ST ANSELM S VERSION OF THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT Anselm s argument relies on conceivability :

Similar documents
Plato gives another argument for this claiming, relating to the nature of knowledge, which we will return to in the next section.

Kant s deontological ethics

Last time we had arrived at the following provisional interpretation of Aquinas second way:

Descartes Meditations. ? God exists I exist (as a thinking thing)

Gödel s Ontological Proof of the Existence of God

Existence Is Not a Predicate by Immanuel Kant

1/9. Locke 1: Critique of Innate Ideas

Philosophical argument

Reality in the Eyes of Descartes and Berkeley. By: Nada Shokry 5/21/2013 AUC - Philosophy

Kant on Time. Diana Mertz Hsieh Kant (Phil 5010, Hanna) 28 September 2004

Divine command theory

Some key arguments from Meditations III-V

The Slate Is Not Empty: Descartes and Locke on Innate Ideas

The Refutation of Relativism

NECESSARY AND SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS

One natural response would be to cite evidence of past mornings, and give something like the following argument:

You will by now not be surprised that a version of the teleological argument can be found in the writings of Thomas Aquinas.

How To Understand The Moral Code Of A God (For Men)

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Phil 420: Metaphysics Spring [Handout 4] Hilary Putnam: Why There Isn t A Ready-Made World

Cosmological Arguments for the Existence of God S. Clarke

ON EXTERNAL OBJECTS By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

Quine on truth by convention

ON WHITCOMB S GROUNDING ARGUMENT FOR ATHEISM Joshua Rasmussen Andrew Cullison Daniel Howard-Snyder

Version 1.0. General Certificate of Education June Religious Studies Philosophy of Religion A2 Unit 3B. Final. Mark Scheme

Course Syllabus Department of Philosophy and Religion Skidmore College. PH 101: Introduction to Philosophy TUTH 3:40-5:30 Spring, 2011

The Meta-Problem of Change

LEGAL POSITIVISM vs. NATURAL LAW THEORY

Social & Political Philosophy. Karl Marx ( ) Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844

The Problem of Evil not If God exists, she'd be OOG. If an OOG being exists, there would be no evil. God exists.

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican, Hertford College. Lecture 3: Induction

Skepticism about the external world & the problem of other minds

A Short Course in Logic Example 8

CHAPTER 7 ARGUMENTS WITH DEFIITIONAL AND MISSING PREMISES

Chapter 5: Fallacies. 23 February 2015

Writing Thesis Defense Papers

In Defense of Kantian Moral Theory Nader Shoaibi University of California, Berkeley

Critical analysis. Be more critical! More analysis needed! That s what my tutors say about my essays. I m not really sure what they mean.

1 Must the universe have a cause?

Invalidity in Predicate Logic

Title: Duty Derives from Telos: The Teleology behind Kant s Categorical Imperative. Author: Micah Tillman

Kant, in an unusually non-technical way, defines happiness as getting

Argument for a Distinction Between the Mind/Soul and the Body. This is a prose summary of the diagrammed argument on the previous page:

GCE Religious Studies Explanation of Terms Unit 1D: Religion, Philosophy and Science

Last May, philosopher Thomas Nagel reviewed a book by Michael Sandel titled

Could I Have Been a Turnip? A Very Short Introduction to the Philosophy of Modality

3. Mathematical Induction

How to Get Your Prayers Answered By Dr. Roger Sapp

Primary and Secondary Qualities Charles Kaijo

Pascal is here expressing a kind of skepticism about the ability of human reason to deliver an answer to this question.

INTELLECTUAL APPROACHES

MILL. The principle of utility determines the rightness of acts (or rules of action?) by their effect on the total happiness.

Argument Mapping 2: Claims and Reasons

How to Get Your Prayers Answered. By Dr. Roger Sapp

P1. All of the students will understand validity P2. You are one of the students C. You will understand validity

Responding to Arguments against the Existence of God Based on Evil

The Cosmological Argument for the Existence of God Gerry J Hughes

EPISTEMOLOGY. PHILOSOPHY FOR AS.indb 23 16/07/ :10

Christian Doctrines about Life after Death

THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT FOR THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

WRITING PROOFS. Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology

Sartre and Freedom. Leo Franchi. Human freedom is undoubtedly one of the most fundamental ideas that has driven the

A LETTER OF INTENT IS ENFORCEABLE. A LETTER OF INTENT IS NOT ENFORCEABLE. Ira Meislik i

Self-Acceptance. A Frog Thing by E. Drachman (2005) California: Kidwick Books LLC. ISBN Grade Level: Third grade

Omnipotence and necessary moral perfection: are they compatible?

Evaluate yourself. Do you feel that you are spiritually mature? Why or Why not?

Kant and Aquinas on the Grounds of Moral Necessity

Same-Sex Marriage: Breeding Ground for Logical Fallacies

Introduction. Hegel s Trinitarian Claim

A Short Course in Logic Zeno s Paradox

Reading Questions for Phil , Spring 2012 (Daniel)

How does the problem of relativity relate to Thomas Kuhn s concept of paradigm?

Inductive Reasoning Page 1 of 7. Inductive Reasoning

Critical Study David Benatar. Better Never To Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006)

ONLINE SAFETY TEACHER S GUIDE:

Practical Jealousy Management

Course Proposal: PHI 1000G Introduction to Philosophy

WRITING A CRITICAL ARTICLE REVIEW

GOD S BIG STORY Week 1: Creation God Saw That It Was Good 1. LEADER PREPARATION

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals

On the Paradox of the Question

E-LOGOS/2006 ISSN

DIVINE TEMPORALITY AND CREATION EX NIHILO

Comfort for Troubled Hearts John 14:1-7

RENE DESCARTES MEDITATIONS ON FIRST PHILOSOPHY A summary by Torrey Wang. Meditation One: Concerning those things that can be called into doubt

Live for the Glory of God

MOST FREQUENTLY ASKED INTERVIEW QUESTIONS. 1. Why don t you tell me about yourself? 2. Why should I hire you?

Kant s Dialectic. Lecture 3 The Soul, part II John Filling jf582@cam.ac.uk

Am I An Atheist Or An Agnostic?

UNDERSTANDING OTHER RELIGIONS Week 3: Islam 1. LEADER PREPARATION

The last three chapters introduced three major proof techniques: direct,

FOUNDATIONS OF THE METAPHYSICS OF MORALS (SELECTION)

Picture yourself in a meeting. Suppose there are a dozen people

God, the Great Creator

Live by Faith. A Disciple s Response to God s Word

BBC Learning English Funky Phrasals Dating

A Few Basics of Probability

The Essential Elements of Writing a Romance Novel

TRINITY EVANGELICAL DIVINITY SCHOOL THE GOAL OF MISSIONS: HUMANIZATION OR SALVATION?

What are you. worried about? Looking Deeper

Transcription:

Michael Lacewing The ontological argument St Anselm and Descartes both famously presented an ontological argument for the existence of God. (The word ontological comes from ontology, the study of (-ology) of what exists or being (ont).) Their versions of the argument are slightly different, but they both argue that we can deduce the existence of God from the idea of God. Just from thinking about what God is, we can conclude that God must exist. Because it doesn t depend on experience in any way, the ontological argument is a priori. ST ANSELM S VERSION OF THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT Anselm s argument relies on conceivability : 1. By definition, God is a being greater than which cannot be conceived. 2. I can conceive of such a being. 3. It is greater to exist than not to exist. 4. Therefore, God must exist. The idea of God as the most perfect possible being has a long history. And perfection has also been connected to reality: what is perfect is more real than what is not. Anselm s argument makes use of both these ideas. Anselm starts from a definition of God if we could think of something that was greater than the being we called God, then surely this greater thing would in fact be God. But this is nonsense God being greater than God. The first being isn t God at all. We cannot conceive of anything being greater than God if we think we can, we re not thinking of God. The second premise says that this idea a being greater than which we cannot conceive is coherent. Now, if we think of two beings, one that exists and one that doesn t, the one that actually exists is greater being real is greater than being fictional! So if God didn t exist, we could think of a greater being than God. But we ve said that s impossible; so God exists. OBJECTIONS Gaunilo and the perfect island Anselm received an immediate reply from a monk named Gaunilo: you could prove anything perfect must exist by this argument! I can conceive of the perfect island, greater than which cannot be conceived. And so such an island must exist, because it would be less great if it didn t. But this is ridiculous, so the ontological argument must be flawed. You can t infer the existence of something, Gaunilo argues, from the idea of its being perfect. Anselm replied that the ontological argument works only for God, because the relation between God and greatness or perfection is unique. An island wouldn t cease to be what

it is an island if it wasn t perfect; of course, it wouldn t then be a perfect island. But islands aren t perfect by definition; perfection is something an island can have or not have. It is an accidental not an essential property of islands. It s perfectly coherent to think of an island that isn t perfect. (An essential property is one that something must have to be the thing that it is. Islands must be areas of land surrounded by water. Can we say that perfect islands are islands that are essentially perfect? Not convincingly, because perfect islands aren t a different kind of thing from islands, but a type of island. So they are still only essentially islands, and accidentally perfect.) By contrast, God, argues Anselm, must be the greatest conceivable being God wouldn t be God if there was some being even greater than God it s incoherent to think of God as imperfect. Being the greatest conceivable being is an essential property of God. But then because it is better to exist than not, existence is an essential property of God. So to be the greatest conceivable being, God must exist. Hume on necessary existence Notice that this conclusion is more than God does exist ; it claims God must exist God s existence is necessary. That isn t true of you or me or islands we can exist or not, we come into existence and cease to exist. Our existence is contingent. (The existence of a being is contingent if it could be true or false that that being exists, e.g. it could now exist, but later cease to exist. The existence of a being is necessary if it cannot come into or go out of existence; it is necessarily true that it exists (or doesn t).) The ontological argument only works for God, says Anselm, because only God s existence could be necessary. Hume argued that the idea of necessary existence was meaningless (Dialogues on Natural Religion, IX). To understand his claim, we need to understand what Hume thought about knowledge. Hume argues that we can have knowledge of just two sorts of thing: the relations between ideas and matters of fact (Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, IV) His distinction was developed by later philosophers, and is now understood in terms two distinctions: analytic/synthetic and a priori/a posteriori. Matters of fact we establish through sense experience, and are a matter of evidence and probability. The ontological argument doesn t rely on sense experience, but on pure reasoning. So the argument, and its conclusion that God exists, are a priori. But the only claims that can be known a priori are relations of ideas. These are demonstrable, i.e. provable, not a matter of probability, but certain. Take the claim all vixens are female. What is a vixen? By definition, it is a female fox. So all vixens are female means all female foxes are female. To deny this is to contradict oneself; if not all female foxes are female, then some female foxes are not female. But how can a female fox not be female?! If God exists is a priori, then we shouldn t be able to deny it without contradicting ourselves: Nothing is demonstrable, unless the contrary is a contradiction, Hume says. But, he goes on, Whatever we conceive as existent, we can also conceive as non-existent. There is no being, therefore, whose non-existence implies a contradiction. Consequently there is no Being whose existence is demonstrable.

So Hume argues that God does not possess existence essentially it is possible to conceive of God not existing (and still be thinking of God). So God does not exist necessarily. And so the ontological argument for God s existence fails. However, Hume assumes that all demonstrable truths must be analytic. Rationalists would argue that there are synthetic a priori truths that are demonstrable as well, and the claim that God exists could be one of these. DESCARTES AND PERFECTION We saw St Anselm s version of the ontological argument relied on the inconceivability of anything greater than God. Descartes version of the argument relies on perfection alone, not conceivability: It is certain that I find the idea of a God in my consciousness, that is the idea of a being supremely perfect: and I know with clearness and distinctness that an [actual and] eternal existence pertains to his nature existence can no more be separated from the essence of God, than the idea of a mountain from that of a valley it is not less impossible to conceive a God, that is, a being supremely perfect, to whom existence is wanting, or who is devoid of a certain perfection, than to conceive a mountain without a valley. (Meditation V) Descartes argument is this: 1. I have the idea of God; 2. God is a supremely perfect being; 3. Existence is a perfection; 4. Therefore, God must exist. Development We can object that there is a gap between the idea that God exists eternally and God actually existing eternally. Descartes is aware of this, and objects to himself: just as it does not follow that there is any mountain in the world merely because I conceive a mountain with a valley, so likewise, though I conceive God as existing, it does not seem to follow on that account that God exists. But, he replies, the cases are not analogous it does not follow that there is any mountain or valley in existence, but simply that the mountain or valley, whether they do or do not exist, are inseparable from each other; whereas, on the other hand, because I cannot conceive God unless as existing, it follows that existence is inseparable from him, and therefore that he really exists. Descartes is arguing that the analogy is not between mountains and existence and God and existence; but between mountains and valleys and God and existence. The idea of existence is no part of the idea of a mountain. But just as the idea of a valley is implied by the idea of a mountain, so the idea of existence is part of the idea of God. And so, as he says, I can t think of God without thinking that God exists. But what does this show? Just because I can t think of God not existing, does that have any relevance to whether or not God exists? Absolutely. The bounds of our thought are,

at least on some occasions, indications of what is possible. This isn t because our thought creates or influences reality, but because thought reveals reality. And so, Descartes argues, the necessary connection between God and existence isn t something I ve come up with, it is something I discover: the necessity which lies in the thing itself, that is, the necessity of the existence of God, determines me to think in this way: for it is not in my power to conceive a God without existence. There is a conceptual connection between the concept of God and God s existence, and this entails that God s must exist. OBJECTIONS TO DESCARTES Gassendi objects that existence is not part of the idea of God as a supremely perfect being. Can t I form the idea of a God who does not exist? (This is similar to Hume s objection.) Descartes replies by drawing claiming, with St Thomas Aquinas, that divine perfections all entail each other. Because our minds are finite, we normally think of the divine perfections omnipotence, omniscience, necessary existence, etc. separately and hence may not immediately notice the necessity of their being joined together. But if we reflect carefully, we shall discover that we cannot conceive any one of the other attributes while excluding necessary existence from it. For example, in order for God to be omnipotent, God must not depend on anything else, and so must not depend on anything else to exist. However, Aquinas didn t think that existence is a perfection. He objects, and Johannes Caterus put the point to Descartes, that the ontological argument doesn t demonstrate that God really exists. It only shows that the concept of existence is inseparable from the concept of God. Descartes argument is only convincing for the claim that if God exists, God exists necessarily. Descartes accepts that what he has shown is that necessary existence is part of the concept of God. But this, he responds, is enough: necessary existence entails actual existence. That God must exist to be God means that God exists. But Caterus says this isn t enough: the question is whether the concept of necessary existence entails actual existence. KANT Everyone now agrees the problem lies with Descartes premise (3). What is a perfection? It s a property that it is better to have than not have. So is existence this kind of property? Descartes and Anselm are supposing that it is that something that has existence is greater than something that doesn t. Immanuel Kant developed the objection to this claim (Critique of Pure Reason, Book II, Ch. 3, 4). Things don t have existence in the same way that they have other properties. Consider whether God exists is an analytic or synthetic judgment. According to Descartes, it must be analytic: his argument is that God does not exist is a contradiction in terms, for the concept God contains the idea of existence (necessary existence belongs to God s essence). But, Kant claims, this is a mistake. Existence does not add anything to, or define, a concept itself; to say something exists is to say that

some object corresponds to the concept. To say something exists is always a synthetic judgment, not an analytic one. When we list the essential properties of something, we describe our concept of that thing. For instance, a dog is a mammal. But now if I tell you that the dog asleep in the corner is a mammal and it exists, I seem to have said two very different sorts of things. To say that it exists is only to say that there is something real that corresponds to the concept dog. It is not to say anything about the dog as a dog. Existence, Kant argues, is not part of any concept, even in the case of God. To say that God exists is quite different from saying that God is omnipotent. So it is not true to say that God exists must be true. NECESSARY EXISTENCE If existence isn t a property that something has, then it can t be a property that God has necessarily! And yet it seems plausible to think that if God exists, God exists necessarily. God cannot be a contingent being. If God s existence were not necessary, God would depend on something else that could cause God to come into or go out of existence. If Kant were right, then not only can existence not be a property, necessary existence as a type of existence can t be a property. So God can t exist necessarily, even if God exists. In fact, this doesn t follow. There is still a sense in which God can exist necessarily, if God exists. Rather than saying God has necessary existence, which suggests existence is a property, we should say that it is necessarily true that God exists. The necessity applies to the claim: God exists must be true. Of course, we need an argument to support the claim, but at least it makes sense. The ontological argument seems to say that because, according to the concept of God, God exists necessarily, that is not contingently, without dependence on anything else, then God exists must be true. But this doesn t follow; it confuses two meanings of necessarily.