Grice: Meaning. In cases of natural meaning, x means that p entails that p; in cases of meaning NN, there is no such entailment.



Similar documents
The Top 10 Misconceptions about Implicature

or conventional implicature [1]. If the implication is only pragmatic, explicating logical truth, and, thus, also consequence and inconsistency.

TO HELL WITH SPEECH ACT THEORY

Pragmatic Meaning (Ch. 4 from Chierchia & McConnell-Ginet)

Semantics versus Pragmatics

The Refutation of Relativism

Kant s deontological ethics

Meaning and communication, swearing and silence

Arguments and Dialogues

Mathematical Induction

Strand: Reading Literature Topics Standard I can statements Vocabulary Key Ideas and Details

5544 = = = Now we have to find a divisor of 693. We can try 3, and 693 = 3 231,and we keep dividing by 3 to get: 1

BBC Learning English Talk about English Business Language To Go Part 1 - Interviews

Critical Analysis So what does that REALLY mean?

Very simple: the phrase 'can I' followed by the verb. But what verb form comes after the phrase 'can I'? Listen to these two examples of asking.

INFORMATIVE SPEECH. Examples: 1. Specific purpose: I want to explain the characteristics of the six major classifications of show dogs.

Introduction: Reading and writing; talking and thinking

Last time we had arrived at the following provisional interpretation of Aquinas second way:

Discourse Markers in English Writing

Writing an Introductory Paragraph for an Expository Essay

WRITING PROOFS. Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology

Is the Symmetry Problem Really a Problem?

CHAPTER 7 ARGUMENTS WITH DEFIITIONAL AND MISSING PREMISES

Slippery Slopes and Vagueness

Quine on truth by convention

Third Grade Language Arts Learning Targets - Common Core

Guidelines for Effective Business Writing: Concise, Persuasive, Correct in Tone and Inviting to Read

Club Accounts Question 6.

How does the problem of relativity relate to Thomas Kuhn s concept of paradigm?

When I think about using an advanced scientific or graphing calculator, I feel:

CS4025: Pragmatics. Resolving referring Expressions Interpreting intention in dialogue Conversational Implicature

Section 11. Giving and Receiving Feedback

Introduction: Presuppositions in Context Theoretical Issues and Experimental Perspectives

1) The subject. The man walked down the street. 2) A participle (word ending in ing or ed) Walking up the street, he tripped.

Philosophical argument

Refer to: Present & future If-clause Main clause. ZERO Present + Present. If you can meet me at the car, that s easiest for me.

3rd Grade Common Core State Standards Writing

THE MORAL AGENDA OF CITIZENSHIP EDUCATION

Cultural Relativism. 1. What is Cultural Relativism? 2. Is Cultural Relativism true? 3. What can we learn from Cultural Relativism?

NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS

DIFFICULTIES AND SOME PROBLEMS IN TRANSLATING LEGAL DOCUMENTS

Writing Thesis Defense Papers

PUNCTUATION PATTERNS

Chapter 5: Fallacies. 23 February 2015

Rethinking the relationship between transitive and intransitive verbs

How To Proofread

The Margin of Error for Differences in Polls

Handouts for Conversation Partners: Grammar

Cambridge English: First (FCE) Frequently Asked Questions (FAQs)

WEB FORM E HELPING SKILLS SYSTEM

Pay per Click Success 5 Easy Ways to Grow Sales and Lower Costs

10th Grade Language. Goal ISAT% Objective Description (with content limits) Vocabulary Words

Did you know that more than 50% of the folks who call themselves Catholic choose not to believe what is really the heart of our faith?

Real Estate Sales Associate Aptitude Test

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2015

Lecture 9 Maher on Inductive Probability

Invalidity in Predicate Logic

Section 8 Foreign Languages. Article 1 OVERALL OBJECTIVE

CORRECTING AND GIVING FEEDBACK TO WRITING

Indiana Department of Education

6b: QUALITATIVE DATA ANALYSIS

The Notions of Literal and Non-literal Meaning in Semantics and Pragmatics

Academic Standards for Reading, Writing, Speaking, and Listening June 1, 2009 FINAL Elementary Standards Grades 3-8

stress, intonation and pauses and pronounce English sounds correctly. (b) To speak accurately to the listener(s) about one s thoughts and feelings,

SIXTH GRADE UNIT 1. Reading: Literature

WRITING EFFECTIVE REPORTS AND ESSAYS

Virginia English Standards of Learning Grade 8

1. Current situation Describe the problem or opportunity (the need for your proposal).

BBC Learning English Talk about English Business Language To Go Part 10 - Dealing with difficult clients

Chapter 4 COMMUNICATION SKILLS. The difference between verbal and nonverbal communication. The difference between hearing and listening

Social Return on Investment

Gifted Middle School Summer Reading Animal Farm

Language Arts Core, First Grade, Standard 8 Writing-Students write daily to communicate effectively for a variety of purposes and audiences.

Argument Mapping 2: Claims and Reasons

ESL Intensive ESLS Listening/Speaking 400 (CLB 4) Unit 2: Shopping. Instructor Resource Guide

Decision Making under Uncertainty

A Short Course in Logic Zeno s Paradox

STAAR Sample Short Answer Questions

Study questions Give a short answer to the following questions:

Gerunds, Participles, and Infinitives

Units of Study 9th Grade

Developing Communication Skills in Learning for Life and Work

Support Materials for Core Content for Assessment. Reading

Preparing for the GED Essay

some ideas on essays and essay writing

xxx Lesson Comprehend the writing process 2. Respond positively to the writing process

THE IMPORTANCE OF SPEAKING SKILLS FOR EFL LEARNERS

Peeling Back the Layers Sister Grade Seven

Language Meaning and Use

Philosophy of Language

EXAMS Leaving Certificate English

Read this syllabus very carefully. If there are any reasons why you cannot comply with what I am requiring, then talk with me about this at once.

In Defense of Kantian Moral Theory Nader Shoaibi University of California, Berkeley

COMPUTER SUPPORT STAFF TIPS FOR DISABILITY ETIQUETTE

1/9. Locke 1: Critique of Innate Ideas

Date Re-Assessed. Indicator. CCSS.ELA-Literacy.RF.5.3 Know and apply grade-level phonics and word analysis skills in decoding words.

COMPARATIVES WITHOUT DEGREES: A NEW APPROACH. FRIEDERIKE MOLTMANN IHPST, Paris fmoltmann@univ-paris1.fr

SECTION 5 TEST III (WRITING) SAMPLE CONSTRUCTED- RESPONSE ASSIGNMENT

Preparing for the IELTS test with Holmesglen Institute of TAFE

Specific Measurable Achievable. Relevant Timely. PERFORMANCE MANAGEMENT CREATING SMART OBJECTIVES: Participant Guide PROGRAM OVERVIEW

Transcription:

INTENTION BASED SEMANTICS Grice: Meaning Grice is proposing an intention based semantics i.e., a semantical theory according to which the meaning of an utterance is explicated in terms of the psychological state it is intended to produce in an audience. Such a semantics focuses on the use of language to communicate. Hence Grice begins with an attempt to isolate a particular kind of meaning, which he calls communicative meaning, or nonnatural meaning (meaning NN ). NATURAL VS. NON-NATURAL MEANING Natural Meaning [ Noncognitive meaning ] Those spots mean measles. Those spots didn t mean anything to me, but to the doctor they meant measles. The recent budget means that we shall have a hard year. Nonnatural Meaning (Meaning NN ) [ Communicative meaning ] Those three rings on the bell mean that the bus is full. That remark, Smith couldn t get on without his trouble and strife, meant that Smith found his wife indispensable. Grice s endeavor is to produce an account of meaning NN. Tests for Meaning NN Entailment In cases of natural meaning, x means that p entails that p; in cases of meaning NN, there is no such entailment. Example Those spots mean measles, but he hasn t got measles is selfcontradictory. Those three rings on the bell mean that the bus is full, but the bus isn t full is not self-contradictory. 1

Quotation In cases of natural meaning, the verb mean cannot be followed by a quotation ( a phrase in inverted commas ); in cases of meaning NN, it can. Example * Those spots mean he has measles. Those three rings on the bell mean the bus is full. REJECTION OF CAUSAL ACCOUNT Grice considers and rejects a causal account of meaning NN. Such an account would run roughly like this: x means NN something iff x has a tendency to produce such and such a cognitive effect in a hearer and to be produced by that state in a speaker. It is easy to find counter-examples to this account. Here is Grice s: my putting on a tail coat tends to make an audience think I am about to go to a dance, and I may put on a tail coat because I think I am about to go to a dance. But my putting on a tail coat does not mean NN that I am about to go to a dance. Grice finds two things wrong with the causal account: 1. It omits the notion of intention. What needs to be specified is not the effect that tends to be produced, but the effect that the speaker intends to produce. 2. It concentrates on the idea of a standard meaning (of an expression or utterance), and ignores what a particular speaker may mean on a particular occasion. Grice further objects, more controversially, that the causal theory gets the priorities between utterance meaning and speaker meaning backwards. That is, the meaning of a sign needs to be explained in terms of what users of the sign mean by it on particular occasions (p. 94). REFLEXIVE-INTENTION ACCOUNT Grice develops his account in stages. Stage 1 introduces an intention. Stage 2 adds a reflexive intention. Stage 3 introduces an additional reflexive intention connecting the first intention to the intended effect on the hearer. 2

Stage 1: Intentions One might think that all that needs to be done is to take the causal account, and replace tends to produce with is intended to produce. That would yield an account that looks like this: x means NN something iff x is intended by its utterer to induce a belief in an audience. x means NN that p iff x is intended by its utterer to induce in an audience the belief that p. But this is too simplistic. If I leave B s handkerchief at a crime scene I may induce in the detective the belief that B is guilty, but my leaving the handkerchief does not mean NN this. Indeed, it does not mean NN anything. Stage 2: Reflexive Intentions What is needed is an intention on the part of the speaker that the hearer recognize the speaker s intention to induce a belief in the hearer: x means NN that p iff x is intended by its utterer to induce in an audience the belief that p and the utterer intends that the audience should recognize that intention. This is not quite right. As Grice s counter-examples (p. 95: Herod presenting the head of St. John to Salome; leaving the broken china in plain view for wife to see) show, the agent needs to do more than just (i 1 ) intend to induce a belief and (coincidentally) (i 2 ) intend that the audience should recognize that he has that intention (i 1 ). What s needed is a connection between intention (i 1 ) and the belief the speaker is trying to induce. That is, it we need it to be by means of a recognition of (i 1 ) that the audience is intended to have that belief. Stage 3: The Final Account The speaker must have these three intentions: (i 1 ) that the audience should believe that p. (i 2 ) that the audience should recognize the speaker s intention (i 1 ). 3

(i 3 ) that it be by means of the recognition of (i 1 ) that the audience comes to believe that p. That is: A meant NN something by x is roughly equivalent to A uttered x with the intention of inducing a belief by means of the recognition of this intention (p. 95). We can slightly expand (and clarify) this account along the lines of Strawson s version ( Intention and Convention in Speech Acts, Phil Rev 1964, p. 446). Where S is the speaker and H is the hearer: In uttering x S means NN that p iff S intends by uttering x: (i 1 ) to produce in H the belief that p, and (i 2 ) that H should recognize S s intention (i 1 ), and (i 3 ) that H should base his belief that p on his recognition of (i 1 ). [Strawson thinks that we have to add (at least) a fourth intention to this, viz.: (i 4 ) that H should recognize S s intention (i 2 ).] GENERAL MORAL OF THE ACCOUNT In a subsequent paper Utterer s Meaning and Intentions (Phil. Rev. 1969), Grice offered a much more complex account along the same lines. But the root idea remains the same: Meaning NN is to be analyzed in terms of reflexive intentions i.e., the intention to induce a psychological state in a hearer by means of a recognition of that very intention. If Grice is right, speaker s meaning (what a speaker intends to communicate) is a more fundamental notion than sentence meaning. That is, sentences mean what they do because of what speakers intend to communicate by means of them; rather than: speakers mean what they do because of what the sentences they use mean (in some non-intentional account of sentence meaning). As Grice later puts it, we can distinguish between: Relativized meaning (a kind of meaning the explication of which essentially involves reference to word users or communicators), and Nonrelativized meaning (where no such reference is required). 4

Then Grice s claim is that nonrelativized meaning is the secondary notion, capable of being reduced to, or analyzed in terms of, relativized meaning; and no corresponding analysis or reduction in the other direction is possible. CRITICISMS OF GRICE There have been many criticisms and amendments, both friendly and unfriendly. We ll look at one from each camp. Searle In What is a Speech Act? in Philosophy in America, 1965. Suppose that I am an American soldier in WW II and that I am captured by Italian troops. And suppose also that I wish to get these troops to believe that I am a German officer in order to get them to release me. What I would like to do is to tell them in German or Italian that I am a German officer. But let us suppose I don t know enough German or Italian to do that. So I put on a show of telling them that I am a German officer by reciting those few bits of German that I know, trusting that they don t know enough German to see through my plan. Let us suppose I know only one line of German, which I remember from a poem I had to memorize in a high school German course. Therefore I, a captured American, address my Italian captors with the following sentence: Kennst du das Land, wo die Zitronen blühen? Searle claims that the three clauses of Grice s account of meaning are satisfied: I intend to produce a certain effect in them, namely, the effect of (i 1 ) believing that I am a German officer; and I intend to produce this effect (i 3 ) by means of their (i 2 ) recognition of my intention. But when I say Kennst du das Land, wo die Zitronen blühen? do I mean I am a German officer? Not at all, says Searle: because what the words mean is, Knowest thou the land where the lemon trees bloom? Meaning is more than a matter of intention, it is also a matter of convention. On the basis of this example, Searle suggests an additional clause, one that adds (roughly) that the speaker intends to respect the linguistic conventions for the use of the sentence he utters. Grice responds to this effectively in Utterer s Meaning and Intentions. 5

Platts 1. He refuses to accept Searle s proposed amendment about conventional meaning. The reason, he says, is that I would like to treat meaning something by the utterance of a sentence as being only a special case of meaning something by an utterance (p. 161). In other words, conventional meaning ( sentence meaning ) is to be analyzed in terms of speaker s meaning, and not the other way around. And this refusal is crucial for Grice if he accepts it, his account of sentence-meaning in terms of speaker s meaning becomes circular (since part of the account of speaker s meaning would, on Searle s amendment, appeal to conventional linguistic meaning). 2. As for the example, Grice s basic line is that it is underdescribed, and can be fleshed out in various ways. In any event, it is not really a counter-example. 3. On one elaboration, the soldier s intention is not to get the Italians to believe that he has said that he s a German officer, but just to get them to believe he has been speaking German. (He hopes that they ll go on to draw the conclusion that he s a German officer who else would be speaking German around here? ) So although he intends (i 1 ) them to believe that he s a German officer, he does not intend (i 2 ) that they should believe this on the basis of their recognition of (i 1 ) he intends that they should believe on the basis of their reasoning as above. 4. Fleshed out in another way, the soldier s intention is to get the Italians to believe that he has just said that he s a German officer i.e. that he was uttering a sentence of German whose conventional meaning in German is I am a German officer. But if so, Grice says, it is not so implausible to suppose that he did mean that he was a German officer. After all, he didn t intend the Italians to take his words literally, for he knew they would have no idea what they meant literally. So what he meant in the circumstances was not the same as what his words literally meant. (It s like the Egyptian shopkeeper who invites his English visitor into his shop: in dulcet tones and with an alluring smile [the shopkeeper] says to [the visitor] the Arabic for You pig of an Englishman. What his words meant was an insult; but what he meant was for the visitor to enter the shop.) (In Ways of Meaning, 1979.) This line of objection is directed against the entire program of (what Schiffer calls) intention-based semantics. The objection is that Grice cannot provide a non-circular account of the meanings of (the infinitely many) unuttered sentences. 6

1. Grice tries to reduce sentence-meaning to the (logically prior) notion of speaker s meaning, which is itself spelled out in terms of speaker s intentions to produce beliefs in hearers. Since belief is a propositional attitude, this means that for Grice the basic unit of meaning is the sentence. 2. But natural languages contain infinitely many meaningful sentences. And only finitely many of them have ever been uttered. So there are many meaningful sentences that have never been uttered what accounts for the meaning of these unuttered sentences? 3. One line that seems open to Grice is to appeal to hypothetical intentions what a speaker would have intended by uttering such a sentence. 4. But there must be some constraints on these hypothetical intentions. Consider some sentence that has never (before now) been uttered: 57% of the armadillos in Texas prefer Wheaties to caviar. One hypothetical intention is that the hearer should believe that snow is white. Clearly that hypothetical intention has to be ruled out otherwise, our sentence could mean anything. 5. The problem is to say what would have been intended by an utterance of this sentence, but to do so without appealing to the meanings of the words it contains. For to do that would be circular. As Platt says: Generally, the constraint upon the hypothetical intentions with which a sentence can be uttered is precisely the meaning of the sentence. If this is correct, the attempt to define the meanings of unuttered sentences in terms of hypothetical intentions and responses is hopeless: for it presupposes a prior notion of sentence-meaning. 6. Notice that although natural languages contain infinitely many meaningful sentences, they contain only finitely many words. It is for this reason that Fregean (and truth-conditional) accounts of meaning are not bothered by the infinity of meaningful sentences objection. They can handle this by means of the compositionality of meaning. (Cf. a Fregean account of the meaning of our example above.) Can a Gricean come up with a counterpart principle of compositionality? 7

CONCLUSION 7. Consider the case of the meanings of predicates and proper names. What are the intentions associated with them? They cannot be propositional attitudes. That is, the intention associated with the sentence Brutus slew Caesar is the intention that the hearer should believe that Brutus slew Caesar. But what is the intention associated with Brutus and slew and Caesar? The only plausible candidates are, e.g., the intention to use Brutus to refer to Brutus, etc. But then we face the circularity problem: we are appealing to the semantic properties of a linguistic expression to spell out the intention with which speakers utter it. An examination of Grice s account of meaning NN will reveal that very little weight is placed on the role of the words the speaker uses. That is, on Grice s account, a speaker, in uttering x, might very well mean NN something (i.e., reflexively intend to communicate something) that goes well beyond what anyone might think is meant by the words that constitute x. The result is that the account of meaning NN so far provided does not distinguish between what a speaker (literally) says from what else he may succeed in conveying by means of some utterance. Making out that distinction becomes the burden of Grice s theory of conversational implicature, to which we will turn next. 8