Size: px
Start display at page:

Download ""

Transcription

1 1 Resource Sensitivity in the Syntax-Semantics Interface and the German Split NP Construction Jonas Kuhn 1.1 Introduction The split NP (or split topicalization) construction of German (henceforth SNP) has received much attention in the literature, as a challenge for syntactic accounts of argument selection and of unbounded dependency constructions (Bayer 1987 van Riemsdijk 1989 Fanselow 1988 Fanselow 1993 Haider 1990 Hinrichs and Nakazawa 1994) and in the discussion of the semantic status of indenites (Diesing 1992 van Geenhoven 1996). 1 In this construction, the descriptive material about one underlying argument is not conned to a single NP as normal, but is spread over two nominal constituents: (1.1) B cher sieht Anna drei books sees Anna three `As for books, Anna can see three.' In terms of morphological marking of declension class (and similarly determiner selection), the two constituents behave like autonomous complete NPs (cf. the form of kein in (1.2a) vs. in (1.2b)), i.e., the lower NP, appearing in the German Mittelfeld, has the same form as elliptical NPs (1.2c). 1 I'd like to thank Judith Berman, Miriam Butt, Mary Dalrymple, Stefanie Dipper, Martin Emele, Christian Fortmann, Anette Frank, John Fry, Christian Rohrer, three anonymous reviewers and the audience at the ESSLLI 98 workshop in Saarbr cken for comments and discussion. Parts of this chapter (1.2, 1.3.1, 1.3.3, and 1.5) are revised sections of (Kuhn to appear). 1

2 2 / Jonas Kuhn (1.2) (van Riemsdijk 1989, p. 109, ex. (11)) a. Ein Schwimmbad hat er sich noch keins/*kein gebaut. a pool has he refl yet none/no built `As for a swimming pool, he hasn't yet built one.' b. Er hat sich noch*keins/kein Schwimmbad gebaut. `He hasn't yet built a swimming pool.' c. Er hat sich nochkeins gebaut. `He hasn't yet built one.' The SNP construction constitutes a problem in view of the widely assumed grammatical principle that the syntactic complement phrases of a head stand in a one-to-one correspondence to argument slots in an underlying conceptual representationformulated e.g. as the Theta Criterion of Government-and-Binding Theory (GB) and as Biuniqueness within LFG. In SNP apparently two NPs can realize a single underlying argument. 2 In previous accounts, dierent strategies have been pursued to avoid the problem, keeping up the Theta Criterion: van Riemsdijk (1989) argues for a movement accountthe NP in the topic position is a preposed part of the remnant NP in the Mittelfeld. The unexpected morphological autonomy of the two NPs is explained by positing that under certain circumstances, non-maximal projections that have been moved can regenerate some amount of structure to meet X-bar requirements applying at S-structure. Fanselow (1988) and Haider (1990) analyze both NPs as base-generated, but only the one in the Mittelfeld as an argument NP bearing a theta role the other phrase is a nonargument (semantically a predicate), further restricting the Mittelfeld NP through some mechanism of coindexation. Being a non-argument, it moves to the topic position. Van Geenhoven (1996) assumes both parts of SNP to be base-generated in the Mittelfeld as indenites of the semantic type of a property the referent that they restrict and that lls the argument slot is provided lexically by the verb, i.e., the NPs are semantically incorporated. Hinrichs and Nakazawa (1994) propose an analysis in Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar (HPSG), positing a construction-specic lexical rule. I'd like to argue that these accounts make unnecessary assumptions of some extra devices to deal with SNP and/or fail to explain the striking 2 Jackendo (1990, sec. 3.1) discusses two ways in which the Theta Criterion is empirically inadequate: (i) there are cases where an NP has more than one theta-role, and (ii) there are cases where multiple NPs hold a single theta-role. The English examples he cites for the latter case, referring to (Gruber 1965) and to talks by Richard Carter (1984), include The box has books in it and Bill carried some books with him. In the further discussion however, Jackendo says little more about the (ii) cases.

3 Resource Sensitivity and the Split NP Construction / 3 parallelism of the Mittelfeld NP and elliptical NPs. The recent version of Lexical-Functional Grammar (LFG) with a resource sensitive (linear logic-based) approach to semantic composition (cf. Dalrymple, Lamping, Pereira, and Saraswat 1997, henceforth DLPS97) provides the basis for an explanatory account without stipulation of construction-specic devices. In the semantic analysis of SNP, I assume that the Mittelfeld NP behaves like an elliptical NPs in that it picks up anaphorically the propertyintroduced by the topic NP. 3 Largely independent of the anaphorical relationship at the level of semantics, the two NPs behave as follows at the syntactic levels: at functional (f-)structure, both NPs are mapped to the same grammatical function (thus, one can speak of a unication analysis), contributing to the same argument slot in the underlying representation of the main predicate whereas locally at constituent (c-) structure, each of the NPs 4 has to independently satisfy constraints on determiner selection etc. The main objective of this paper is to motivate this particular division of labour in the architecture of grammar, assuming dierent formal devices to model the constraints on dierent structural levels. This methodology is fully in the LFG tradition, as well as central aspects of the unication analysis are. In a few details however, I'll argue either for modications of standard LFG assumptions containing redundancy, or for (conservative) extensions of an existing theory to cover a new type of data. In arguing for the division of labour, I will address resource-(in-)sensitivity of argument selection at the various structural levels. It should be noted that for the architectural point that I'd like to make, only certain aspects of each level are relevant. Iwillpoint out which aspects I think these are, and also whyitake other aspects to be orthogonal. The presentation of these orthogonal aspects follows practical considerations of simplicity rather than high standards of theoretical depth. In sec. 1.2, I give anoverview of the main empirical data discussed in the literature. Sec. 1.3 addresses the syntactic unication account in the LFG setting, and its implications for the character of the syntactic constraints. After briey introducing linear logic-based LFG semantics, sec. 1.4 presents the approach to semantic construction in SNP. Having presented myown account, I will discuss the mentioned approaches from the literature in some more detail (sec. 1.5), before concluding in sec Following (van Geenhoven 1996) I assume that under particular circumstances of semantic incorporation, indenites can denote just a property. 4 For simplicity, I will be using the label NP to refer to a maximal nominal projection, whenever internal details are irrelevant as will become clear in sec , the label DP would be more precise technically.

4 4 / Jonas Kuhn 1.2 Properties of the Split NP construction In addition to the morphological autonomy of the nominal projections involved in SNP, discussed already in the introduction, the following properties have been observed (for an extensive discussion, see van Riemsdijk 1989 this section is entirely based on his data): Determiner selection. Each of the two NPs has to locally satsify restrictions on determiner selection, i.e., a singular count noun is illformed without a determiner (1.3). (1.3) *(einen) neuen Wagen kann er sich noch keinen leisten a.acc new.acc car can he re yet none.acc aord `As for a new car, he can't aord one yet.' Agreement. The two NPs agree in number (and case and gender): Other than in the `as for... ' paraphrase in English, the SNP construction is ungrammatical when a mismatch in number occurs (1.4). (1.4) Ein Buch/*B cher ist erst eins von ihm erschienen a book/books has only one by him appeared `As for books, only one by him has appeared yet.' Indeniteness. The topic NP must be non-quanticational (cf. the ungrammatical manche `some' in (1.5)). Some dialects allow only a bare plural (like in (1.1)), others alternatively allow a singular indenite (cf. (1.4)). (1.5) (*Manche) some H user houses habe ich auch noch kleinere gesehen. have I also even smaller (ones) seen. Topic position. Other than in the oating quantier construction (1.6a), the higher NP in SNP is structurally conned to the (preverbal) topic position: (1.6b) is infelicitous. 5 (1.6) a. Er hat die Zigaretten gestern alle vier geraucht. he has the cigarettes yesterday all four smoked `Yesterday, he has smoked all four cigarettes.' b. *Er he hat has einen a Wagen sich car refl noch never nie before einen one leisten aord k nnen. been-able-to 5 Van Geenhoven (1996, p. 24, fn. 5) points out that example (i) (attributed to Fanselow, p.c.) shows that verb-nal (embedded) clauses may also contain SNP (note however that in this sentence, B cher needs to be pronounced with the prosodic characteristics of a topic: a rising pitch accent). (i)...weil...because man one B cher books damals then in to den the Osten East keine none mitbringen bring durfte was-allowed-to `because in the past it was not allowed to take books to East Germany. '

5 Resource Sensitivity and the Split NP Construction / 5 Headless remnant. The NP in the Mittelfeld may not contain an overt nominal head (1.7). 6 (1.7) *B cher books hat er noch keine Romane geschrieben. has he yet no novels written. Unbounded dependency. The standard diagnostics for an unbounded dependency construction apply (for instance, extraction out of a whclause is impossible: (1.8b)). (1.8) a. Unbesch digte undamaged auf in Vorrat stock habe. have b. *Unbesch digte undamaged Vorrat stock hat. has Exemplare copies glaube ich, da ich nur noch zwei believe I, that I only still two Exemplare wollte er wissen, wer noch zwei auf copies wanted he to-know who still two in VP topicalization. SNP can be part of (partial) VP topicalization: In (1.9), the (usually sentence-nal) participle appears in topicalized position, together with an indenite argument NP, and another NP realizing the same argument slot is left in the Mittelfeld. 7 (1.9) [Einen a Wagen gekauft] hat er sich noch car bought has he refl yet `As for cars, he has not yet bought one.' keinen. none 6 Fanselow (1993, 63) cites (i) (attributed to Santorini, p.c.) as a counterexample to this. To me, examples of this type are marginal, and I'd propose that their acceptability is due to a performance strategy dealing with duplication eects (cf. also fn. 35 below). (i) Raubv gel glaube ich kennt Gereon nur Bussarde. birds-of-prey believe I knows Gereon only buzzards `As for birds of prey, I believe that Gereon knows only buzzards.' 7 A further property van Riemsdijk (1989) discusses is the fact that restrictions on the serialization of multiple adjectives bear over to the split NP situation suggesting that the topic NP has to be reinserted into the remnant NP for checking this condition (examples (i)-(ii)). However, since very little is known about the formal character of this restriction, it is not unlikely that it applies on a more semantic level of representation, not requiring that there be some congurational level with a single unsplit NP. (i) a. ein neues amerikanisches Auto `a new American car' b. * ein amerikanisches neues Auto (ii) a. Ein amerikanisches Auto kann ich mir kein neues leisten. `As for an American car, I cannot aord a new one.' b. * Ein neues Auto kann ich mir kein amerikanisches leisten.

6 6 / Jonas Kuhn 1.3 Syntactic Analysis The architecture of LFG with its system of correspondence between parallel structuresconstituent (c-)structure, functional (f-)structure, argument (a-)structure and semantic structureturns out to provide the means for an explanatory analysis of the SNP construction that need not stipulate any construction-specic mechanisms. In subsection 1.3.1, I will present the core idea of the syntactic analysis, which centers on the mapping from c-structure to f-structure. This analysis has some implications for the character of c-structure and f- structure one has to assume. In the subsections and 1.3.3, I will address these issues and argue that the specic assumptions are fully compatible with independently developed recent LFG theories Unication in mapping from c-structure to f-structure The starting point for my analysis is the observation that on a low level, both parts of the SNP behave like autonomous NPs: the topic part has to satisfy standard requirements for determiner selection (singular mass nouns can stand without a determiner, while count nouns can't) the Mittelfeld NP surfaces exactly like an elliptical NP both parts must independently meet constraints on declension class. 8 This behaviour is precisely predicted under two independently established assumptions about the mapping from c-structure to f-structure: (1.10) In German, the same grammatical function can be assigned in different c-structure positions. (1.11) Under certain circumstances, more than one c-structure constituent can simultaneously contribute to the same grammatical function. Assumption (1.11) underlies, e.g., the unication analysis of clitic doubling by Andrews (1990). The conditions for compatibility in SNP will be discussed in detail in sec below. In the following, I will motivate assumption (1.10) and illustrate the basic SNP analysis. According to LFG theory, in a case-marking language like German the functional annotations in c-structure rules are underspecied as to the exact grammatical function (e.g., subj or obj) an NP bears not the congurational position, but case and agreement principles are decisive for function specication (cf. e.g., Bresnan 1996, 17 Bresnan 1995, ch. 5 Bresnan 1998 Berman 1998). Thus, on the basis of c-structure rules and case principles, an NP bearing a particular function (say, obj) can occur in dierent congurational positionse.g., in the Mittelfeld or in the preverbal position. Moreover, since the annotations are conned to 8 I will come back to the question which type of constraints regulate these NP-local restrictions in sec

7 Resource Sensitivity and the Split NP Construction / 7 local trees, nothing prevents the simultaneous occurrence of obj NPs in both these positions (provided their f-structures are compatible). The general mechanism of functional specication just laid out can be eshed out in dierent ways, the details of which are orthogonal to the matter of this chapter. One way to think of the case and agreement principles is as some kind of meta-constraints on the f-annotations of c-structure rules, like for example the functional specication for subj stated informally in (1.12) (cf. Bresnan 1995, ch. 5). (1.12) NP: (#case)=nom ^ ("subj agr)=(#agr) ) ("subj)=# Principle (1.12) says that if an NP is morphologically marked as nominative and agrees with the verb under which it is f-structurally embedded, then the grammatical function it bears is subj. Another possibility would be to follow Nordlinger's (1997) constructive case approach, according to which in languages with morphologically controlled functional specication, the case morphology comes with an inside-out designator (e.g., (obj ") for accusative case) specifying under which grammatical function the marked NP mustbeembedded. To avoid unneccessary complications in the following, I will present fully specied functional annotations in the c-structure trees, above the category symbols. If one assumes one of the mentioned generalized accounts, these annotations should not be seen as rule-specic stipulations, but the result of applying general morphological principles to underspeci- ed annotations (which again follow from an X-bar based general scheme of rule annotation, cf. (Bresnan 1995, ch. 5)). The general idea of the unication-based SNP analysis is illustrated by the simplied c-structure and f-structure analysis of (1.13) given in g (1.13) Einen Frosch sah er einen kleinen. a.acc frog saw he.nom a.acc small.acc `As for frogs, he could see a small one.' The NP nodes for einen Frosch and einen kleinen are both mapped to the same f-structure, as the obj of the verb sehen. 10 C-structurally, both NPs are treated as autonomous canonical NPs, under independent application of local constraints on determiner selection and morpholog- 9 The arrows (" and #) in the functional annotations (which interact to constrain the construction of the f-structure) are metavariables " refers to the f-structure projected from the mother node, # refers to the f-structure projected from the node itself. For more background information on the mechanisms of standard LFG, the reader is referred to the articles in (Dalrymple et al. 1995). 10 Since the merging of two constituents as a single underlying argument is captured by unication at the level of f-structure already, we can ignore the LFG level of argument (a-)structure in this study.

8 8 / Jonas Kuhn CP ("comp* obj)=# "=# NP C 0 H H einen Frosch "=# "=# C VP pred subj obj sah ("subj)=# ("obj)=# NP NP er `sehenhsubj obji' pred `er' 2 pred `Frosch' 4 spec adjuncts ein pred `klein' H H einen kleinen FIGURE 1 Unication analysis of (1.13) ical marking (declension class) to be discussed in sec Furthermore, the unbounded dependency behaviour of the construction is directly predicted, since the topic part is interrelated with its functional source by the same functional uncertainty equations (in g. 1, the optional comp* path for an embedded obj function) as in the standard case, where no Mittelfeld argument doubles its grammatical function. A relevant example would be (1.14), with f-structure analysis (1.15). (1.14) Einen Frosch glaube ich, da er einen kleinen sah. a.acc frog believe I that he.nom a.acc small.acc saw `As for frogs, I believe he could see a small one.' 2 pred `glaubenhsubj compi' 6 subj 6 pred 2 `ich' 6 pred `sehenhsubj obji' 6 (1.15) 6 6 subj 6 6 pred 2 `er' 6 6 comp 6 pred `Frosch' obj 4 spec ein adjuncts pred `klein' The unication analysis also carries over directly to the (partial) VP topicalization cases such as(1.9) like NPs, VPs can be introduced to the f-structure from dierent c-structure positions, provided their f-structures can be unied (i.e., if also f-structures embedded in their f-structuressay, under objcan be unied). So the SNP contained in (partial) VP topicalization is reduced to the same conditions as the stand-alone SNP

9 Resource Sensitivity and the Split NP Construction / Local categorial structure The above discussion of SNP assumed that the observed independence of the two NPs in terms of determiner selection and declension class can be captured at a local (i.e., pre-f-structure) level: if f-structure were involved to control, e.g., determiner selection, the unication account would predict that a single determiner could full the requirements of both NPsin one case locally, in the other case non-locally through uni- cation. The data contradict this prediction: (1.3) is ill-formed without a determiner. 11 This means that the classical LFG analysis of NPs, where the determiner and the noun simply map their contribution to the same f- structure and there is no more ne-grained distinction at the level of c-structure, has to be modied. However, taking into account more recent theories of c-structure regularities, the observed behaviour is not at all unexpected: Bresnan (1998, sec. 6.2) dispenses with the view of LFG category labels as simple, unanalyzed symbols, and introduces a feature system to classify category labels, drawing upon (and extending) concepts and ideas well-known from the generative literature: X-bar theory, lexical categorial features, the lexical/functional distinction. 12 The determiner and declension class requirements within NPs have often been regarded as intimately connected with conditions on functional completion of the lexical category NP as a DP (cf. e.g. in the constraint-based setting Netter's (1993) DP analysis in HPSG). One (Netter-style) way to put the requirement of a determiner with singular count nouns in the category format of recent LFG would be the following: (i) only functional projections (i.e., DPs) are allowed in argument position (e.g., with verbs) and (ii) singular count nouns are lexically 11 In certain dialects, examples like (i), with a determiner-less singular count noun, are reported to be acceptable (cf. Fanselow 1988, 103). (i) Hemd tr gt er keines. shirt wears he none `As for a shirt, he doesn't wear one.' However, to account for the standard German data, a local explanation is indispensable the (i) data on the other hand can just as well be explained in a local account: in these dialects, there is no strict syntactic requirement of a determiner, not even with singular count nouns. Thus, when the semantics doesn't make a determiner necessary (i.e., in cases where the singular indenite denotes a property, as I will argue below in sec. 1.4), we can nd a bare singular count noun. 12 Formally, such a categorial feature system can be captured by a GPSG-style multiplication of c-structure rules, since the values are atomic and the set of possible values is nite. The LFG implementation of the Xerox Linguistic Environment(XLE) provides this mechanism of complex category symbols, which has been used successfully for generalizations over rules in the Parallel Grammar Development project (Kuhn 1998).

10 10 / Jonas Kuhn marked as non-functional (whereas plurals and mass nouns are optionally marked as functionalor possibly underspecied). The eect is thatindependently of the question whether there are any other nominal projections contributing to the same grammatical function in the sentenceeach singular count noun has to go together with a determiner else, the analysis would fail already at the level of c-structure. 13 Note furthermore, that with this purely syntactic and very local account of determiner selection with singular count nouns, we expect there to be determiners even in situations where they wouldn't be required semantically. One situation where no determiner is semantically required is when an indenite NP is used to denote a mere property (without introducing and quantifying over a variable) as I will argue at length in sec. 1.4, the topic part of SNP is exactly such a property-denoting indenite. 14 And indeed we nd the indenite article ein(en) to be obligatory with singular count nouns in the topic NP of the SNP construction: example (1.3)which we can now explain as an eect of the local syntactic constraints just laid out. 15 This observation about the occurrence of the determiner ein is quite revealing about its semantic status. As we just saw, there is at least one usage in which ein occurs for purely syntactic reasons (as a default determiner), and is semantically empty. It is not strictly compelling to assume a second, semantic, version of ein to account for the use in existential NPs: bare plurals and mass nouns can have an existential reading without there being an overt determiner, so some other device has to be assumed anyway. Dynamic semantic theories such as Discourse Representation Theory (DRT Kamp and Reyle 1993) explain the existential interpretation indenites to be a discourse level eect rather than a lexical one. In the exposition of a linear logic-based semantics for SNP in sec. 1.4 below, I will nevertheless follow anestablished generalizedquantier analysis of the semantic variant of the indenite article to 13 Another way to express the pre-f-structure constraints, which is equally feasible for the present purposes, and which is also independently motivated, would be the assumption of a special projection level distinct from f-structure, projected locally from c-structure (cf. the so-called m(orphological)-structure of (Butt, Ni o, and Segond 1996 Butt, Fortmann, and Rohrer 1996)). 14 Another context where according to (Zimmermann 1993) we can nd propertydenoting NPs is as the (de dicto) object of intensional verbs like seek: (i) Hans Hans sucht seeks ein a Einhorn. unicorn 15 Note that using the plural in the topic NP instead, (which does not come with the syntactic requirement of a determiner) is no viable alternative, since the number feature does get projected to f-structure, and thus must unify with the partner NP in SNP (cf. example (1.4)).

11 Resource Sensitivity and the Split NP Construction / 11 avoid additional complications of this heavily formal section this forces me to assume an extra lexical entry for the syntactically triggered ein discussed in the present section. Consequently, as an example the two occurrences of ein(en) in (1.13) have to be analyzed as two dierent readings. A dynamic reconstruction of the account should be able to do with just a single entry for ein. Summing up this subsection on local syntactic constraints in SNP: Even though I could not go into much detail as to the exact c-structure constraints regulating local restrictions in German nominal projections, I hope the character of such constraints has become clear. For the overall picture that arises we can note that the SNP data support a division of labour between local c-structure constraints on the one hand, formulated using categorial features with a limited expressive power (they can be compiled out as a context-free grammar) and independent unication at f-structure on the other hand The role of pred values Coming back to f-structure, the general idea of the unication analysis outlined in sec is fairly straightforward. However, it remains to be shown that there are independent principles constraining the mechanism inaway that explains the data. 16 Given the mechanism of f-structure unicationwhy cannot simply any canoncial NP dissociate and spread its contribution to the sentence over various c-structure NPs? The constraints on morphological marking following from autonomy ofthenps at the level of c-structure do not explain the indeniteness and topichood restrictions observed in sec. 1.2 moreover the question arises whether assumption (1.11) from abovethat the f-structures of the two NPsin SNP unifyis tenable without an undermining of the key concepts regulating subcategorization in LFG. Classically, a central role of f-structure is to constrain the great freedom at c-structure (especially in non-congurational languagescf. assumption (1.10) above), by excluding that two canonical NPs are assigned the same grammatical function. This is achieved by functional uniqueness (which disallows two distinct appearences of the same grammatical function within a single f-structure), combined with the fact that the pred values of the NPs will fail to unify. Even if the pred values are of the same form, standard LFG interprets them as instantiated symbols, i.e., as semantically distinct from any other symbol (Kaplan and 16 It would be certainly possible to explicitly state restrictions on the rules that ensure the empirical generalizationsimilarly as in the lexical rule of (Hinrichs and Nakazawa 1994)but as will be shown, these restrictions follow from independent properties of the elements involved.

12 12 / Jonas Kuhn Bresnan 1995, 77). Doubling of a functionas in the ungrammatical example (1.16)is thus ruled out as shown in g. 2. (1.16) *den Peter sieht der Karl den Peter. the.acc Peter sees the.nom Karl the.acc Peter. ("...obj)=#... ("obj)=# NP NP DET N DET N ("pred)=`peter' 27 ("pred)=`peter' pred `sehenhsubj obji' subj pred `Karl' obj pred? 3 5 den Peter den Peter FIGURE 2 Eect of instantiated symbols (cf. (1.16)) It has been observed however (Andrews 1990) that to a limited degree, some languages allow for exceptions to this rule. While in French, the presence of an object clitic on the verb makes the appearence of a full NP with the same function impossible, Spanish does allow clitic doubling (1.17) (Andrews 1990, sec. 3.1). (1.17) Lo him vimos we saw a l. him `We sawhim.' Keeping up the standard pred mechanism, Andrews formally models the construction by making the introduction of the clitic's pred value optional. This has certainly the desired eect and is plausible as far as the instantiated symbol character of the pred value is concerned, but it seems somehow ad hoc to give an otherwise referential item the option of being semantically empty. My claim here is that the observations are due to more general principles of resource sensitivity in the syntax-semantics interface that become clearer when a more ne-grained view is taken on what standard LFG bundles up in the semantic forms under the pred feature. Already Dalrymple et al. (1995, 14) note that of the four types of information that semantic forms classically encoded, three 17 are now covered by new mechanisms like argument structure with linking theory, and the linear logic-based account of semantics. The only remaining type of information still encoded in the pred values, they argue, is instantiation to mark predicate uniqueness These are: specication of the semantic relation, mapping of grammatical functions to semantic roles, and subcategorization information (the governed grammatical functions). 18 In their analysis of complex predicate constructions, they assume that the light

13 Resource Sensitivity and the Split NP Construction / 13 As it turns out, even instantiation can be taken over by resource sensitivity in the linear logic-based account of semantics (see sec below). Thus, the pred feature can be removed entirely from the f- structure representation. This means that one can get a very clear-cut formal division in the architecture of grammar, with resource accounting exclusively on the semantic side, and feature unication (without any exceptional value types like the old pred values) for functional syntax Modelling resource sensitivity in Split NPs with pred values? Before going into the linear logic formalism in sec. 1.4, let us clarify the polarity of resource sensitivity in the SNP data. A consideration how this could be modelled with the classical pred values will give additional support for the revision. Contrary to the excluded doubling of canonical NPs as in (1.16), one of the NPs in the German SNP construction must resemble Spanish clitics in that it tolerates c-structurally distinct material contributing to the same grammatical function as itself. The following question will help to judge which part of the SNP has this nature: Can there be even more than two NPs, and if so, which ofthetwo NPtypes in SNP can be iterated? It turns out that it is the topic part of SNP the attempt to iterate the lower NP (which introduces and quanties over the variable/referent) leads to ungrammaticality (1.18), while in a context providing appropriate contrast, it is in fact possible to havetwo (property-denoting) topic parts (1.19): the NP politische, in the Mittelfeld, clearly bears the intonational marking of atopic(a rising pitch accent, cf. example (i) in fn. 5). (1.18) *Bilder haben wir welche im Museum einige gesehen. paintings have we some in-the museum several seen (1.19) B cher books durfte was-allowed man one politische political damals then in to den the Osten East keine none mitbringen. bring `Talking about booksas for political ones, one wasn't allowed to bring any toeastgermany.' If one wanted to capture this behaviour within the standard account of pred values, one way would be to have the topic NP introduce its contribution under an embedded set-valued feature like adjuncts,while the Mittelfeld NP, although noun-less, introduces an ordinary (pronominal) pred value. (1.21) sketches this analysis for (1.20). verb diyaa `permit' (in Urdu) lacks a pred value, and can thus unify f-structurally with a full verb to form a complex predicate.

14 14 / Jonas Kuhn (1.20) Fr sche sieht Karl kleine. frogs sees Karl small `As for frogs, Karl can see small ones.' (1.21) Fr sche: ("...obj adjuncts 3 pred) =`Frosch' kleine: ("obj pred) =`pro' ("obj adjuncts 3 pred) = `klein' 2 pred `sehenhsubj obji' 6 4 subj pred 2 pred 4 adjuncts `Karl' `pro' 3 5 obj pred `Frosch' pred `klein' Due to the (instantiated) pred value it introduces (here called `pro', quite arbitrarily), the Mittelfeld NP cannot be repeated, whereas there could be more of the adjunct-introducing topic NPs. Note that this way of enforcing the right restrictions with the standard pred mechanism leads to a picture that is almost the opposite of the naive way ofputting the pred's together, shown in g. 1. The confusion is caused by the dierent rolespred's play, which diverge in the SNP construction. This brief consideration should be enough to motivate a formally separated approach to the resource-sensitive aspects in the SNP construction The Syntax-Semantics Interface This section contains a fair amount of formalism however, the general ideas should become clear even if one doesn't follow the linear logic derivation in every detail Linear logic-based semantic construction In the introduction, a close parallel between the Mittelfeld NP of the SNP construction and elliptical NPs has been observed. Based on the c- and f-structural analysis from the previous section, I will argue here that underlying both NP usages is a common anaphoric behaviour requiring an antecedent of the semantic type of a property (Fanselow 1988, 105 van Geenhoven 1996). Again, the formal modelling relies mainly on established assumptions, in this case from the linear logic-based framework of semantic construction within LFG, established by Dalrymple and colleagues in a series of papers (among others Dalrymple et al Dalrymple et al. 1995, DLPS97). This approach builds on LFG's projection architecture, assuming a level of semantic representation, projected from 19 See (Kuhn to appear) for more discussion. A similar set of issues is also discussed in (Berman, Dipper, Fortmann, and Kuhn 1998), for the empirical domain of the correlative pronouns co-occurring with nite argument clauses

15 Resource Sensitivity and the Split NP Construction / 15 f-structure, that is associated with a meaning. Meaning association is expressed by the predicate symbol. Constraints on the meaning associated with a semantic structure are called meaning constructors and are expressed in the lexical entries, like intheentry (1.22) for the proper name Anna. 20 (1.22) Anna NP ("pred) = `Anna' " Anna The central insight of the linear logic approach is that the semantic contribution of lexical items can be viewed as resources that are being subsequently consumed, as the meaning for larger expressions is built up. At the end of a successful derivation, all resources will be used up and only the meaning for the entire sentence will be left, which has to be of type t. This intuition cannot be modelled by a derivation in classical logic, since there, a premise may be used arbitrarily many times in a derivation. Linear logic, with its connectives (multiplicative conjunction) and ( (linear implication), captures the resource consciousness of natural language semantics: deducing B from A (A ( B) by modus ponens will consume A i.e., A B is not derivable from just this formula. The meaning constructors for transitive verbs like sieht `sees' make use of these connectives: 21 (1.23) sieht NP ("pred) = `sehen' 8X Y:(" subj) X (" obj) Y (" sehen (X Y ) The logic language containing both meaning associations and linear logic expressions that control their processing is called the glue language. (1.24) (weil) Anna Otto sieht because Anna Otto sees Now, the linear logic derivation of a sentence like `Anna sees Otto' (1.24) starts out with a c-, f- and semantic structure analysis, as given in g. 3, with arrows illustrating the projection functions. The premises for the linear logic derivation originating from the lexical entries are given 20 Entry (1.22) has the following eects: (i) it introduces the string Anna under the c-structure category NP, (ii)it introduces the feature pred with value `Anna' in the f-structure projected from the NP node (referred to by the metavariable "), and (iii) it associates the semantic structure projected from that f-structure (which is mathematically the result of applying the projection function to the f-structure that " refers to) with the meaning language constant Anna. 21 Intuitively, the meaning constructor in this entry says: for any meaning language terms X and Y,suchthat("subj) the semantic structure projected from the value of subjis associated with X, and("obj) is associated with Y, a new meaning can be associated with (the semantic structure " projected from) the verb itself, which has the shape of a meaning language predicate sehen, applied to X and Y.

16 16 / Jonas Kuhn VP NP NP V Anna Otto sieht f : `sehen' pred subj pred g : case obj h : pred case `Anna' nom `Otto' acc g : [ ] f : [ ] h : [ ] FIGURE 3 LFG projections for (1.24) in (1.25). Here, the metavariables (", #) from the lexical entries have been instantiated to the f-structure labels from g. 3: (1.25) Anna: g Anna Otto: h Otto sieht: 8X Y: g X h Y ( f sehen (X Y ) Looking at the premises Anna and sieht, the meaning language constant Anna can be substituted for X in sieht, producing (1.26) as an intermediate result nally the constant Otto can likewise be substituted for Y, generating the meaning association (1.27) for the complete sentence. Since all premises have been used, leaving just an association for the entire sentence with a meaning language term of type t, the derivation has been successful. 22 (1.26) Anna-sieht: 8Y: h Y ( f sehen (Anna Y) (1.27) Anna-Otto-sieht: f sehen (Anna Otto ) Had there been an additional NP, not subcategorized for by theverb, like in the ungrammatical sentence (1.16) above, there would have been no derivation using up all premises, predicting ill-formedness. The instantiated symbols as values of pred are thus no longer needed to exclude illicit doubling. (As briey mentioned in sec , Dalrymple and colleagues point out that the glue language semantics replaces the Completeness and Coherence conditions of standard LFG, but to my knowledge, the observation that even instantiated symbols are made redundant has not been stated in the literature. 23 ) The f-structure in g. 3 can thus be reduced to (1.28). (1.28) f : subj g : case nom obj h : case acc To be able to address the SNP, weneedtobrieylookatthegeneralized quantier analysis in the linear logic framework (DLPS97, 234). As the representation at semantic structure for an NP like ein Kaninchen, an object with some internal structurea var(iable) and a restr(iction) featureis assumed. So, for (1.29), the LFG projections 22 For a more detailed introduction the reader is referred to DLPS It should be noted however that Johnson (1997, 1998) proposes a variant oflfg (R-LFG) that uses linear logic even as a replacement for f-descriptions.

17 look as in g. 4. (1.29) (weil) because Resource Sensitivity and the Split NP Construction / 17 Anna Anna VP ein a Kaninchen rabbit NP NP V sieht sees DET N Anna ein Kaninchen sieht f : subj g : obj h : case case nom acc g : [ ] f : [ ] var [ ] h : restr [ ] FIGURE 4 LFG projections for (1.29) In (1.30), the lexical entries with meaning constructors for the determiner ein `a' (R and S are property type variables, mnemonic for the restrictor and scope in the generalized quantier), 24 and for the common noun Kaninchen `rabbit' are given. (1.30) ein DET 8H R S:(8x(" var) x ( (" restr) R(x)) (8x " x ( H S (x)) ( H ein(r S) Kaninchen N 8X:(" var) X ( (" restr) Kaninchen (X ) Combining the two in the concrete example of g. 4, with the metavariables instantiated to h, and furthermore instantiating R in ein as Kaninchen will yield (1.31) as the meaning constructor for the NP. (1.31) ein-kaninchen: 8H S:(8x:h x ( H S (x)) ( H ein (Kaninchen S ) The antecedent of this linear implication is matched by the subjectverb semantics Anna-sieht of (1.26) above, which isidentical for this sentence, so instantiating H with the semantic structure f of the complete sentence, and S with the property z:sehen(anna z ) (by higherorder unication), we end up with the meaning association (1.32): (1.32) Anna-ein-Kaninchen-sieht: f ein (Kaninchen z :sehen (Anna z )) 24 Recall the discussion of the indenite article in sec above. I assume a generalized quantier analysis for the indenite article merely for ease of presentation, paying the price of having to assume two dierent lexicon entries for ein.

18 18 / Jonas Kuhn Anaphora In order to model the observed interplay between compositionality and anaphoricity in SNP in the linear logic framework, at least a simple analysis of anaphora is required. It is obvious that some adjustment of the basic mechanism is required, since intuitively anaphoricity allows to refer back to the meaning of an expression that is already involved as a resource in some independent derivation. DLPS97 (sec. 3.8) discuss two alternatives of a linear logic-based account of (E-type) anaphora. The rst one is to provide the anaphoric element (e.g. the pronoun himself ) with a meaning constructor that takes in some other meaning (from its antecedent) to generate its own meaning, but simultaneously outputs an identical copy of the antecedent's meaning, cf. the lexical entry in (1.33). 25 (1.33) himself NP ("pred) = `pro' (DLPS97, p. 249 (55)) 8X:(" ant) X ( (" ant) X " X This account is however problematic when dealing with extrasentential antecedents, as it requires for the anaphor to access the antecedent's meaning before this has been consumed. 26 The other alternative DLPS97 discuss avoids this problem by shifting the copying task from the anaphors to the (potential) antecedents. The meaning constructor for himself will then be simply the consumer (1.34) 8X:(" ant) X (" Y and the entry for a name, for instance, will supply arbitrarily many (including zero) extra copies of its meaning. Formally, thisisachieved with the of course connective of linear logic `!', which provides a reusable resource: (1.35) Anna: " Anna!(" Anna ) A problem that DLPS97 note for this account is that modications made to the meaning of an antecedent cannot be taken into account by the E-type anaphor. 27 A further problem may arise when the linear logic derivation is to replace the function of pred values completely, as argued in sec above. With the antecedent of an anaphor providing arbitrarily many, including zero, extra copies of its meaning for external 25 Like DLPS97, I assume that anaphora have been resolved (taking into account discourse factors such as salience, topichood, and focus). The choice of an antecedent is marked for simplicity within semantic structure, by a feature ant, which has as its value the antecedent's semantic structure. 26 If the linear logic derivation is not at all taken to model aspects of linguistic derivation, this may not be a problem. 27 This problem leads Crouch and van Genabith (1998) to propose yet another linear logic-based analysis of anaphoricity, assuming a context assignment,! for every expression besides the meaning assignment under.

19 Resource Sensitivity and the Split NP Construction / 19 use, an illicit NP doubling conguration like (1.36) might become possible: an NP (here den Peter) occurs exclusively to provide its meaning as an antecedent for an anaphor (ihn), without actually contributing to a local derivation. However, it is possible that such congurations are always ruled out by syntactic binding principles here, more research is required. (1.36) *den Peter sieht der Karl ihn. the.acc Peter sees the.nom Karl him I leave the question of anaphor-based vs. antecedent-based provision of extra resources open for now, temporarily adopting the second variant for practical reasons (dealing with extra-sentential antecedents in the following exposition of elliptical NPs) I'll briey come back tothe question in sec below Elliptical NPs The second key assumption I make for the overall SNP analysis, besides f-structure unication of the participating NPs, is anaphoricity of the Mittelfeld NP, completely parallel to elliptical NPs with an extrasentential antecedent. For elliptical NPs, it should be uncontroversial to assume anaphoric behaviour, in the sense that they take up a property that is salient in the context. In English, this anaphoricitycaneven be lexically tied to the item one (as in a new one). 28 In the corresponding cases in German, no overt element is required. (1.37) Ottos Auto ist kaputt gegangen. Er will sich Otto's car has broken gone he wants refl ein a neues new kaufen. buy `Otto's car has broken down. He wants to buy a new one.' I won't go into the question whether the eect should be captured by an empty nominal head like thepro that Fanselow (1988) assumes, or by category change, or at the level of the construction, since this is orthogonal to the main point under discussion. 29 For illustration I will simply use the indenite pronoun welche `some' as in (1.38) and assume (i) 28 However, where no adjective appears in the elliptical NP, one is not required: Isawsome/two/many/none. 29 Depending on this decision, the glue language expression marking anaphoricity (which gets introduced lexically in the case of (1.39) below) will be introduced in dierent ways for an example like einen kleinen `a small (one)': if an empty element is assumed, this will contribute the anaphorial expression lexically if one works with category change of the adjective, the lexical rule performing this change will add the anaphorial expression nally, if a construction-level treatment of headless NPs is assumed, we would have to deal with a glue language expression introduced by the construction. All this is possible technically.

20 20 / Jonas Kuhn that it is lexically anaphoric to a property, as expressed by the meaning constructor in (1.39). (1.38) Gestern wollten wir Kaninchen beobachten. Aber nur Anna hat yesterday wanted we rabbits watch but only Anna has welche some gesehen. seen `Yesterday, we wanted to watch rabbits. But only Anna could see any.' (1.39) welche NP 8H R S:(8x:(" ant var) x ( (" ant restr) R(x)) (8x: " x ( H S (x)) ( H welche (R S) Note that the meaning constructor is like the one for a determiner (cf. (1.30)), except that the rst implication (for the property that ends up as the generalized quantiers's restrictor) is based on the anaphor's antecedent rather than on the locally available noun semantics. Following the account for anaphora based on reusable resources on the side of the antecedents, we can assume that the common noun Kaninchen `rabbits' from the rst sentence of (1.38) supplies (on demand) additional copies of its meaning constructor under the of course connective: (1.40) Kaninchen: 8X:(" var) X ( (" restr) Kaninchen (X )!(8X:(" var) X ( (" restr) Kaninchen (X )) Thus, even after the derivation of the rst sentence has consumed the semantics of Kaninchen, another copy will be available for welche, which we can assume to mark the semantic structure projected from Kaninchen as its antecedent (i.e., as the value of the ant feature), as sketched in the f- and semantic structures for (1.38) given in g. 5 (the curved line without arrowheads signies identity).. VP NP... NP NP V f : subj g : obj h : case case nom acc Kaninchen Anna welche gesehen 2 4 ::: gf i : ::: ::: 3 5 f : [ ] g : [ ] 2 h 4 var [ ] : restr [ ] ant 3 5 i : [ ] FIGURE 5 Elliptical NP Analysis (cf. (1.38))

21 Resource Sensitivity and the Split NP Construction / 21 Instantiating the metavariables from (1.39) with the labels from g. 5, furthermore inserting i for (h ant), the premise for welche looks as follows: (1.41) welche: 8H R S:(8x:(ivar) x ( (irestr) R(x)) (8x:h x ( H S (x)) ( H welche (R S) The antecedent's left over semantics at i (cf. (1.42)) will match the rst implication in (1.41), so after anaphora resolution we getwelche 0 (1.43). (1.42) Kaninchen: 8X:(ivar) X ( (irestr) Kaninchen (X ) (1.43) welche 0 : 8H S:(8x:h x ( H S (x)) ( H welche (Kaninchen S ) Note that this is of identical form as ein-kaninchen in (1.31) above. The remainder of the derivation for the second sentence in (1.38) will thus go through as above The semantics of the Split NP construction Now, when welche is used as part of an SNP like in (1.44), my claim is that exactly the same lexicon entry is used as with an extrasentential antecedent. Although in this case, its f-structure happens to be unied with the f-structure projected from the NP Kaninchen under a single grammatical function (as discussed in sec ), welche still introduces an anaphorically dependent meaning constructor. (1.44) Kaninchen hat Anna welche gesehen. rabbits has Anna some seen `As for rabbits, Anna could see some.' The choice of a possible antecedent for the property-type anaphor is heavily restricted by thediscourse functions. 30 The antecedent has to be the topic of the sentence, i.e., in the concrete case the NP Kaninchen. For the standard mechanisms involved in this reasoning, it is a matter of coincidence that at f-structure, the chosen antecedentisidentical with the anaphor 31 the resources will nevertheless interact as usual. Essential for this to work is the circumstance that in the course of a glue-language derivation, the meanings associated with a particular semantic structure can change (this dierence from a unication account is also central for the analysis of adjuncts and complex predicates, cf. Dalrymple et al Dalrymple et al. 1995). 30 For a full understanding of the impact and interpretation of discourse functions in this context, further research is required. 31 As far as I can see, cyclic semantic structures of the form [1][ANT [1]] should pose no problem for the linear logic-based interpretation.

22 22 / Jonas Kuhn CP f : subj g : obj h : case nom NP C 0 Kaninchen C VP hat NP NP V Anna welche gesehen g : [ ] f : [ 2 ] h 4 var [ ] : restr [ ] ant 3 5 FIGURE 6 Projections of split NP analysis (cf. (1.44)) Based on the f- and semantic structure analysis of (1.44) in g. 6, the premises for the linear logic derivation are as follows. (1.45) Kaninchen: 8X:(hvar) X ( (hrestr) Kaninchen (X )!(8X:(hvar) X ( (hrestr) Kaninchen (X )) gesehen: 8X Y:g X h Y ( f sehen (X Y ) Anna: welche: g Anna 8H R S:(8x:(hant var) x ( (hant restr) R(x)) (8x:h x ( H S (x)) ( H welche (R S) First of all, Anna matches the rst conjunct in gesehen, yielding (1.46). (1.46) Anna-gesehen: 8Y:h Y ( f sehen (Anna Y ) Furthermore, since Kaninchen is the antecedent forwelche ((h ant) = h ), a copy ofkaninchen matches the rst conjunct in the antecedent of welche, substituting Kaninchen for R: (1.47) Kaninchen-welche: 8H S:(8x:h x ( H S (x)) ( H welche (Kaninchen S ) Finally, substituting z:sehen(anna z ) for S, (1.46) matches the antecedent of (1.47), and we get a meaning association for the complete sentence: (1.48) Kaninchen-Anna-welche-gesehen: f welche (Kaninchen z :sehen (Anna z )) Now, we have to see if all premises have been consumedto make this a successful derivation. This brings us back to the question which anaphoric mechanism to assume (sec ). Adopting the antecedentbased provision of extra resources, as we just did, there is a linear logic derivation that indeed consumes all premises: the of course operator

Word order in Lexical-Functional Grammar Topics M. Kaplan and Mary Dalrymple Ronald Xerox PARC August 1995 Kaplan and Dalrymple, ESSLLI 95, Barcelona 1 phrase structure rules work well Standard congurational

More information

The compositional semantics of same

The compositional semantics of same The compositional semantics of same Mike Solomon Amherst College Abstract Barker (2007) proposes the first strictly compositional semantic analysis of internal same. I show that Barker s analysis fails

More information

Anaphoric binding and. Topics in Lexical-Functional Grammar. Ronald M. Kaplan and Mary Dalrymple. Xerox PARC. August 1995

Anaphoric binding and. Topics in Lexical-Functional Grammar. Ronald M. Kaplan and Mary Dalrymple. Xerox PARC. August 1995 Anaphoric binding and `inside-out' functional uncertainty Topics in Lexical-Functional Grammar Ronald M. Kaplan and Mary Dalrymple Xerox PARC August 1995 Kaplan and Dalrymple, ESSLLI 95, Barcelona 1 Syntactic

More information

Cross-linguistic differences in the interpretation of sentences with more than one QP: German (Frey 1993) and Hungarian (É Kiss 1991)

Cross-linguistic differences in the interpretation of sentences with more than one QP: German (Frey 1993) and Hungarian (É Kiss 1991) Cross-linguistic differences in the interpretation of sentences with more than one QP: German (Frey 1993) and Hungarian (É Kiss 1991) 1. Quantifier Scope in English (May 1977, 1985) Predictions of May

More information

Movement and Binding

Movement and Binding Movement and Binding Gereon Müller Institut für Linguistik Universität Leipzig SoSe 2008 www.uni-leipzig.de/ muellerg Gereon Müller (Institut für Linguistik) Constraints in Syntax 4 SoSe 2008 1 / 35 Principles

More information

The finite verb and the clause: IP

The finite verb and the clause: IP Introduction to General Linguistics WS12/13 page 1 Syntax 6 The finite verb and the clause: Course teacher: Sam Featherston Important things you will learn in this section: The head of the clause The positions

More information

Paraphrasing controlled English texts

Paraphrasing controlled English texts Paraphrasing controlled English texts Kaarel Kaljurand Institute of Computational Linguistics, University of Zurich kaljurand@gmail.com Abstract. We discuss paraphrasing controlled English texts, by defining

More information

Scrambling in German - Extraction into the Mittelfeld

Scrambling in German - Extraction into the Mittelfeld Scrambling in German - Extraction into the Mittelfeld Stefan Mailer* Humboldt Universitat zu Berlin August, 1995 Abstract German is a language with a relatively free word order. During the last few years

More information

Constraints in Phrase Structure Grammar

Constraints in Phrase Structure Grammar Constraints in Phrase Structure Grammar Phrase Structure Grammar no movement, no transformations, context-free rules X/Y = X is a category which dominates a missing category Y Let G be the set of basic

More information

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1. Topic of the dissertation

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1. Topic of the dissertation Chapter 1. Introduction 1.1. Topic of the dissertation The topic of the dissertation is the relations between transitive verbs, aspect, and case marking in Estonian. Aspectual particles, verbs, and case

More information

Varieties of specification and underspecification: A view from semantics

Varieties of specification and underspecification: A view from semantics Varieties of specification and underspecification: A view from semantics Torgrim Solstad D1/B4 SFB meeting on long-term goals June 29th, 2009 The technique of underspecification I Presupposed: in semantics,

More information

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 3: Covert Movement vs. Type Shifting 1

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Quantificational DPs, Part 3: Covert Movement vs. Type Shifting 1 Quantificational DPs, Part 3: Covert Movement vs. Type Shifting 1 1. Introduction Thus far, we ve considered two competing analyses of sentences like those in (1). (1) Sentences Where a Quantificational

More information

Generalized Tree Descriptions for LFG

Generalized Tree Descriptions for LFG Generalized Tree Descriptions for LG Jonas Kuhn University of Texas at Austin Department of Linguistics jonask@mail.utexas.edu Proceedings of the LG03 Conference Saratoga Springs, NY, USA Miriam Butt and

More information

What s in a Lexicon. The Lexicon. Lexicon vs. Dictionary. What kind of Information should a Lexicon contain?

What s in a Lexicon. The Lexicon. Lexicon vs. Dictionary. What kind of Information should a Lexicon contain? What s in a Lexicon What kind of Information should a Lexicon contain? The Lexicon Miriam Butt November 2002 Semantic: information about lexical meaning and relations (thematic roles, selectional restrictions,

More information

UNBOUND ANAPHORIC PRONOUNS: E-TYPE, DYNAMIC, AND STRUCTURED-PROPOSITIONS APPROACHES

UNBOUND ANAPHORIC PRONOUNS: E-TYPE, DYNAMIC, AND STRUCTURED-PROPOSITIONS APPROACHES FRIEDERIKE MOLTMANN UNBOUND ANAPHORIC PRONOUNS: E-TYPE, DYNAMIC, AND STRUCTURED-PROPOSITIONS APPROACHES ABSTRACT. Unbound anaphoric pronouns or E-type pronouns have presented notorious problems for semantic

More information

Structure of Clauses. March 9, 2004

Structure of Clauses. March 9, 2004 Structure of Clauses March 9, 2004 Preview Comments on HW 6 Schedule review session Finite and non-finite clauses Constituent structure of clauses Structure of Main Clauses Discuss HW #7 Course Evals Comments

More information

Syntactic and Semantic Differences between Nominal Relative Clauses and Dependent wh-interrogative Clauses

Syntactic and Semantic Differences between Nominal Relative Clauses and Dependent wh-interrogative Clauses Theory and Practice in English Studies 3 (2005): Proceedings from the Eighth Conference of British, American and Canadian Studies. Brno: Masarykova univerzita Syntactic and Semantic Differences between

More information

COMPARATIVES WITHOUT DEGREES: A NEW APPROACH. FRIEDERIKE MOLTMANN IHPST, Paris fmoltmann@univ-paris1.fr

COMPARATIVES WITHOUT DEGREES: A NEW APPROACH. FRIEDERIKE MOLTMANN IHPST, Paris fmoltmann@univ-paris1.fr COMPARATIVES WITHOUT DEGREES: A NEW APPROACH FRIEDERIKE MOLTMANN IHPST, Paris fmoltmann@univ-paris1.fr It has become common to analyse comparatives by using degrees, so that John is happier than Mary would

More information

Scrambling in German { Extraction into te Mittelfeld Stefan Muller y Humboldt Universitat zu Berlin August, 199 Abstract German is a language wit a relatively free word order. During te last few years

More information

Appendix to Chapter 3 Clitics

Appendix to Chapter 3 Clitics Appendix to Chapter 3 Clitics 1 Clitics and the EPP The analysis of LOC as a clitic has two advantages: it makes it natural to assume that LOC bears a D-feature (clitics are Ds), and it provides an independent

More information

L130: Chapter 5d. Dr. Shannon Bischoff. Dr. Shannon Bischoff () L130: Chapter 5d 1 / 25

L130: Chapter 5d. Dr. Shannon Bischoff. Dr. Shannon Bischoff () L130: Chapter 5d 1 / 25 L130: Chapter 5d Dr. Shannon Bischoff Dr. Shannon Bischoff () L130: Chapter 5d 1 / 25 Outline 1 Syntax 2 Clauses 3 Constituents Dr. Shannon Bischoff () L130: Chapter 5d 2 / 25 Outline Last time... Verbs...

More information

Outline of today s lecture

Outline of today s lecture Outline of today s lecture Generative grammar Simple context free grammars Probabilistic CFGs Formalism power requirements Parsing Modelling syntactic structure of phrases and sentences. Why is it useful?

More information

Likewise, we have contradictions: formulas that can only be false, e.g. (p p).

Likewise, we have contradictions: formulas that can only be false, e.g. (p p). CHAPTER 4. STATEMENT LOGIC 59 The rightmost column of this truth table contains instances of T and instances of F. Notice that there are no degrees of contingency. If both values are possible, the formula

More information

How the Computer Translates. Svetlana Sokolova President and CEO of PROMT, PhD.

How the Computer Translates. Svetlana Sokolova President and CEO of PROMT, PhD. Svetlana Sokolova President and CEO of PROMT, PhD. How the Computer Translates Machine translation is a special field of computer application where almost everyone believes that he/she is a specialist.

More information

Comprendium Translator System Overview

Comprendium Translator System Overview Comprendium System Overview May 2004 Table of Contents 1. INTRODUCTION...3 2. WHAT IS MACHINE TRANSLATION?...3 3. THE COMPRENDIUM MACHINE TRANSLATION TECHNOLOGY...4 3.1 THE BEST MT TECHNOLOGY IN THE MARKET...4

More information

Overview of the TACITUS Project

Overview of the TACITUS Project Overview of the TACITUS Project Jerry R. Hobbs Artificial Intelligence Center SRI International 1 Aims of the Project The specific aim of the TACITUS project is to develop interpretation processes for

More information

CS4025: Pragmatics. Resolving referring Expressions Interpreting intention in dialogue Conversational Implicature

CS4025: Pragmatics. Resolving referring Expressions Interpreting intention in dialogue Conversational Implicature CS4025: Pragmatics Resolving referring Expressions Interpreting intention in dialogue Conversational Implicature For more info: J&M, chap 18,19 in 1 st ed; 21,24 in 2 nd Computing Science, University of

More information

3. Mathematical Induction

3. Mathematical Induction 3. MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION 83 3. Mathematical Induction 3.1. First Principle of Mathematical Induction. Let P (n) be a predicate with domain of discourse (over) the natural numbers N = {0, 1,,...}. If (1)

More information

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Nathaniel Hendren January, 2014 Abstract Both Akerlof (1970) and Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976) show that

More information

Chapter 13, Sections 13.1-13.2. Auxiliary Verbs. 2003 CSLI Publications

Chapter 13, Sections 13.1-13.2. Auxiliary Verbs. 2003 CSLI Publications Chapter 13, Sections 13.1-13.2 Auxiliary Verbs What Auxiliaries Are Sometimes called helping verbs, auxiliaries are little words that come before the main verb of a sentence, including forms of be, have,

More information

Ling 201 Syntax 1. Jirka Hana April 10, 2006

Ling 201 Syntax 1. Jirka Hana April 10, 2006 Overview of topics What is Syntax? Word Classes What to remember and understand: Ling 201 Syntax 1 Jirka Hana April 10, 2006 Syntax, difference between syntax and semantics, open/closed class words, all

More information

An Underspecied HPSG Representation for Information Structure Jonas Kuhn Institut fur maschinelle Sprachverarbeitung Azenbergstrae 1 D-014 Stuttgart, Germany Email: jonas@ims.uni-stuttgart.de Abstract

More information

bound Pronouns

bound Pronouns Bound and referential pronouns *with thanks to Birgit Bärnreuther, Christina Bergmann, Dominique Goltz, Stefan Hinterwimmer, MaikeKleemeyer, Peter König, Florian Krause, Marlene Meyer Peter Bosch Institute

More information

Superiority: Syntax or Semantics? Düsseldorf Jul02. Jill devilliers, Tom Roeper, Jürgen Weissenborn Smith,Umass,Potsdam

Superiority: Syntax or Semantics? Düsseldorf Jul02. Jill devilliers, Tom Roeper, Jürgen Weissenborn Smith,Umass,Potsdam Superiority: Syntax or Semantics? Düsseldorf Jul02 Jill devilliers, Tom Roeper, Jürgen Weissenborn Smith,Umass,Potsdam Introduction I. Question: When does a child know the grammaticality difference between

More information

Projektgruppe. Categorization of text documents via classification

Projektgruppe. Categorization of text documents via classification Projektgruppe Steffen Beringer Categorization of text documents via classification 4. Juni 2010 Content Motivation Text categorization Classification in the machine learning Document indexing Construction

More information

A Beautiful Four Days in Berlin Takafumi Maekawa (Ryukoku University) maekawa@soc.ryukoku.ac.jp

A Beautiful Four Days in Berlin Takafumi Maekawa (Ryukoku University) maekawa@soc.ryukoku.ac.jp A Beautiful Four Days in Berlin Takafumi Maekawa (Ryukoku University) maekawa@soc.ryukoku.ac.jp 1. The Data This paper presents an analysis of such noun phrases as in (1) within the framework of Head-driven

More information

Non-nominal Which-Relatives

Non-nominal Which-Relatives Non-nominal Which-Relatives Doug Arnold, Robert D. Borsley University of Essex The properties of non-restrictive relatives All non-restrictive relative clauses include a wh-word. There are no that or zero

More information

Syntactic Theory. Background and Transformational Grammar. Dr. Dan Flickinger & PD Dr. Valia Kordoni

Syntactic Theory. Background and Transformational Grammar. Dr. Dan Flickinger & PD Dr. Valia Kordoni Syntactic Theory Background and Transformational Grammar Dr. Dan Flickinger & PD Dr. Valia Kordoni Department of Computational Linguistics Saarland University October 28, 2011 Early work on grammar There

More information

Complex Predications in Argument Structure Alternations

Complex Predications in Argument Structure Alternations Complex Predications in Argument Structure Alternations Stefan Engelberg (Institut für Deutsche Sprache & University of Mannheim) Stefan Engelberg (IDS Mannheim), Universitatea din Bucureşti, November

More information

Co-Creation of Models and Metamodels for Enterprise. Architecture Projects.

Co-Creation of Models and Metamodels for Enterprise. Architecture Projects. Co-Creation of Models and Metamodels for Enterprise Architecture Projects Paola Gómez pa.gomez398@uniandes.edu.co Hector Florez ha.florez39@uniandes.edu.co ABSTRACT The linguistic conformance and the ontological

More information

Integrating Pattern Mining in Relational Databases

Integrating Pattern Mining in Relational Databases Integrating Pattern Mining in Relational Databases Toon Calders, Bart Goethals, and Adriana Prado University of Antwerp, Belgium {toon.calders, bart.goethals, adriana.prado}@ua.ac.be Abstract. Almost a

More information

COMPUTATIONAL DATA ANALYSIS FOR SYNTAX

COMPUTATIONAL DATA ANALYSIS FOR SYNTAX COLING 82, J. Horeck~ (ed.j North-Holland Publishing Compa~y Academia, 1982 COMPUTATIONAL DATA ANALYSIS FOR SYNTAX Ludmila UhliFova - Zva Nebeska - Jan Kralik Czech Language Institute Czechoslovak Academy

More information

On Shared Indefinite NPs in Coordinative Structures *

On Shared Indefinite NPs in Coordinative Structures * On Shared Indefinite NPs in Coordinative Structures * To appear in Journal of Semantics 2001 Kerstin Schwabe (U Leipzig/ZAS Berlin) & Klaus von Heusinger (U Konstanz) Abstract Indefinite NPs in shared

More information

IP PATTERNS OF MOVEMENTS IN VSO TYPOLOGY: THE CASE OF ARABIC

IP PATTERNS OF MOVEMENTS IN VSO TYPOLOGY: THE CASE OF ARABIC The Buckingham Journal of Language and Linguistics 2013 Volume 6 pp 15-25 ABSTRACT IP PATTERNS OF MOVEMENTS IN VSO TYPOLOGY: THE CASE OF ARABIC C. Belkacemi Manchester Metropolitan University The aim of

More information

Syntax: Phrases. 1. The phrase

Syntax: Phrases. 1. The phrase Syntax: Phrases Sentences can be divided into phrases. A phrase is a group of words forming a unit and united around a head, the most important part of the phrase. The head can be a noun NP, a verb VP,

More information

Moral Hazard. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Moral Hazard. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Moral Hazard Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania 1 Principal-Agent Problem Basic problem in corporate finance: separation of ownership and control: o The owners of the firm are typically

More information

Noam Chomsky: Aspects of the Theory of Syntax notes

Noam Chomsky: Aspects of the Theory of Syntax notes Noam Chomsky: Aspects of the Theory of Syntax notes Julia Krysztofiak May 16, 2006 1 Methodological preliminaries 1.1 Generative grammars as theories of linguistic competence The study is concerned with

More information

Is there repair by ellipsis?

Is there repair by ellipsis? Is there repair by ellipsis? Craig Sailor University of Groningen cwsailor@gmail.com Carson T. Schütze UCLA cschutze@ucla.edu Draft: December, 2014 Written for The book of syntactic questions 100 ideas

More information

English prepositional passive constructions

English prepositional passive constructions English prepositional constructions An empirical overview of the properties of English prepositional s is presented, followed by a discussion of formal approaches to the analysis of the various types of

More information

Quantifier Scope in Formal Linguistics

Quantifier Scope in Formal Linguistics Quantifier Scope in Formal Linguistics E.G. Ruys Utrecht University Yoad Winter Technion/Utrecht University To appear in D. Gabbay (ed.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic Second Edition 1. Introduction

More information

Structure Of Noun Phrases In German W. P. Lehmann University of Texas

Structure Of Noun Phrases In German W. P. Lehmann University of Texas [Eighth Annual Round Table Meeting on Linguistics and Language Studies, Georgetown University, 1957] Structure Of Noun Phrases In German W. P. Lehmann University of Texas Analyzing German materials with

More information

Proceedings of the LFG02 Conference. National Technical University of Athens, Athens. Miriam Butt and Tracy Holloway King (Editors) CSLI Publications

Proceedings of the LFG02 Conference. National Technical University of Athens, Athens. Miriam Butt and Tracy Holloway King (Editors) CSLI Publications GETARUN PARSER A parser equipped with Quantifier Raising and Anaphoric Binding based on LFG Rodolfo Delmonte Ca' Garzoni-Moro, San Marco 3417 Università "Ca Foscari" 30124 - VENEZIA Tel. 39-41-2578464/52/19

More information

Learning Translation Rules from Bilingual English Filipino Corpus

Learning Translation Rules from Bilingual English Filipino Corpus Proceedings of PACLIC 19, the 19 th Asia-Pacific Conference on Language, Information and Computation. Learning Translation s from Bilingual English Filipino Corpus Michelle Wendy Tan, Raymond Joseph Ang,

More information

Data Analysis 1. SET08104 Database Systems. Copyright @ Napier University

Data Analysis 1. SET08104 Database Systems. Copyright @ Napier University Data Analysis 1 SET08104 Database Systems Copyright @ Napier University Entity Relationship Modelling Overview Database Analysis Life Cycle Components of an Entity Relationship Diagram What is a relationship?

More information

Topology-based network security

Topology-based network security Topology-based network security Tiit Pikma Supervised by Vitaly Skachek Research Seminar in Cryptography University of Tartu, Spring 2013 1 Introduction In both wired and wireless networks, there is the

More information

Errata: Carnie (2008) Constituent Structure. Oxford University Press (MAY 2009) A NOTE OF EXPLANATION:

Errata: Carnie (2008) Constituent Structure. Oxford University Press (MAY 2009) A NOTE OF EXPLANATION: Errata: Carnie (2008) Constituent Structure. Oxford University Press (MAY 2009) A NOTE OF EXPLANATION: Dear Readers. There are a very large number of errata for this book. Most are minor but some of them

More information

Modeling Guidelines Manual

Modeling Guidelines Manual Modeling Guidelines Manual [Insert company name here] July 2014 Author: John Doe john.doe@johnydoe.com Page 1 of 22 Table of Contents 1. Introduction... 3 2. Business Process Management (BPM)... 4 2.1.

More information

SYNTAX: THE ANALYSIS OF SENTENCE STRUCTURE

SYNTAX: THE ANALYSIS OF SENTENCE STRUCTURE SYNTAX: THE ANALYSIS OF SENTENCE STRUCTURE OBJECTIVES the game is to say something new with old words RALPH WALDO EMERSON, Journals (1849) In this chapter, you will learn: how we categorize words how words

More information

Phrase Structure Rules, Tree Rewriting, and other sources of Recursion Structure within the NP

Phrase Structure Rules, Tree Rewriting, and other sources of Recursion Structure within the NP Introduction to Transformational Grammar, LINGUIST 601 September 14, 2006 Phrase Structure Rules, Tree Rewriting, and other sources of Recursion Structure within the 1 Trees (1) a tree for the brown fox

More information

Texas Success Initiative (TSI) Assessment

Texas Success Initiative (TSI) Assessment Texas Success Initiative (TSI) Assessment Interpreting Your Score 1 Congratulations on taking the TSI Assessment! The TSI Assessment measures your strengths and weaknesses in mathematics and statistics,

More information

Syntactic Theory on Swedish

Syntactic Theory on Swedish Syntactic Theory on Swedish Mats Uddenfeldt Pernilla Näsfors June 13, 2003 Report for Introductory course in NLP Department of Linguistics Uppsala University Sweden Abstract Using the grammar presented

More information

Texas Success Initiative (TSI) Assessment. Interpreting Your Score

Texas Success Initiative (TSI) Assessment. Interpreting Your Score Texas Success Initiative (TSI) Assessment Interpreting Your Score 1 Congratulations on taking the TSI Assessment! The TSI Assessment measures your strengths and weaknesses in mathematics and statistics,

More information

AUTOMATIC F-STRUCTURE ANNOTATION FROM THE AP TREEBANK

AUTOMATIC F-STRUCTURE ANNOTATION FROM THE AP TREEBANK AUTOMATIC F-STRUCTURE ANNOTATION FROM THE AP TREEBANK Louisa Sadler Josef van Genabith Andy Way University of Essex Dublin City University Dublin City University louisa@essex.ac.uk josef@compapp.dcu.ie

More information

Checking Access to Protected Members in the Java Virtual Machine

Checking Access to Protected Members in the Java Virtual Machine Checking Access to Protected Members in the Java Virtual Machine Alessandro Coglio Kestrel Institute 3260 Hillview Avenue, Palo Alto, CA 94304, USA Ph. +1-650-493-6871 Fax +1-650-424-1807 http://www.kestrel.edu/

More information

Chapter II. Controlling Cars on a Bridge

Chapter II. Controlling Cars on a Bridge Chapter II. Controlling Cars on a Bridge 1 Introduction The intent of this chapter is to introduce a complete example of a small system development. During this development, you will be made aware of the

More information

Comma checking in Danish Daniel Hardt Copenhagen Business School & Villanova University

Comma checking in Danish Daniel Hardt Copenhagen Business School & Villanova University Comma checking in Danish Daniel Hardt Copenhagen Business School & Villanova University 1. Introduction This paper describes research in using the Brill tagger (Brill 94,95) to learn to identify incorrect

More information

2. Basic Relational Data Model

2. Basic Relational Data Model 2. Basic Relational Data Model 2.1 Introduction Basic concepts of information models, their realisation in databases comprising data objects and object relationships, and their management by DBMS s that

More information

Statistical Machine Translation

Statistical Machine Translation Statistical Machine Translation Some of the content of this lecture is taken from previous lectures and presentations given by Philipp Koehn and Andy Way. Dr. Jennifer Foster National Centre for Language

More information

Natural Language Database Interface for the Community Based Monitoring System *

Natural Language Database Interface for the Community Based Monitoring System * Natural Language Database Interface for the Community Based Monitoring System * Krissanne Kaye Garcia, Ma. Angelica Lumain, Jose Antonio Wong, Jhovee Gerard Yap, Charibeth Cheng De La Salle University

More information

Questions? Assignment. Techniques for Gathering Requirements. Gathering and Analysing Requirements

Questions? Assignment. Techniques for Gathering Requirements. Gathering and Analysing Requirements Questions? Assignment Why is proper project management important? What is goal of domain analysis? What is the difference between functional and non- functional requirements? Why is it important for requirements

More information

Parsing Natural Language using LDS: A Prototype

Parsing Natural Language using LDS: A Prototype Parsing Natural Language using LDS: A Prototype MARCELO FINGER, Departamento de Ciência da Computação, Instituto de Matemática e Estatística, Universidade de São Paulo, Brazil. E-mail: mfinger@ime.usp.br

More information

Chapter 6. The stacking ensemble approach

Chapter 6. The stacking ensemble approach 82 This chapter proposes the stacking ensemble approach for combining different data mining classifiers to get better performance. Other combination techniques like voting, bagging etc are also described

More information

Chapter 1 Verificationism Then and Now

Chapter 1 Verificationism Then and Now Chapter 1 Verificationism Then and Now Per Martin-Löf The term veri fi cationism is used in two different ways: the fi rst is in relation to the veri fi cation principle of meaning, which we usually and

More information

The College Standard

The College Standard The College Standard Writing College Papers: Identifying Standards and Critical Thinking Challenges Building Blocks Grammar Vocabulary Questions The Goals of Academic Writing Thesis Argument Research Plagiarism

More information

Overview of MT techniques. Malek Boualem (FT)

Overview of MT techniques. Malek Boualem (FT) Overview of MT techniques Malek Boualem (FT) This section presents an standard overview of general aspects related to machine translation with a description of different techniques: bilingual, transfer,

More information

Modelling and Implementing a Knowledge Base for Checking Medical Invoices with DLV

Modelling and Implementing a Knowledge Base for Checking Medical Invoices with DLV Modelling and Implementing a Knowledge Base for Checking Medical Invoices with DLV Christoph Beierle 1, Oliver Dusso 1, Gabriele Kern-Isberner 2 1 Dept. of Computer Science, FernUniversität in Hagen, 58084

More information

Hybrid Strategies. for better products and shorter time-to-market

Hybrid Strategies. for better products and shorter time-to-market Hybrid Strategies for better products and shorter time-to-market Background Manufacturer of language technology software & services Spin-off of the research center of Germany/Heidelberg Founded in 1999,

More information

CONSTRAINING THE GRAMMAR OF APS AND ADVPS. TIBOR LACZKÓ & GYÖRGY RÁKOSI http://ieas.unideb.hu/ rakosi, laczko http://hungram.unideb.

CONSTRAINING THE GRAMMAR OF APS AND ADVPS. TIBOR LACZKÓ & GYÖRGY RÁKOSI http://ieas.unideb.hu/ rakosi, laczko http://hungram.unideb. CONSTRAINING THE GRAMMAR OF APS AND ADVPS IN HUNGARIAN AND ENGLISH: CHALLENGES AND SOLUTIONS IN AN LFG-BASED COMPUTATIONAL PROJECT TIBOR LACZKÓ & GYÖRGY RÁKOSI http://ieas.unideb.hu/ rakosi, laczko http://hungram.unideb.hu

More information

Draft Martin Doerr ICS-FORTH, Heraklion, Crete Oct 4, 2001

Draft Martin Doerr ICS-FORTH, Heraklion, Crete Oct 4, 2001 A comparison of the OpenGIS TM Abstract Specification with the CIDOC CRM 3.2 Draft Martin Doerr ICS-FORTH, Heraklion, Crete Oct 4, 2001 1 Introduction This Mapping has the purpose to identify, if the OpenGIS

More information

Resumption by Buffers: German Relative Clauses

Resumption by Buffers: German Relative Clauses Resumption by Buffers: German Relative Clauses Gereon Müller Abstract In a local derivational (phase-based) approach to syntax, instances of resumption in German (longdistance) relativization constructions

More information

CHAPTER 7 GENERAL PROOF SYSTEMS

CHAPTER 7 GENERAL PROOF SYSTEMS CHAPTER 7 GENERAL PROOF SYSTEMS 1 Introduction Proof systems are built to prove statements. They can be thought as an inference machine with special statements, called provable statements, or sometimes

More information

A Knowledge-based System for Translating FOL Formulas into NL Sentences

A Knowledge-based System for Translating FOL Formulas into NL Sentences A Knowledge-based System for Translating FOL Formulas into NL Sentences Aikaterini Mpagouli, Ioannis Hatzilygeroudis University of Patras, School of Engineering Department of Computer Engineering & Informatics,

More information

Phase 2 of the D4 Project. Helmut Schmid and Sabine Schulte im Walde

Phase 2 of the D4 Project. Helmut Schmid and Sabine Schulte im Walde Statistical Verb-Clustering Model soft clustering: Verbs may belong to several clusters trained on verb-argument tuples clusters together verbs with similar subcategorization and selectional restriction

More information

1 Uncertainty and Preferences

1 Uncertainty and Preferences In this chapter, we present the theory of consumer preferences on risky outcomes. The theory is then applied to study the demand for insurance. Consider the following story. John wants to mail a package

More information

VP-TOPICALIZATION AND THE VERB GJØRE IN NORWEGIAN 1

VP-TOPICALIZATION AND THE VERB GJØRE IN NORWEGIAN 1 3 Working Papers in Scandinavian Syntax 45 1990 pp. 3-12. Helge Lødrup: VP-TOPICALIZATION AND THE VERB GJØRE IN NORWEGIAN 1 1. It is well known that VP-topicalization in Norwegian (as in Swedish and Danish)

More information

19. Morphosyntax in L2A

19. Morphosyntax in L2A Spring 2012, April 5 Missing morphology Variability in acquisition Morphology and functional structure Morphosyntax in acquisition In L1A, we observe that kids don t always provide all the morphology that

More information

The Graphical Method: An Example

The Graphical Method: An Example The Graphical Method: An Example Consider the following linear program: Maximize 4x 1 +3x 2 Subject to: 2x 1 +3x 2 6 (1) 3x 1 +2x 2 3 (2) 2x 2 5 (3) 2x 1 +x 2 4 (4) x 1, x 2 0, where, for ease of reference,

More information

OPRE 6201 : 2. Simplex Method

OPRE 6201 : 2. Simplex Method OPRE 6201 : 2. Simplex Method 1 The Graphical Method: An Example Consider the following linear program: Max 4x 1 +3x 2 Subject to: 2x 1 +3x 2 6 (1) 3x 1 +2x 2 3 (2) 2x 2 5 (3) 2x 1 +x 2 4 (4) x 1, x 2

More information

Unit 2.1. Data Analysis 1 - V2.0 1. Data Analysis 1. Dr Gordon Russell, Copyright @ Napier University

Unit 2.1. Data Analysis 1 - V2.0 1. Data Analysis 1. Dr Gordon Russell, Copyright @ Napier University Data Analysis 1 Unit 2.1 Data Analysis 1 - V2.0 1 Entity Relationship Modelling Overview Database Analysis Life Cycle Components of an Entity Relationship Diagram What is a relationship? Entities, attributes,

More information

FINANCIAL ECONOMICS OPTION PRICING

FINANCIAL ECONOMICS OPTION PRICING OPTION PRICING Options are contingency contracts that specify payoffs if stock prices reach specified levels. A call option is the right to buy a stock at a specified price, X, called the strike price.

More information

Sentence Structure/Sentence Types HANDOUT

Sentence Structure/Sentence Types HANDOUT Sentence Structure/Sentence Types HANDOUT This handout is designed to give you a very brief (and, of necessity, incomplete) overview of the different types of sentence structure and how the elements of

More information

A Day in the Life of a Trader

A Day in the Life of a Trader Siena, April 2014 Introduction 1 Examples of Market Payoffs 2 3 4 Sticky Smile e Floating Smile 5 Examples of Market Payoffs Understanding risk profiles of a payoff is conditio sine qua non for a mathematical

More information

A Review of Database Schemas

A Review of Database Schemas A Review of Database Schemas Introduction The purpose of this note is to review the traditional set of schemas used in databases, particularly as regards how the conceptual schemas affect the design of

More information

ž Lexicalized Tree Adjoining Grammar (LTAG) associates at least one elementary tree with every lexical item.

ž Lexicalized Tree Adjoining Grammar (LTAG) associates at least one elementary tree with every lexical item. Advanced Natural Language Processing Lecture 11 Grammar Formalisms (II): LTAG, CCG Bonnie Webber (slides by Mark teedman, Bonnie Webber and Frank Keller) 12 October 2012 Lexicalized Tree Adjoining Grammar

More information

Estudios de lingüística inglesa aplicada

Estudios de lingüística inglesa aplicada Estudios de lingüística inglesa aplicada ADVERB ORIENTATION: SEMANTICS AND PRAGMATICS José María García Núñez Universidad de Cádiz Orientation is a well known property of some adverbs in English. Early

More information

LESSON THIRTEEN STRUCTURAL AMBIGUITY. Structural ambiguity is also referred to as syntactic ambiguity or grammatical ambiguity.

LESSON THIRTEEN STRUCTURAL AMBIGUITY. Structural ambiguity is also referred to as syntactic ambiguity or grammatical ambiguity. LESSON THIRTEEN STRUCTURAL AMBIGUITY Structural ambiguity is also referred to as syntactic ambiguity or grammatical ambiguity. Structural or syntactic ambiguity, occurs when a phrase, clause or sentence

More information

Introduction to formal semantics -

Introduction to formal semantics - Introduction to formal semantics - Introduction to formal semantics 1 / 25 structure Motivation - Philosophy paradox antinomy division in object und Meta language Semiotics syntax semantics Pragmatics

More information

Automating Software Development Process Using Fuzzy Logic

Automating Software Development Process Using Fuzzy Logic Automating Software Development Process Using Fuzzy Logic Francesco Marcelloni 1 and Mehmet Aksit 2 1 Dipartimento di Ingegneria dell Informazione, University of Pisa, Via Diotisalvi, 2-56122, Pisa, Italy,

More information

WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT?

WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT? WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT? introduction Many students seem to have trouble with the notion of a mathematical proof. People that come to a course like Math 216, who certainly

More information