PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS

Similar documents
DISCRETE MATH: LECTURE 3

ON WHITCOMB S GROUNDING ARGUMENT FOR ATHEISM Joshua Rasmussen Andrew Cullison Daniel Howard-Snyder

DEDUCTIVE & INDUCTIVE REASONING

Read this syllabus very carefully. If there are any reasons why you cannot comply with what I am requiring, then talk with me about this at once.

Kant s deontological ethics

Skepticism about the external world & the problem of other minds

Quine on truth by convention

Chapter 5: Fallacies. 23 February 2015

Mathematical Induction

Philosophical argument

2. Argument Structure & Standardization

Divine command theory

Locke s psychological theory of personal identity

Cosmological Arguments for the Existence of God S. Clarke

Against Zangwill s Extreme Formalism About Inorganic Nature

Reality in the Eyes of Descartes and Berkeley. By: Nada Shokry 5/21/2013 AUC - Philosophy

Likewise, we have contradictions: formulas that can only be false, e.g. (p p).

Last time we had arrived at the following provisional interpretation of Aquinas second way:

You will by now not be surprised that a version of the teleological argument can be found in the writings of Thomas Aquinas.

Writing Thesis Defense Papers

How To Understand The Moral Code Of A God (For Men)

The Refutation of Relativism

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

A Few Basics of Probability

CHAPTER 3. Methods of Proofs. 1. Logical Arguments and Formal Proofs

Arguments and Dialogues

Time and Causation in Gödel s Universe.

1/9. Locke 1: Critique of Innate Ideas

NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS

Book Review of Rosenhouse, The Monty Hall Problem. Leslie Burkholder 1

SCHOPENHAUER AND WITTGENSTEIN ON SELF AND OBJECT. In the 5.6 s of the Tractatus, Wittgenstein introduces remarks about the self and

Invalidity in Predicate Logic

The Slate Is Not Empty: Descartes and Locke on Innate Ideas

Critical Analysis So what does that REALLY mean?

Argument for a Distinction Between the Mind/Soul and the Body. This is a prose summary of the diagrammed argument on the previous page:

Killing And Letting Die

Responding to Arguments against the Existence of God Based on Evil

Lecture 9 Maher on Inductive Probability

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist

The Problem of Evil not If God exists, she'd be OOG. If an OOG being exists, there would be no evil. God exists.

P1. All of the students will understand validity P2. You are one of the students C. You will understand validity

WRITING PROOFS. Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology

The Meta-Problem of Change

Philosophy 1100 Introduction to Ethics. Lecture 3 Three Different Types of Ethical Theories

In Defense of Kantian Moral Theory Nader Shoaibi University of California, Berkeley

Split brains, teletransportation, and personal identity

Conceiving What Is Not There

Reply to French and Genone Symposium on Naïve Realism and Illusion The Brains Blog, January Boyd Millar

Writer moves somewhat beyond merely paraphrasing someone else s point of view or

Kant s Dialectic. Lecture 3 The Soul, part II John Filling jf582@cam.ac.uk

CONCEPTUAL CONTINGENCY AND ABSTRACT EXISTENCE

def: An axiom is a statement that is assumed to be true, or in the case of a mathematical system, is used to specify the system.

Math 3000 Section 003 Intro to Abstract Math Homework 2

Kant on Time. Diana Mertz Hsieh Kant (Phil 5010, Hanna) 28 September 2004

Critical Thinking Reading & Writing Test

Chunking? Sounds like psychobabble!

Organizing an essay the basics 2. Cause and effect essay (shorter version) 3. Compare/contrast essay (shorter version) 4

Handout #1: Mathematical Reasoning

How does the problem of relativity relate to Thomas Kuhn s concept of paradigm?

Some key arguments from Meditations III-V

3. Mathematical Induction

MILL. The principle of utility determines the rightness of acts (or rules of action?) by their effect on the total happiness.

Critical Study David Benatar. Better Never To Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006)

CRITICAL THINKING REASONS FOR BELIEF AND DOUBT (VAUGHN CH. 4)

A Short Course in Logic Zeno s Paradox

Does rationality consist in responding correctly to reasons? John Broome Journal of Moral Philosophy, 4 (2007), pp

Lecture 2: Moral Reasoning & Evaluating Ethical Theories

THE MORAL AGENDA OF CITIZENSHIP EDUCATION

Independent samples t-test. Dr. Tom Pierce Radford University

DEREK PARFIT. Derek Parfit is a Fellow of All Souls College, Oxford, and author of the controversial and widely acclaimed book Reasons and Persons.

of Nebraska - Lincoln

1.2 Forms and Validity

A simple solution to the hardest logic puzzle ever

Neutrality s Much Needed Place In Dewey s Two-Part Criterion For Democratic Education

Mathematical Induction

Discourse Markers in English Writing

1 Must the universe have a cause?

Deductive reasoning is the kind of reasoning in which, roughly, the truth of the input

A. Schedule: Reading, problem set #2, midterm. B. Problem set #1: Aim to have this for you by Thursday (but it could be Tuesday)

Phil 420: Metaphysics Spring [Handout 4] Hilary Putnam: Why There Isn t A Ready-Made World

or conventional implicature [1]. If the implication is only pragmatic, explicating logical truth, and, thus, also consequence and inconsistency.

Mind & Body Cartesian Dualism

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products

WHAT MAKES SOMEONE'S LIFE GO BEST Derek Parfit (From Parfit, Reasons and Persons, 1984)

The Double Lives of Objects: An Essay in the Metaphysics of the Ordinary World

Gödel s Ontological Proof of the Existence of God

In his 2007 paper, Locke on Individuation and the Corpuscular

Hume on identity over time and persons

Things That Might Not Have Been Michael Nelson University of California at Riverside

Arguments and Methodology INTRODUCTION

CELC Benchmark Essays Set 3 Prompt:

3. Logical Reasoning in Mathematics

Buridan and the Avicenna-Johnston semantics

Explain and critically assess the Singer Solution to Global Poverty

Writing an essay. This seems obvious - but it is surprising how many people don't really do this.

Practical Jealousy Management

ON EXTERNAL OBJECTS By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

Association Between Variables

One natural response would be to cite evidence of past mornings, and give something like the following argument:

Einstein s Theory of Special Relativity Made Relatively Simple!

Transcription:

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS Topic IV: The Nature of the Mind Arguments for (Persisting) Substance Dualism Argument 1: The Modal Argument from Personal Identity This first type of argument is advanced by Richard Swinburne in his book The Evolution of the Soul Revised Edition (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997) pages 148ff.). In one version of his argument, Swinburne considers the case where the left and right hemispheres of a person s brain are transplanted into different bodies. Swinburne advances the following crucial claims about this sort of case: The operation would therefore create at least one new person we may have our views about which (if either) resultant person p is, but we could be wrong. And that is my basic point however much we knew in such a situation about what happens to the parts of a person s body, we would not know for certain what happens to the person. (148-9) Although it may be the case that if my two brain hemispheres are transplanted into different bodies, I survive partly as the person whose body is controlled by one and partly as the person whose body is controlled by the other, it may not be like that at all. Maybe I go just where the left hemisphere goes. (150) Given these claims, it seems to me that Swinburne s argument can be put as follows: Personal Identity and the Hemisphere s Argument (1) In the case where one hemisphere of one s brain is transplanted into one body, and the other hemisphere into another body, it is possible that the result is that one then has two new people, but it is also possible that one is identical with, say, the person associated with the left hemisphere. (2) If one s mind is an immaterial substance, this is a possibility, since one s immaterial mind could accompany the left hemisphere into the new body. (3) On the other hand, if one does not have an immaterial mind, then no facts about one s two hemispheres could make it the case that one was identical with the person associated with the body containing the left hemisphere. (4) Accordingly, one must have an immaterial mind, since otherwise what is clearly a possibility would be not be a possibility. A bit later, Swinburne focuses instead on the idea of surviving bodily death. Here the heart of Swinburne s argument is found in the following passage: This liberalized Aristotelian assumption I will call the quasi-aristotelian assumption: that a substance S 2 at t 2 is the same substance as an earlier substance S 1 at t 1 only if S 2 is made of some of the same stuff as S 1 (or stuff obtained by gradual replacement). Given the quasi-aristotelian assumption, and given, that for any present person who is currently conscious, there is no logical impossibility, whatever else may be true now of that person, that that person continues to exist without his body,

2 it follows that that person must now actually have a part other than a bodily part which can continue, and which we may call his soul and so that his possession of it is entailed by his being a conscious being. For there is not even a logical possibility that if I now consist of nothing but matter and that matter is destroyed, that I should nevertheless continue to exist. From the mere logical possibility of my continued existence there follows the actual fact that there is now more to me than my body; and that more is the essential part of myself. A person s being conscious is thus to be analyzed as an immaterial core of himself, his soul being conscious. (The Evolution of the Soul Revised Edition, p. 154) Here it seems that Swinburne s argument is as follows: Personal Identity and the Survival of Death Argument (1) It is logically possible for a person to continue to exist without his body. (2) If one s mind is an immaterial substance, continuing to exist without one s body is a possibility, since one continues to exist if one s mind continues to exist. (3) On the other hand, if one does not have an immaterial mind, then continuing to exist without one s body is not a possibility (4) Accordingly, one must have an immaterial mind, since otherwise what is clearly a possibility would be not be a possibility. Discussion of Argument 1: The Personal Identity Arguments One can talk about what things are logically possible simpliciter and about what things are logically possible given certain other things. To say that p is logically possible simpliciter is to say that the proposition that p is true does not generate any contradiction. The following things are logically possible simpliciter: (1) It is logically possible that person A s experiences and other mental states belong to an immaterial mind. (2) It is logically possible that if person A s hemispheres were transplanted into two different bodies, person A would be identical with the person associated with the body containing A s left hemisphere, and not with the person associated with the body containing A s right hemisphere. To say that p is logically possible relative to q is to say that the conjunction p & q does not generate any contradiction. What is one to say, now, about the following claim? (3) Given everything that is true about person A, it is logically possible that if person A s hemispheres were transplanted into two different bodies, person A would be identical with the person associated with the body containing A s left hemisphere, and not with the person associated with the body containing A s right hemisphere. The answer is that whether this last proposition is true depends upon what is true about person A. If it is true that person A has an immaterial mind, then (3) is true. But if it is false that person A has an immaterial mind, then (3) is false.

3 One can now see what is wrong with Swinburne s argument involving personal identities and transplantation of hemispheres into different bodies. The problem with the argument is that Swinburne is failing to distinguish between proposition (2) and proposition (3). Once one does so, it is clear that proposition (2) may be true while proposition (3) is false, and because of this it is clear that the truth of (2) does not entail that human persons have immaterial minds. How could Swinburne make this mistake? Here is a possible explanation. Consider the following statement: (1) p entails q. Statement (1) can also be expressed as (2) Necessarily, if p then q. But sometimes, in ordinary speech, statement (2) is expressed by (3) If p, then necessarily q. Statement (3), however, is not a happy way of expressing either (1) or (2). This is most easily seen if we introduce the following symbols: for if then--- for necessarily. Sentences (2) and (3) are then most naturally symbolized as follows: (2*) (p q) (3*) p q But (2*) and (3*) are not, of course, logically equivalent. Not does (2*) entail (3*). In passing, it is worth noting that a fallacious inference of this type is sometimes involved in arguments for logical fatalism. Consider, for example, the following argument: (1) It is necessarily the case that if p then p. (2) If p, then necessarily p. (3) It is necessarily the case that if ~p then ~p. (4) If ~p, then necessarily ~p. (5) Either p or ~p. (6) Necessarily p or necessarily ~p. In symbols: (1) (p p)

4 (2) p p (3) (~p ~p) (4) ~p ~p (5) p v ~p (6) p v ~p My suggestion, then, is that Swinburne may be making the fallacious inference involved in the following line of thought: (1) The proposition that humans have no immaterial minds entails that it is not the case in the splitting scenario that the person before the splitting is identical with the person associated later with the body containing the left hemisphere. (2) Necessarily, if humans have no immaterial minds, then it is not the case in the splitting scenario that the person before the splitting is identical with the person associated later with the body containing the left hemisphere. (3) If humans have no immaterial minds, then necessarily it is not the case in the splitting scenario that the person before the splitting is identical with the person associated later with the body containing the left hemisphere. (4) If humans have no immaterial minds, then it is impossible in the splitting scenario that the person before the splitting is identical with the person associated later with the body containing the left hemisphere. Similarly, in the case of the version of Swinburne s personal identity and survival of death argument, the following two things are true: (1) It is logically possible for a person to continue to exist in the absence of his body. (2) The proposition that humans do not have immaterial minds entails that a human person does not continue to exist in the absence of his body. These two things do not entail: (3) Accordingly, human persons have immaterial minds. But if one expresses (2) by means of the following misleading statement: (2*) If humans do not have immaterial minds, then necessarily it is not the case that a person continues to exist in the absence of his body. it will then be tempting to move to (2**) If humans do not have immaterial minds, then it is impossible for a person to continue to exist in the absence of his body. But given (1) and (2**), one can move to (3) via modus tollens. The problem, in short, is that (2) does not entail (2**), but if one uses (2*) to express what is being said by (2), it is easy to think that one can move from (2) to (2**).

5 I am not sure that Swinburne is committing this modal fallacy. But it is one that is easy to commit if one formulates things in terms of ordinary language, rather than in a more formal way. Another possibility is that Swinburne is formulating things in terms of a sentence that is ambiguous, and that, when interpreted in one way, makes one premise true, but another false, and when interpreted in the other way, again makes only one of the two premises true, but this time the premise that is true under the first interpretation comes out false, while the premise that is false under the first interpretation now comes out true. Here s an illustration of how that can happen. First of all, let us use the following abbreviations: p = [A s mind = A s brain]. q = [A s mind survives the destruction of A s brain]. Now in my earlier account of where Swinburne might be going wrong, I supposed that he was, to put it in terms of the present propositions, moving fallaciously from (p ~q) to (p ~q), and then on to (p ~ q). But let us suppose that he simply views the last of these as an obvious premise. His argument is then simply this: (1) (p ~ q) (2) q (3) ~p My suggestion now is that q can be interpreted in the following two ways: q 1 = [The thing that is, as a matter of fact, A s mind survives the destruction of A s brain]. q 2 = [A s experiences and other mental states (but not powers) belong to something namely, an immaterial mind that survives the destruction of A s brain]. My claims are now as follows: (1) It is true that (p ~q 1 ). (2) It is also true that (p ~ q 1 ). But (3) It is not true that one can establish that q 1 is the case by an appeal to what one can imagine or coherently conceive. Whether it is possible that the thing that is, as a matter of fact, A s mind survives the destruction of A s brain depend on what sort of thing A s mind is. If it is A s brain, then q 1 is not possible. (4) It is true, on the other hand, that one can establish that q 2 is the case by an appeal to what one can imagine or coherently conceive. (5) It is also true that (p ~q 2 ).

6 (6) But it is not true that (p ~ q 1 ). The proposition that p is perfectly compatible with the proposition that it is possible that A s mind,, rather than being identical with A s brain, is instead an immaterial substance. The upshot is that q is capable of being interpreted in two ways, either as q 1 or as q 2. On either interpretation, only one of the following two premises is true: (1) (p ~ q) (2) q. To sum up, then, it seems to me that Swinburne is probably going astray for either of two reasons. One is that he is using a formulation of a premise that is ambiguous, and either interpretation of which makes only one of this two premises true. The other is that he is starting from premises, all of which are true, but then is committing a modal fallacy on route to his conclusion.