FORMING ETHICAL STANDARDS

Similar documents
Handout for Central Approaches to Ethics p. 1 meelerd@winthrop.edu

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

ETHICAL APPROACHES TO PUBLIC RELATIONS

Ethical Theories ETHICAL THEORIES. presents NOTES:

MS 102- PROFESSIONAL & BUSINESS ETHICS 2 MARKS QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS UNIT I

Kant s deontological ethics

CHAPTER 1 Understanding Ethics

Getting to the Bottom of Values

Objections to Friedman s Shareholder/Stockholder Theory

PHIL 341: Ethical Theory

Ethics in International Business

CRITICAL THINKING REASONS FOR BELIEF AND DOUBT (VAUGHN CH. 4)

Chapter Four. Ethics in International Business. Introduction. Ethical Issues in International Business

Philosophy 1100 Introduction to Ethics. Lecture 3 Three Different Types of Ethical Theories

A Worksheet for Defining your Code of Ethics

Unit 3 Handout 1: DesJardin s Environmental Ethics. Chapter 6 Biocentric Ethics and the Inherent Value of Life

Lecture 2: Moral Reasoning & Evaluating Ethical Theories

A. What is Virtue Ethics?

Critical Analysis o Understanding Ethical Failures in Leadership

LEGAL POSITIVISM vs. NATURAL LAW THEORY

In Defense of Kantian Moral Theory Nader Shoaibi University of California, Berkeley

Ethical decision-making. Kitty Uys (Ph.D) Michal Harty (Ph.D) (012)

Chapter 2 ETHICAL DECISION-MAKING: PERSONAL AND PROFESSIONAL CONTEXTS

TUSD CAPTAIN S ACADEMY LEADERSHIP TRAINING

~SHARING MY PERSONAL PERSPECTIVE~

Killing And Letting Die

Honesty, Integrity and Ethics in Public Relations. In the quote above, Mitchell Friedman (n.d.), identifies a core principle of public

MILL. The principle of utility determines the rightness of acts (or rules of action?) by their effect on the total happiness.

Cultural Relativism. 1. What is Cultural Relativism? 2. Is Cultural Relativism true? 3. What can we learn from Cultural Relativism?

Ethical Egoism. 1. What is Ethical Egoism?: Let s turn to another theory about the nature of morality: Ethical Egoism.

How To Understand The Moral Code Of A God (For Men)

Code of Ethics and Professional Conduct

Code of Business Conduct and Ethics. With Special Message for Senior Business and Finance Leaders

Modern Science vs. Ancient Philosophy. Daniel Gilbert s theory of happiness as presented in his book, Stumbling on Happiness,

Our Code is for all of us

MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2004

Lecture #2: Ethical Dilemmas, Choices, and Codes of Ethics

Fundamentals Explained


An Analysis of the Objectivist Ethics in Educational Leadership Though Ayn Rand s The Virtues of Selfishness (1964)

ENLIGHTENMENT THINKERS AND GOVERNMENT MAN IS BORN FREE, BUT EVERYWHERE IS IN CHAINS.

Professional Ethics PHIL Today s Topic Absolute Moral Rules & Kantian Ethics. Part I

PROFESSIONAL VALUES: The Basis of My Professional Life

Divine command theory

Shareholder Theory (Martin Friedman)

12 Step Worksheet Questions

In this essay, I will first outline my understanding of the basis for Kant's categorical

Ethics in Biomedical Engineering. Ethics and morality. Ethical theories. Kantianism (Kant, ) Act Utilitarianism (Bentham, )

1/9. Locke 1: Critique of Innate Ideas

Code of Business Conduct and Ethics THE WOODBRIDGE WAY. integrity honesty respect responsibility

Code of Ethics December 2013

Ethical Decision Making

Ethical Guidelines for the Development of Emergency Plans

Right is right, even if everyone is against it; and wrong is wrong, even if everyone is for it.

@ Home FAMILY Study Session

Explain and critically assess the Singer Solution to Global Poverty

Moral Theory. What makes things right or wrong?

GCE. Religious Studies. Mark Scheme for June Advanced GCE Unit G582: Religious Ethics. Oxford Cambridge and RSA Examinations

Business Ethics comprises the principles, values, and standards that guide behavior in the world of business.

Understanding Accounting Ethics Cheffers & Pakaluk (2005): Allen David Press. Basics of Accounting Ethics

Hope In-Home Care CODE OF CONDUCT AND ETHICS

Professional Roles in Nursing Practice. Legal and Ethical Principles and Values

Ethics and the Criminal Justice Professional

OUR CODE OF ETHICS. June 2013

Leonard W. Vona, CPA, CFE

A. The Three Main Branches of the Philosophical Study of Ethics. 1. Meta-ethics. 2. Normative Ethics. 3. Applied Ethics

Vortrag Dubrovnik SS 2013

June The way we work

The Transpersonal (Spiritual) Journey Towards Leadership Excellence Using 8ICOL

Free Legal Consumer Guide Series

VALUES AND ETHICS IN UNIVERSITY GOVERNANCE. Ilkka Niiniluoto University of Helsinki Paris, September 12, 2006

CODE OF ETHICS POLICY

Contents. Preface 7. Contents

Justice and Ethics. Jimmy Rising. October 18, 2002

Kern Community College District Board Policy Manual Section Eleven General Personnel Administration

MOST FREQUENTLY ASKED INTERVIEW QUESTIONS. 1. Why don t you tell me about yourself? 2. Why should I hire you?

Fiscal Policies and Procedures Fraud, Waste & Abuse

The way we do business.

GIVING VOICE TO VALUES: BRIEF INTRODUCTION

Manufacturers versus Component Part and Raw Material Suppliers: How to Prevent Liability By Kenneth Ross *

50 Tough Interview Questions

The Good Samaritan. Lesson Text: Luke 10:25-37

Critical Analysis So what does that REALLY mean?

Last May, philosopher Thomas Nagel reviewed a book by Michael Sandel titled

THE MORAL AGENDA OF CITIZENSHIP EDUCATION

Accounting Ethics: The Moral of the Story

REPUTATION MANAGEMENT SURVIVAL GUIDE. A BEGINNER S GUIDE for managing your online reputation to promote your local business.

Neutrality s Much Needed Place In Dewey s Two-Part Criterion For Democratic Education

AQA PHILOSOPHY SYLLABUS: USEFUL WEB LINKS

Principles and standards in Independent Advocacy organisations and groups

H o w t o W r i t e a J u d g e m e n t

Systems of Law RSPT Application of the Law to Respiratory Care. Public Law. Private Law. Types of Negligence. Tort Law

1983, 1993, 2003 Mars, Incorporated Printed on environmentally friendly paper, 100% chlorine free in manufacture

Perspectives on Ideology Social 30-1 Introduction

The 2014 Ultimate Career Guide

Chapter 2 The Ethical Basis of Law and Business Management

CHARACTER-CENTERED TEACHING: SIX STEPS TO BECOMING A MODEL PROGRAM

NEGOTIATING STRATEGIES

for Sample Company November 2012

Finding Your Gift: Three Paths to Maximizing Impact in Your Career

Transcription:

FORMING ETHICAL STANDARDS Ethical standards of any type require a devotion to ethical action, and ethical action often comes in conflict with our instinct to act in our own self-interest. This tendency toward egoism is manifested at every level of our lives and reflected not only in our actions but also in our deepseated sympathy for the tenets of self-interest. We innately understand the desire of our newspaper to turn a profit, or of our media conglomerate to expand. We understand in the same way that we justify our own decisions to move ahead in life. That is why it is important to understand ethical standards from at least three perspectives: the personal, the professional, and the societal. By understanding the ethical principles associated with each level, we are less likely to act self-interestedly. However, it would be erroneous to assume that these levels are interchangeable or that a decision made using personal ethical standards would automatically apply at the professional or societal levels or vice versa. Most of us tend to act at each of these levels with no particular priority assigned to any one, forgetting that we are obligated differently at each level. These obligations can, and often do, conflict. However, since we tend to assimilate ethical principles at each of these levels, we cannot truly separate them nor should we. Instead, we must learn to recognize when professional standards override personal standards, or when obligations to society outweigh obligations to our employers or to ourselves. In other words, we must learn how and when the standards of each level apply. We cannot, try as we may, divorce ourselves from any of these standards and obligations and exist only on one level. How our standards develop at each level has much to do with our values and ideals, for from these two sources come our principles the basis for our ethical actions at every level. CAN PERSONAL ETHICS BECOME PROFESSIONAL ETHICS? The obligations incurred by an individual assuming a professional role may differ radically from personal obligations. For example, it may never be appropriate for a private individual to reveal secrets about someone that might result in that person s reputation being ruined, even if the information is true. Take that same private individual and make her a journalist whose job is to investigate the extramarital love affair of the President of the United States, and her actions might not only be deemed appropriate, they might prove to be necessary. When we adopt a profession whose entire reason for being is to provide information, we may find the obligations of that job may, and generally do, supersede those of our personal lives. By letting our personal principles take first priority, we could be compromising our professional principles. The question then becomes, Which do we want most to be, a private citizen or a journalist? While the two roles are not mutually exclusive, there is an awareness that one assumes the mantle of professionalism willingly, accepting that a muting of personal values is part of the payment for doing so. This does not mean that we suddenly become immune to human suffering or deaf to pleas for civility or good taste. It simply means that professional values may, and often do, outweigh personal values. 1

To some degree personal and professional principles will certainly mesh. However, deference is usually, and possibly rightly, given to professional principles. After all, those principles ideally have been established for good reasons reasons that go beyond satisfying personal values. The ultimate test of any principle, personal or professional, must be the efficacy of the resulting actions based on those principles not just for the person acting (the moral agent), but for all those involved or affected by the action. WHERE DO OUR PRINCIPLES COME FROM? Principles come from values and ideals. When we say that truth is of paramount importance to journalism, we are stating a professional value. When we talk about believing in the sanctity of life, we are expressing a personal value. When we tout journalistic objectivity, we are really talking about an ideal in the same way that being virtuous may be a personal ideal. When we say that we will not print the names of rape victims, we are talking about a principle based on the value of privacy. Likewise, a principle of not printing the names of alleged perpetrators could be based on the ideal of innocent until proven guilty. While the differences among these three concepts may seem at first to be small, there are some distinct definitional contrasts. Values cover a broad range of possibilities, such as aesthetic values (something is harmonious or pleasing), professional values (innovation and promptness), logical values (consistency and competency), sociocultural values (thrift and hard work), and moral values (honesty and nonviolence). Values are also further defined by philosophers as being either instrumental or intrinsic. An instrumental value is one that leads to something of even more value. For example, money usually is seen has having instrumental value, because possessing it leads to other things of greater value, including (we suppose) happiness. Other values, such as happiness, are said to possess intrinsic value they are sought after because they are ends in and of themselves, and don t necessarily lead to greater values. As journalists, for instance, we could value truth telling because it leads to an honest account of what s happening in the world, which leads to our fulfilling our goals as reporters, which leads to us being satisfied with ourselves, which leads to happiness for us. Conversely, we could simply value truth telling as an end in itself. However, we need not trace every value through to its intrinsic conclusion; rather, we should simply be aware that some values can be ranked as more important to us because they are ends to be sought in themselves and not means to other ends. Ideals are a bit easier to define. An ideal can be seen as a notion of excellence or a a goal that is thought to bring about greater harmony to ourselves and to others. For example, our culture respects ideals such as tolerance, compassion, loyalty, forgiveness, peace, justice, fairness, and respect for persons. In addition to these human ideals are institutional or organizational ideals, such as profit, efficiency, productivity, quality, and stability. Ideals often come in conflict with each other. In such cases, decisions become much harder to make. For example, a choice to place the journalistic ideal of providing information an audience 2

wants over the societal ideal of honoring privacy, could result in a decision to run a story that may, in fact, violate someone s privacy. Principles are those guidelines we derive from values and ideals and are precursors to codified rules. They are usually stated in positive (prescriptive) or negative (proscriptive) terms. For example, Never corrupt the integrity of media channels, would be a principle derived from the professional value of truth telling in public relations. Or, Always maximize profit, might be derived from belief in the efficacy of the free-enterprise system. When we begin to establish principles, we are committing ourselves to a course of action based on our values and ideals. When we act ethically, we typically act on principle. Principle can serve as a guideline for ethical action. That is why principles often tend to become codified, either as policies, codes, or laws. A newspaper s policy against publishing the names of rape victims is probably based on a belief in privacy for victims of violent crimes. The principle of that belief (value) is to withhold the name, or nondisclosure. In the same way, valuing human life can lead to a principle of nonviolence. In both cases, action (or inaction) is the result of the principle and is derived from it in the same way that the principle is derived from the value or ideal. NORMATIVE PRINCIPLES IN APPLIED ETHICS (by James Fieser, writing for the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy) The following principles are the ones most commonly appealed to in applied ethical discussions: Personal benefit: acknowledge the extent to which an action produces beneficial consequences for the individual in question. Social benefit: acknowledge the extent to which an action produces beneficial consequences for society. Principle of benevolence: help those in need. Principle of paternalism: assist others in pursuing their best interests when they cannot do so themselves. Principle of harm: do not harm others. Principle of honesty: do not deceive others. Principle of lawfulness: do not violate the law. Principle of autonomy: acknowledge a person's freedom over his/her actions or physical body. Principle of justice: acknowledge a person's right to due process, fair compensation for harm done, and fair distribution of benefits. Rights: acknowledge a person's rights to life, information, privacy, free expression, and safety. The above principles represent a spectrum of traditional normative principles and are derived from both consequentialist and duty-based approaches. The first two principles, personal benefit 3

and social benefit, are consequentialist since they appeal to the consequences of an action as it affects the individual or society. The remaining principles are duty-based. The principles of benevolence, paternalism, harm, honesty, and lawfulness are based on duties we have toward others. The principles of autonomy, justice, and the various rights are based on moral rights. APPROACHES TO ETHICS Most ethical issues involve values: our own, and those of the people affected by our decision. Throughout history, philosophers have developed various approaches to establishing societal and personal values and methods of using them to help solve ethical dilemmas. Listed below are some of these approaches. THE CONSEQUENTIAL APPROACH Basing an ethical decision on the outcome is called consequential ethics. The action that produces the greatest balance of good over bad is the correct action to take. The most common form of consequential ethics is Utilitarianism. Utilitarianism was originally conceived as a way to recognize the poorer classes in a society during legislative decision making. Under this approach, ethical actions are those that provide the greatest good for the greatest number of people, no matter who those people are. When a journalist justifies an action by saying that the public had the right to know certain information, she is using a Utilitarian argument. She is basically saying that the benefit to the public outweighs any potential harm to the subject of the story. The danger of using this approach exclusively is that a minority opinion might be ignored, or an undeserving majority may benefit from your actions. THE DUTY-BASED OR RIGHTS APPROACH Some people have proposed that some actions are just plain right or wrong in an of themselves, regardless of the consequences. Because we are imbued with the ability to reason, we should be able to figure out which actions are right and which are wrong. Under this approach, human beings are obligated to preserve each other s dignity, which means a respect for rights. Obligations and rights often go hand-in-hand. For example, William David Ross, a contemporary British philosopher, developed a set of six obligations that he believed everyone everywhere would recognize as being morally binding. Fidelity If you promise (explicitly or implicitly) to do something, you should do it. For instance, most relationships, professional and personal, assume a duty to tell the truth or, at least, not to lie. Duties of fidelity would also include remaining faithful to contracts, explicit or implicit; and keeping promises. This category also includes duties of reparation that is, if you do something wrong, you are obliged to undo the wrong. 4

Gratitude If any person performs some service (favor) for you, then you have some obligation to the person who performed the favor. This would apply both to relationships between friends and to relationships between employer and employee. For example, if your employer treats you in an exceptional manner, above that normally expected in an employee employer relationship, your obligation would deepen to honor your employer s wishes beyond the duty of fidelity. Justice If any person deserves something by virtue of merit, you are obligated to help them achieve what they merit. By the same token, you are obligated to deny to those who do not deserve. In practice, this can often mean giving greater consideration to the claims of those who deserve it rather than to those who demand it, regardless of their position or power. Beneficence There are always those who need our help. If you can make some person better with respect to their state of existence, then you are obliged to do so. In a decisionmaking situation, this duty may oblige you to act when non-action is preferred or recommended by others. Self improvement If you can make yourself better with respect to your state of existence, then you are obliged to do so. This can cover anything from preserving your own integrity to taking advantage of a favorable situation for self-improvement. Non-injury If you are in a position to avoid hurting someone, then you are obliged to do so. This contrasts with the duty of beneficence. Although not injuring others incidentally means doing them good, Ross interprets the avoidance of injuring others as a more pressing duty than beneficence. This may, in fact, be the most important of Ross s duties, since it implies that the possibility of injury to any claimant to whom you are obligated must be assigned some weight. However, this very often results in a form of cost-benefit or riskbenefit analysis, which is counter to the underlying premise of duty-based theory that rules can, and should, be moral in and of themselves, and not based on considerations of outcome. If you turn these around, they become rights. The parallel of an obligation of non-injury is a right not to be injured. The obverse of a duty of justice is a right to be treated fairly and according to your merit. We should always strive not to violate the rights of others. For example, the socalled Harm Principle states that my freedom to do what I want is only limited by the degree to which it violates someone else s rights. Rules formulated based on obligations and rights need to be consistently followed with few exceptions. One of the best ways to discover these rules is to ask yourself if you would be willing to make this into a law that everyone everywhere would have to follow all the time no exceptions. Do not kill might be one such rule. The major drawback to duty-based ethics is that they often become absolute rules that don t allow the flexibility that human beings need to make moral decisions. After all, if we are to use our reason, then we must realize that situations differ and no single rule can possibly cover all contingencies. 5

THE SOCIAL CONTRACT APPROACH This approach assumes that all members of society are bound together by a social contract. Under this contract, each member is obligated to the whole of society to fulfill his part of the contract. Working for the common good is part of the formula of most social contracts. As Thomas Hobbes once suggested, if we don t work together we will become mere beasts, scratching out a meager living in a state of nature. The ideal of the social contract is that we each realize that we rely on the other as much as the other relies on each of us. Community is a key component of the social contract, and appeals to community or community spirit are frequently part of the decision making process. All media professions are bound by the public interest, which means they must, at least in part, be responsive to community needs and provide forums for public discourse. THE VIRTUE/CHARACTER APPROACH Virtue or character ethics dates back at least to the early Greek philosophers, Plato and Aristotle. They tended to ask not so much about right actions as about right character, assuming that a person of good character would automatically take right action. Character is developed through the acquisition of virtues. Virtues are defined as traits of character, practiced habitually, that are good for you. For example: courage, honesty, integrity, fairness, benevolence, and compassion. Through education and practice, we gradually develop these character traits, eventually realizing our potential to be the best we can be. A person of good character will eventually be able to recognize automatically the right action in a given situation. And that action will normally support the morally correct position. In addition, a person of good character will act in a consistent manner. For example, we would expect a person of good moral character to be honest in both her private and public lives. THE CARE APPROACH Recently, a new approach to ethics has cited a desire to move beyond the traditional-rational approach to moral decision making and consider the emotional-subjective approach outlined by the ethic of care. The formality of such concepts as duty and justice often results in objectification of human beings, or, at least, a distancing of the parties involved in and affected by moral decision making. Caring, on the other hand, requires a closer relationship between parties and recognition of the other as a subjective being. Care approaches recognize the network of individual lives common within society and the careneed relationships that we all develop. Based on an obligation to care, this approach would have us view ourselves as part of a network of individuals whose needs (when they become clear) create a duty in us to respond. Like most ethical decisions, responding to need requires a weighing of interests; however, relating to the need on an emotional level is a vital consideration absent from many other such formulas. 6

While not dismissing the importance of justice and fairness, moral decisions should also make allowances for differences in needs. In other words, need may dictate an obligation to care. The ethic of care requires, at minimum, that need be recognized as an important component of human interaction. CAVEAT Any moral decision-making process worth its salt must allow for three things: reflection, justification, and consistency. In order to rationalize our reasons to ourselves, we must reflect on all of the facets of the dilemma we are facing. We must do so without presumption that any particular course of action is automatically appropriate. An honest assessment will provide the only means to an equitable solution. We may be called upon to justify our decisions to others. We must be prepared to do so with the expectation that we will never satisfy everyone, but with the determination to try. Finally, we must be consistent, for moral consistency is the one of the hallmarks of integrity, and integrity may be the most valuable coin of the moral realm. Moral decision making must become routine so engrained in our professional behavior that we cannot separate it from our other decision-making processes. The ultimate goal of any decisionmaking tool is to allow for the formulation of principles and guidelines by which to make future decisions. At the very least, its consistent use should so educate the user that future moral decisions might become second nature. A final caveat: Blind obedience to any one philosophy is not sufficient for an educated analysis of a moral issue. Unwavering adherence to any rule, no matter how well-intentioned, can lead to callousness. By the same token, service always to the greater good can result in tyrannizing a deserving minority. We cannot let our emotions rule our decisions any more than we can let our reason alone (often cold and calculating) do so. And, we must remember that service to our professions and service to society are not always one and the same thing. There are times when each of these may fairly overrule the other. While it is probably true that we can justify almost any decision using an approach such as the ones suggested here, it must be borne in mind that we will be judged not solely by our own principles but, to a greater degree, by the principles of those we most affect. 7