da Universidade de Lisboa

Understanding Options: Calls and Puts

Solving Linear Systems, Continued and The Inverse of a Matrix

1.6 The Order of Operations

תילגנאב תורגבה תניחב ןורתפ

Cartesian Products and Relations

Planning and Writing Essays

Decision Making under Uncertainty

Cosmological Arguments for the Existence of God S. Clarke

INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY

Colored Hats and Logic Puzzles

Arguments and Dialogues

Using Questions to Promote Critical Thinking By Cindy McClung, coordinator for quality, and Bob Hoglund, president of Bob Hoglund Inc.

Jesus at the Temple (at age 12)

MONEY MANAGEMENT. Guy Bower delves into a topic every trader should endeavour to master - money management.

Self-Acceptance. A Frog Thing by E. Drachman (2005) California: Kidwick Books LLC. ISBN Grade Level: Third grade

FILMS AND BOOKS ADAPTATIONS

Ch. 13.2: Mathematical Expectation

I. GROUPS: BASIC DEFINITIONS AND EXAMPLES

BBC Learning English Talk about English Business Language To Go Part 1 - Interviews

The Real Estate Philosopher Porter s Five Forces in the Real Estate World

P1. All of the students will understand validity P2. You are one of the students C. You will understand validity

Ling 201 Syntax 1. Jirka Hana April 10, 2006

INTRODUCTION TO TEAMWORK AND GROUP DEVELOPMENT CORPORATE LEARNING COURSE TEAMBUILDING BLOCK SEMINAR 3.2

The Slate Is Not Empty: Descartes and Locke on Innate Ideas

TeachingEnglish Lesson plans

The Easy Way To Flipping Domain Names

Formal Languages and Automata Theory - Regular Expressions and Finite Automata -

How Expressivists Can and Should Solve Their Problem with Negation

Conditional Probability, Hypothesis Testing, and the Monty Hall Problem

Playing with Numbers

Q: What types of businesses/industries can benefit from the SBA loan programs? A: Most small owner-operated business can benefit from SBA loans

TO HELL WITH SPEECH ACT THEORY

1 Uncertainty and Preferences

TEST-TAKING STRATEGIES FOR READING

The structure of the English Sentence

KSE Comp. support for the writing process 2 1

BPM: Chess vs. Checkers

A Few Basics of Probability

Ep #19: Thought Management

Non-nominal Which-Relatives

Likewise, we have contradictions: formulas that can only be false, e.g. (p p).

Executive Summary of Mastering Business Growth & Change Made Easy

Row Echelon Form and Reduced Row Echelon Form

The Prime Numbers. Definition. A prime number is a positive integer with exactly two positive divisors.

So You d Like a Sport Psychology Consultant to Work With Your Team? Three Key Lessons Learned from Olympic Teams

Generic one, arbitrary PRO, and the first person

Lab 11. Simulations. The Concept

Transcription:

The Semantics of Control Infinitives: A First Introduction to De Se Attitudes 1. Non-Finite Control Complements and De Se Attitudes (1) Two Sentences that Seem Very Close in Meaning a. Dave expects he will win. b. Dave expects to win. Having developed a semantics for propositional attitude verbs like believes, we have the basic tools to develop an analysis of sentences like (1a). Can / Should we extend those tools to sentences like (1b), with non-finite complements? (2) Towards an Analysis of Sentence (1a) a. The Function Expectations : Just like belief -worlds, we could maybe introduce sets of expectation -worlds Expectations(x, w) = the set of worlds where x s expectations in w are realized = { w : x s expectations in w are realized in w } b. Lexical Semantics for Expects (based on [[believes]]): [[ expects ]] w = [ λp <st> : [ λx : For all w Expectations(x,w): p(w ) = T ] ] p is true in all the worlds where x s expectations are met c. Predicted Truth-Conditions for (1a): (i) Syntax: [ Dave 1 [ 1 [ t 1 [ expects [ he 1 will win ] ] ] (ii) Predicted Truth-Conditions: o For now, we ll fudge the presence of will in the complement clause... [[(1a)]] w = T iff For all w Expectations(Dave,w): Dave wins in w In every world where Dave s expectations in w are met, Dave wins. Easy peasy, right?... 1

Can we apply this to the case of the non-finite, Control sentence in (1b)?... (3) Towards an Analysis of Sentence (1b) a. Syntax of Non-Finite Control There is a great deal of converging syntactic evidence that Control sentences like (1b) have a structure with the following properties: (i) (ii) The non-finite clause contains a (phonologically empty) pronominal subject, PRO. This pronominal subject has to be bound. b. Possible Syntax of (1b): [ Dave 1 [ 1 [ t 1 [ expects [ PRO 1 to win ] ] ] c. Predicted Truth-Conditions: If we suppose that PRO is simply a bound pronoun, just like he in (2c), we ll end up predicting the exact same reading for (3b) [[(1b)]] w = T iff For all w Expectations(Dave,w): Dave wins in w So much winning!! But wait If it s this easy then why is there so much semantic literature on Control??... (4) Problem: Semantic Non-Equivalence of (1a) and (1b) Contrary to first impressions, sentences (1a) and (1b) do not mean exactly the same. In particular, their felicity differs in the following bizarre sorts of cases: a. Scenario: Dave is running for office, but he s pessimistic about his chances of winning. In his depression, he s getting drunk at a bar. On the TV, they play one of his political ads. He s so incredibly drunk, that he doesn t recognize himself or the ad on the TV. But, he s really impressed with the ad. He says to everyone else in the bar: See, that guy s gonna win this election! b. Judgments: (i) Sentence (1a) is sorta OK (meh?) (ii) Sentence (1b) is totally, definitely OUT! 2

(5) Some New Terminology: De Se Attitude 1 An agent x bears a de se attitude towards some content P only if: a. P is about x b. x figures into P in virtue of x thinking of themselves in a first personal way (Definition adapted from Pearson 2015) (6) De Se Attitudes More Informally a. In a de se attitude, like that expressed by (1b), the attitude holder is consciously self-ascribing a particular property (e.g., the property of going to win ) b. In a non-de se attitude, like that expressible by (1a), the attitude holder merely stands in a particular relation to a proposition involving themselves they needn t consciously recognize that they are themselves a component of that propositional content (7) Generalizations Invited by Facts like (4) a. Attitude sentences with Control infinitives can only express de se attitudes. Hence, the infelicity of (1b) in scenario (4a) b. Attitude sentences with finite complement need not express de se attitudes. Hence, the felicity of (1a) in scenario (4a) (8) The Obvious Task Now How can we augment our semantics to capture (7)? We need a theory of the truth-conditions of the de se reading for (1b). We need to concoct a story whereby (1b) can only get those truth-conditions, while (1a) doesn t (necessarily). 2. A Formal Theory of De Se Truth-Conditions (9) David Lewis s Insight About De Se Readings Lewis (1979) was the first to propose that de se readings involve the (conscious) selfascription of a property 99.999% of subsequent philosophical and semantic work builds on this key idea 1 The term de se is Latin for about oneself. 3

(10) Introducing Doxastic Alternatives a. Our Old Friend Beliefs, Restated: (i) Earlier Definition: Beliefs(x,w) = the worlds consistent with x s beliefs in w (ii) An Equivalent (But More Complicated) Formulation: Beliefs(x,w) = the worlds that x (in w) thinks they could be in b. A New Game Involving Beliefs To motivate Beliefs in (10a), we imagined playing a game, where we submit possible worlds to an entity x and ask Could this be the world you re in? We could also imagine another variant on this game o We submit to the entity x a pair consisting of a world w and an entity y from that world o We ask entity x, Given what you believe, could you be the entity y living in this world w? The set of pairs <y,w > to which the entity x answers Yes to are (obviously) those pairs <y,w > such that x (in w) thinks they could be y in w. c. Our New Friend, Doxastic Alternatives Dox-Alt(x,w) = the pairs <y,w > such that x (in w) thinks they could be y in w. Note that, just like Beliefs(x,w), Dox-Alt(x,w) can also be used to model the belief state of x in w. Note, moreover, that is provides even richer, more fine-grained information than Beliefs(x,w) o In addition to giving us the worlds that x thinks they re in o Dox-Alt also tells us the things in those worlds that x consciously identifies themselves as! 4

With all this in mind, the following seems like an attractive way of modeling the de se truthconditions of sentence (1b) (11) Dox-Alt and De Se Attitudes [[(1b)]] w = T iff For all <y,w > Dox-Alt(Dave,w): y wins in w These truth-conditions do not hold in scenario (4a) o After all, if we submitted to Dave a pair <y,w > such that y wins in w, Dave would (by assumption) say that he couldn t be entity y in world w But, these truth-conditions would definitely hold in a scenario where Dave thinks (optimistically) to himself I am going to win o Again, any pair <y,w > that Dave would say yes to in our game, must be one where y goes on to win! 3. Deriving the Desired Truth-Conditions So How can we set up things so that sentence (1b) receives the truth-conditions in (11)? Recalling the key insight in (9) that de se attitudes involve the (conscious) selfascription of a property Let s suppose that Control complements denote properties (type <s<et>>) (12) Lexical Semantics of Expect Control When it combines with a control complement, expect has the lexical semantics below: [[ expect ]] w = [ λp <s<e,t>> : [ λx : For all <y,w > Dox-Alt(x,w): P(w )(y) = T ] ] (13) Syntax of Control Complements As noted above in (3a), PRO has to be bound However, its not bound by the matrix subject, but rather by an operator in the leftperiphery of the control complement. 2 [ S1 Dave 1 [ VP expects [ CP 1 [ S2 PRO 1 to win ] ] ] ] 2 This general approach to the compositional semantics of Control is widely attributed to Chierchia (1990), Anaphora and Attitudes De Se. 5

(14) Derivation of the Desired Truth-Conditions a. [[(13)]] w,g = T iff (by FA, Lex.) b. [[VP]] w,g ( Dave ) = T iff (by IFA) c. [[expects]] w,g ( [λw : [[CP]] w,g ] )(Dave) = T iff (by PA) d. [[expects]] w,g ( [λw : λx: [[S]] w,g(1/x) ] )(Dave) = T iff (by FA, Lex., LC) e. [[expects]] w,g ( [λw : λx: x wins in w ] )(Dave) = T iff (by Lex.) f. [ λp <s<e,t>> : [ λx : For all <y,w > Dox-Alt(x,w): P(w )(y) = T ] ] ( [λw : λx: x wins in w ] )(Dave) = T iff (by LC) g. For all <y,w > Dox-Alt(Dave,w): [λw : λx: x wins in w ](w )(y) = T iff (by LC) h. For all <y,w > Dox-Alt(Dave,w): y wins in w A Potentially Problematic Quirk of This Treatment: Under this analysis, PRO is not directly bound by the subject Rather, it s bound by an operator in the left periphery of the subordinate clause The understood co-evaluation of PRO and the subject is due to the lexical semantics of the attitude verb (and the nature of what a Doxastic Alternative is) In recent work, Landau (2015) argues that this is in conflict with the syntactic evidence that the subject does directly bind PRO in control sentences like (1b) 3 o Landau proposes a synthesis of these two analyses, which allows us to retain the core of our semantic treatment above But what about sentence (1a)?... 3 Direct Variable Binding and Agreement in Obligatory Control. Available online at Lingbuzz: http://ling.auf.net/lingbuzz/002392 6

(15) Some Initial Thoughts on Finite Complements In a few more classes, we ll develop a more in-depth treatment of the reading sentences like (1a) get in scenarios like (4) (i.e., so-called de re readings) For now, though, it can be noted that our original semantics in (2c) actually does a pretty good job! o Note that (2c) says only that in all of Dave s belief worlds, Dave is the winner. o These truth-conditions are completely agnostics as to whether Dave consciously self-identifies as the winner or not. o Thus, these truth-conditions would seem to hold both in scenarios with conscious self-identification ( I m going to win ) and ones without it (4a). o Thus, at first glance, they d seem to do the right job They predict that (1a) will end up being construed as true in either such scenario But, we ll have much more to say about this later 7