24.00 Problems of Philosophy September 21, 2005

Similar documents
Pascal is here expressing a kind of skepticism about the ability of human reason to deliver an answer to this question.

The Problem of Evil not If God exists, she'd be OOG. If an OOG being exists, there would be no evil. God exists.

LECTURE 7: THE EXISTENCE OF GOD & THE REALITY OF EVIL:

The Wager by Blaise Pascal

Atheism. Richland Creek Community Church

PRAYING FOR OTHER PEOPLE

Year 11 Revision. Complete the range of questions set within class and revise using the revision guides, working around a range of techniques.

Reality in the Eyes of Descartes and Berkeley. By: Nada Shokry 5/21/2013 AUC - Philosophy

Cosmological Arguments for the Existence of God S. Clarke

Kant s deontological ethics

Read this syllabus very carefully. If there are any reasons why you cannot comply with what I am requiring, then talk with me about this at once.

You will by now not be surprised that a version of the teleological argument can be found in the writings of Thomas Aquinas.

UNDERSTANDING OTHER RELIGIONS Week 3: Islam 1. LEADER PREPARATION

PURPOSE OF LIFE What Does Islam Say About Life's Purpose?

HarperOne Reading and Discussion Guide for The Weight of Glory. Reading and Discussion Guide for. The Weight of Glory. C. S. Lewis.

Critical Analysis So what does that REALLY mean?

Playing with Numbers

Phil 4800 Notes #1: Rational Choice & Framing

LESSON TITLE: A Story about Investing. THEME: We should share the love of Jesus! SCRIPTURE: Luke 19:11-27 CHILDREN S DEVOTIONS FOR THE WEEK OF:

The 5 P s in Problem Solving *prob lem: a source of perplexity, distress, or vexation. *solve: to find a solution, explanation, or answer for

HarperOne Reading and Discussion Guide for The Problem of Pain. Reading and Discussion Guide for. C. S. Lewis

Love the Lord your God... with all your mind. Mathew 22:37

KNOWING GOD PERSONALLY

Reality 2: God Pursues a Continuing Love Relationship with You that is Real and Personal

WRITING PROOFS. Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology

Acts 11 : 1-18 Sermon

Truth Focus Statements for the Twelve Healing Code Categories

Religion and Science

Devotion NT273 CHILDREN S DEVOTIONS FOR THE WEEK OF: LESSON TITLE: The Garden of Gethsemane. THEME: We always need to pray! SCRIPTURE: Luke 22:39-53

3. Mathematical Induction

Section #7: NOAH: A MAN OF FAITH

The subtitle of Ravi Zacharias book, Jesus Among Other Gods, is The

~SHARING MY PERSONAL PERSPECTIVE~

Jesus and the Counsellor in John s Gospel

The Doctor-Patient Relationship

Decision Making under Uncertainty

Sermon Promise in Unexpected Places Genesis 39:1-23, September 21, 2014

Session 1 : Alive - Ephesians 2:1-10

Divine command theory

WHAT EVERY CHRISTIAN NEEDS TO KNOW. Lesson 20. Spiritual Gifts

Key Words Immortality: endless life or existence; life after death

Jesus Parables in Chronological Order. Four Kingdom of Heaven Parables. Parable #16 Matthew 13:44 Hidden Treasure

National Quali cations 2014

Jesus Parables in Chronological Order. Parable #34 ~ Matthew 20:1-16 ~ Workers in the Vineyard ~ Scripture

Relative and Absolute Change Percentages

In an article titled Ethical Absolutism and the

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 2

IS JESUS THE ONLY WAY?

THIS IS IT. This week's Living Abundantly message is short - one sentence - but super powerful. This one changed my life. It's called THIS IS IT.

Responding to Arguments against the Existence of God Based on Evil

INTELLECTUAL APPROACHES

Chapter 1 How would you describe worship and its impact in your life? p. 14

Jesus Parables in Chronological Order. Parable #41 ~ Matthew 24:32-35 ~ Signs From a Fig Tree ~ Scripture

4 Possessive/Jealous. Men in Relationships

Jesus is The Way. A copy of the activity sheet for each child A hole-punch Crayons, scissors, yarn, and double-sided tape Duct tape for one activity

1.6 The Order of Operations

A Short Guide to Significant Figures

Job s Faith, Part 4 Eliphaz, Bildad and Zophar

WELCOME TO GOD S FAMILY

Spiritually Enabled John 16:13

How to Simplify Your Life

LESSON TITLE: Jesus Visits Mary and Martha THEME: Jesus wants us to spend time with \ Him. SCRIPTURE: Luke 10:38-42

WHAT MATTERS MOST THE BEST USE OF LIFE IS LOVE

Your Strength Comes from God

MILL. The principle of utility determines the rightness of acts (or rules of action?) by their effect on the total happiness.

15 Most Typically Used Interview Questions and Answers

KEY QUESTIONS Lesson 1 - Creation and the Environment

The Cosmological Argument for the Existence of God Gerry J Hughes

The Fruit of the Spirit is Love

Understanding Options: Calls and Puts

STUDY GUIDE. for I AM by Ken Hemphill

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products

Handout #1: Mathematical Reasoning

Quality Meets the CEO

Writing Thesis Defense Papers

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Cultural Relativism. 1. What is Cultural Relativism? 2. Is Cultural Relativism true? 3. What can we learn from Cultural Relativism?

Philosophical argument

LECTURES ON REAL OPTIONS: PART I BASIC CONCEPTS

MOST FREQUENTLY ASKED INTERVIEW QUESTIONS. 1. Why don t you tell me about yourself? 2. Why should I hire you?

WILL WE BE MARRIED IN THE LIFE AFTER DEATH?

Chapter 11 Number Theory

The Gospel & The Scholars. For most of us, our college days are a time in our lives centered around study, research,

So let us begin our quest to find the holy grail of real analysis.

Decision Analysis. Here is the statement of the problem:

Independent samples t-test. Dr. Tom Pierce Radford University

OVERCOMING THE FEAR OF REJECTION Series: Freedom From Your Fears - Part 7 of 10

Blessing & Curse, How Much Is In Our Own Hands? Commentary to Parashat Ki Tavo

Critical Study David Benatar. Better Never To Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006)

5 DARWIN, EVOLUTION & FAITH 850L

ASVAB Study Guide. Peter Shawn White

Practical Jealousy Management

Critical analysis. Be more critical! More analysis needed! That s what my tutors say about my essays. I m not really sure what they mean.

PERSONAL EVANGELISM: Why Are We So Lost? 1. Why Are We So Lost?

WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT?

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2015

LESSON TITLE: Taming the Tongue. THEME: God wants us to watch what we say. SCRIPTURE: James 3:1-12 CHILDREN S DEVOTIONS FOR THE WEEK OF:

How satan stops Christians from receiving the Prayer Language.

Making Your Best Right Decisions

The Refutation of Relativism

Transcription:

24.00 Problems of Philosophy September 21, 2005 Pascal's Wager September 26, 2005 I. Recap Does God exist? Rational theism (Anselm): we can prove that God exists with the ontological argument. Irrational theism: belief in God despite compelling evidence that God doesn t exist. Arational theism: we cannot prove that God exists; compelling evidence is not available, but we can provide pragmatic grounds for belief in God. II. Kinds of Reasons It may have occurred to you that we are going about considering the existence of God in a misguided way. Few people believe in a Supreme Being because they were forced to this conclusion by powerful arguments. For many, part of the religious attitude is that to believe in God is to put yourself at risk, trusting that you will not be let down in the end. This at any rate is Pascal s view: Who will condemn Christians for being unable to give rational grounds for their belief, professing as they do a religion for which they cannot give rational grounds? They declare that it is a folly [to prove it], and then you complain that they do not prove it. If they did prove it they would not be keeping their word. (RR 115) So the whole approach in terms of proof and evidence is arguably beside the point. What we have before us is not a theoretical question about what is or is not likely to be true, but a practical question about how to act: granted that God is not supported by the evidence, shall we accept God or shan t we? But if the question is not a theoretical one but a practical one, we have to approach it in a whole different way. To find out what is likely to be true, we look for evidence. To find out which of two possible actions to perform, we ask, which action is likely to confer the greater benefit? To continue along these lines, we need to further complicate the distinction drawn in the first lecture. Remember we distinguished: motivating reasons v. justifying reasons. I wanted to distinguish motivating reasons from justifying reasons because I wanted us to focus not on what causes us to believe something (I might be caused to believe something by even a bump on the head!), but one s basis for believing it, i.e., the reasons that seem to justify the claim in question. Normally when we consider whether to believe something, what matters is the evidence we have for it and the likelihood of its truth. But coming to believe something can also be regarded as a kind of action that may or may not be practically justified. This suggests a further distinction among justifying reasons: evidential reasons (reasons giving evidence that the claim in question is true); practical reasons (reasons for action, and for belief when believe is considered as a kind of action). For example, let vegetarianism be the belief that it is wrong to eat meat. Contrast: I accept vegetarianism because as a teenager it was a way for me to rebel against my father. (motivating/generating reason) I accept vegetarianism because causing unnecessary pain and suffering to animals is wrong and eating meat causes such pain and suffering. (evidential reason) I accept vegetarianism because it helps me stay healthy. (practical reason)

Just to get the hang of this, suppose that you are facing a decision under conditions of uncertainty : suppose the question is whether to take an umbrella or not, on a day when the chance of rain is one half. Since the value of taking as opposed to leaving the umbrella will be different depending on whether or not it rains, we might start out by listing all the possible scenarios, and how well things work out for us in all of them. There are four: taking and rain, taking and dry, leaving and rain, and leaving and dry. How should we decide? Here s a proposal: Practical Rationality Principle: The practically rational thing to do is the thing with the highest expected value, where the expected value (x) = the sum of the values of the various possible outcomes that x could give rise to, weighted according to their probabilities. Should I take an umbrella along to class on a day when the chance of rain is 50%? poss. circumstances: Rain Dry Expected Value= options: TAKE 10-4 3 << LEAVE -20 2-9 EV(TAKE) = value of taking if rain x chance of rain + value of taking if dry x chance of dry = 10 x.50 + -4 x.50 = 3 EV(LEAVE) = value of leaving if rain x chance of rain + value of leaving if dry x chance of dry = -20 x.50 + 2 x.50 = -9. This suggests you should take the umbrella. But if the probability of rain is different, (or the values you assign to the possible outcomes) you could reach a different result. E.g., if the probability of rain is only 10%: EV(TAKE) = 1 + -3.6 = -2.6 EV (LEAVE) = -2 + 1.8 = -.2 << III. The Wager Suppose now that we apply this procedure to theism. Let's start by being as neutral as possible about the chances of God's existence. If we don't have evidence either way, suppose that the probability of God's existence is 50%. Assuming that God exists, believers are rewarded with eternal joy and happiness as a result of being united with their Lord in heaven. Eternal bliss is infinitely valuable so the first box gets filled like this:. Disbelievers, let s assume, are punished with eternal damnation and torment, in a place where there is weeping and wailing and gnashing of teeth. This is infinitely horrible so the second box gets filled like this: -. Now what if God does not exist? Then the believer, let s assume, suffers some inconvenience as a function of his/her observant lifestyle, and the nonbeliever, let s assume enjoys an equal amount of pleasure. Then we have: poss. circumstances: God exists No God Expected Value= options: BEL -20 DON'T BEL - 20 - EV(BEL) 24.00: Problems of Philosophy 2

= value of BEL if God exists x prob. God exists + value of DON'T BEL if no God x prob. no God = x.5 + -20 x.5 = EV(DON'T BEL) = value of DON'T BEL if God exists x prob. God exists + value of DON'T BEL if no God x prob. no God. = - x.50 + 20 x.50 = - It looks like there s a clear, indeed an infinitely large, advantage to believing! So that s what we should do. In short: 1. Whether to believe in God is not a theoretical decision but a practical one: how should I live my life? 2. The practically rational thing to do is the thing with the highest expected utility. (Practical Rationality Principle) 3. The expected value of theism is higher than that of atheism. 4. Therefore, I should believe in God. IV. Objections A. "Minor" Objections: i. Belief is not under our control. We don't choose whether or not to believe things. ii. The Wager is cynical and God would not reward a theist whose belief is based on it. iii. The probability of God is much smaller than 50%. iv. One s life will be based on a lie if one accepts the Wager and God doesn't exist. B. "Major" Objection: Problem of Too Many Gods So far, following Pascal, we have assumed a very specific sort of God, call him or her the God of Abraham, i.e., the God that many would argue is common to Christianity, Judaism and Islam. But what about the gods of Hinduism and other polytheistic religions? What about the gods worshipped by any of hundreds of different religions around the world? What for that matter about possible gods not worshipped by any religion? Why not an AntiGod who is just like the God of Abraham except in being absolutely evil? Why not an Jealous God who will reward you for believing in him but has an infinitely horrible fate in store for you if you so much as think of believing in the God of Abraham? Or a Shy God who gives you everlasting life provided you don t believe in him or indeed in any Gods, and rains infinite terror on you if you do believe? The trouble is that as far as Pascal s actual reasoning goes, it would seem that we have just as good an argument for believing in many of these other Gods (or, in the case of the Jealous and Shy Gods, disbelieving) as we do for believing in the God of Abraham. Yet to believe in all of them at once makes no practical or theoretical sense. It makes no practical sense because some of these Gods will rain infinite punishment on you if you believe in the others. It makes no theoretical sense because these various Gods actually contradict each other. The Christian God by definition is greater than any other thing, so it logically cannot coexist with the AntiGod. This makes a belief in all the Gods like a belief that it s raining and not raining: a literal contradiction. But how is one to choose which God to believe in? 24.00: Problems of Philosophy 3

i. First Answer: All Gods aren't equally probable Granted that none of these Gods can be ruled out, they aren t all equally probable. Contrary to what Pascal suggests, we do have at least some evidence about these matters. There are various kinds of holy writings (the Torah, the Bible, the Koran, etc.) that are at least partially checkable. Also the very fact that a religion has managed to attract and sustain adherents over thousands of years is a mark in its favor, for one explanation of how this happens is that the religion s God is helping out. So, the proposal is, since the expected utilities of belief in any of these Gods is the same (infinity), believe in the God that the empirical evidence favors. Problem: Even granting that the empirical evidence does some work here, surely it doesn t zero in on a unique God. How to choose between the Gods of the great religions? Can t easily say they re all the same. And even if they were, still the conduct required by these religions is greatly different. How do we decide whether to give our children bar mitzvahs, for example, or rather confirmations? Also, isn t there a problem with believing in the God of Abraham if there s even a tiny chance of a God who will send me to hell if I do? ii. Second Answer: Choose simplest hypothesis. When the data doesn t determine a single answer, what is the rational way to proceed? The scientists will tell us that we should pick the simplest hypothesis of those available. Here it seems that the OOG God, or the particular version of that God advanced by Anselm, has a real advantage. According to Anselm, God is simply an absolutely perfect being. Everything else true of the OOG God, follows from his absolute perfection. Problem: The idea that everything about the OOG God follows from its absolute perfection is doubtful. Does perfection tell us whether God is in time or out of it? More important, does perfection tell us how God wants to be worshipped? This is the kind of thing we need to know if we are to make the decision with the best long term benefits. C. REAL MANY GODS PROBLEM: All of this is relatively minor, however, compared to the real problem. Let s agree that the rational agent should perform the action with the highest expected value. It has appeared thus far that lots of God hypotheses have infinite expected value; the issue is how do we choose between them? Actually though, no God hypothesis has infinite expected value. This can be seen if we take another look at the chart: poss. circumstances: God exists No God options: BEL -20 DON'T BEL - 20 But once the possibility of alternative Gods is thrown into the hopper, the figures in the right hand column become questionable to say the least. Is it really clear that if you believe, and God doesn't exist, then you lose only 20? Because remember, there are various ways it can happen that the God of Abraham doesn t exist. One way is that no God exists; another one way is that the Anti-Abrahamic God exists, and puts you through eternal hell if you believe in the God of Abraham. That s certainly worse than -20!! So we need a new chart: (GA=God of Abraham, AG=Anti-Abrahamic God) probabilities??:.50.10.40 poss. circumstances: GA exists AA exists No God exists options: BEL GA - -20 24.00: Problems of Philosophy 4

DON'T BEL GA - 20 Whatever nonzero probabilities you assign, believing no longer has an advantage over disbelieving. So, let GA have probability.50, AA have probability.10, and no God have probability.40. Then the expected value of believing is EV(BEL GA) = x.50 + - x.10 + -20 x.40 = + - + - 8 And the expected value of disbelieving is EV(DON'T BEL GA) = - x.50 + x.10 + 20 x.40 = + - + 8 The immediate problem here is that mathematically there is no well-defined way to calculate the result, because while infinite numbers can be added there's no well-defined way to subtract them. This suggests that the very project of calculating EV in the context of infinite expected payoffs is misguided. But suppose we bracket that concern. It would certainly seem that here the expected value calculation favors, if anything, disbelieving in GA, since you don t have to pay the cost of religious practice. The advantage of believing in GA over disbelieving has entirely dissipated. Alternatively, one might argue that no God is favored; with these infinite values around, the finite ones can be ignored, hence we get the same result in both cases. But in any case, there is no basis for saying that belief in the God of Abraham is warranted on the basis of the Wager. 24.00: Problems of Philosophy 5