Sleeping Beauty: in defence of Elga

Similar documents
When Betting Odds and Credences Come Apart: More Worries for Dutch Book Arguments

Self-locating belief and the Sleeping Beauty problem

Sleeping Beauty, as described on wikipedia, citing Arnold

Lecture 8 The Subjective Theory of Betting on Theories

One natural response would be to cite evidence of past mornings, and give something like the following argument:

Pascal is here expressing a kind of skepticism about the ability of human reason to deliver an answer to this question.

In Defense of Kantian Moral Theory Nader Shoaibi University of California, Berkeley

Mathematical goals. Starting points. Materials required. Time needed

Reality in the Eyes of Descartes and Berkeley. By: Nada Shokry 5/21/2013 AUC - Philosophy

Arguments and Dialogues

Locke s psychological theory of personal identity

In an article titled Ethical Absolutism and the

Mathematical Induction

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 10

Lecture 9 Maher on Inductive Probability

Killing And Letting Die

A Few Basics of Probability

Time and Causation in Gödel s Universe.

CONCEPTUAL CONTINGENCY AND ABSTRACT EXISTENCE

You will by now not be surprised that a version of the teleological argument can be found in the writings of Thomas Aquinas.

Against Zangwill s Extreme Formalism About Inorganic Nature

Why Betting Odds and Credences Come Apart

Read this syllabus very carefully. If there are any reasons why you cannot comply with what I am requiring, then talk with me about this at once.

P1. All of the students will understand validity P2. You are one of the students C. You will understand validity

Reply to French and Genone Symposium on Naïve Realism and Illusion The Brains Blog, January Boyd Millar

Einstein s Theory of Special Relativity Made Relatively Simple!

Writing Thesis Defense Papers

Logic and Reasoning Practice Final Exam Spring Section Number

WRITING PROOFS. Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology

How should we think about the testimony of others? Is it reducible to other kinds of evidence?

3. Mathematical Induction

Independent samples t-test. Dr. Tom Pierce Radford University

What Is Induction and Why Study It?

Linear Programming Notes VII Sensitivity Analysis

A simple solution to the hardest logic puzzle ever

CRITICAL THINKING REASONS FOR BELIEF AND DOUBT (VAUGHN CH. 4)

Wald s Identity. by Jeffery Hein. Dartmouth College, Math 100

Review. Bayesianism and Reliability. Today s Class

Herxheimer Reaction Record. Patient s Name: Available on Request Start Date: July 2, 2005

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican, Hertford College. Lecture 3: Induction

Introduction to Hypothesis Testing

Philosophical argument

Hypothesis testing. c 2014, Jeffrey S. Simonoff 1

MTH6120 Further Topics in Mathematical Finance Lesson 2

6.3 Conditional Probability and Independence

MOST FREQUENTLY ASKED INTERVIEW QUESTIONS. 1. Why don t you tell me about yourself? 2. Why should I hire you?

On the Paradox of the Question

Introduction to Hypothesis Testing OPRE 6301

(Refer Slide Time: 2:03)

Critical Study David Benatar. Better Never To Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006)

Causality and the Doomsday Argument

The Bayesian Approach to the Philosophy of Science

The Cable Guy Paradox

Does rationality consist in responding correctly to reasons? John Broome Journal of Moral Philosophy, 4 (2007), pp

Practical Jealousy Management

1/9. Locke 1: Critique of Innate Ideas

ASVAB Study Guide. Peter Shawn White

6th Grade Lesson Plan: Probably Probability

Critical Analysis So what does that REALLY mean?

Conditional Probability, Hypothesis Testing, and the Monty Hall Problem

ON WHITCOMB S GROUNDING ARGUMENT FOR ATHEISM Joshua Rasmussen Andrew Cullison Daniel Howard-Snyder

Phil 420: Metaphysics Spring [Handout 4] Hilary Putnam: Why There Isn t A Ready-Made World

WHAT MAKES SOMEONE'S LIFE GO BEST Derek Parfit (From Parfit, Reasons and Persons, 1984)

1.7 Graphs of Functions

Writing an essay. This seems obvious - but it is surprising how many people don't really do this.

Human Resources Training. Performance Management Training Module 2: Managing Employee Performance

Continued Fractions and the Euclidean Algorithm

Plato gives another argument for this claiming, relating to the nature of knowledge, which we will return to in the next section.

Book Review of Rosenhouse, The Monty Hall Problem. Leslie Burkholder 1

Decision Making under Uncertainty

Mathematical Induction. Mary Barnes Sue Gordon

Brewer s Conjecture and the Feasibility of Consistent, Available, Partition-Tolerant Web Services

The Slate Is Not Empty: Descartes and Locke on Innate Ideas

Basic Proof Techniques

Scientific Knowledge: Truth, Induction and Falsification Jennifer Booth

There is a simple equation for calculating dilutions. It is also easy to present the logic of the equation.

1. The Fly In The Ointment

Mathematical Induction

Approaches to Apologetics

OPTIMALITY THEORY AND THE THREE LAWS OF ROBOTICS 1

Lecture Note 7: Revealed Preference and Consumer Welfare

Module Five Critical Thinking

Use Your Master s Thesis Supervisor

Understanding Options: Calls and Puts

LESSON TITLE: A Story about Investing. THEME: We should share the love of Jesus! SCRIPTURE: Luke 19:11-27 CHILDREN S DEVOTIONS FOR THE WEEK OF:

WRITING A CRITICAL ARTICLE REVIEW

Acts 11 : 1-18 Sermon

Taxes are dealt with and collected by HM Revenue and Customs (HMRC). There are different types of tax, which include those listed below.

ISAAC LEVI JAAKKO HINTIKKA

English as a Second Language Podcast ESL Podcast 292 Business Insurance

Chapter 21: The Discounted Utility Model

Web Appendix for Reference-Dependent Consumption Plans by Botond Kőszegi and Matthew Rabin

COMP6053 lecture: Relationship between two variables: correlation, covariance and r-squared.

Supply and Demand in the Market for Money: The Liquidity Preference Framework

HarperOne Reading and Discussion Guide for The Weight of Glory. Reading and Discussion Guide for. The Weight of Glory. C. S. Lewis.

NOT RECOMMENDED FOR PUBLICATION File Name: 13a0927n.06. No UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) )

Binomial Sampling and the Binomial Distribution

Science and Religion

The Stewardship Role of Accounting

Descriptive Statistics and Measurement Scales

Transcription:

292 cian dorr References Tarski, A. 1956. The concept of truth in formalized languages. In his Logic, Semantics and Metamathematics, 152 375. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Tarski, A. 1944. The semantic conception of truth. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 4: 341 75. Sleeping Beauty: in defence of Elga Cian Dorr The story of the Sleeping Beauty, in the version I will be concerned with, is this: Sleeping Beauty is a paradigm of rationality. On Sunday she learns for certain that she is to be the subject of an experiment. The experimenters will wake her up on Monday morning, and tell her some time later that it is Monday. When she goes back to sleep, they will toss a fair coin. If the outcome of the toss is Heads, they will do nothing. If the outcome is Tails, they will administer a drug whose effect is to destroy all memories from the previous day, so that when she wakes up on Tuesday, she will be unable to tell that it is not Monday. The paradox of the Sleeping Beauty is this: Let P be her credence distribution immediately after waking up on Monday. Let P + be her credence distribution after having been told that it is Monday. Let HEADS be the proposition that the coin lands Heads. Let MONDAY be the centred proposition that it is Monday. Then each of the following claims seems very plausible: (1) P(HEADS) = 1/2 (2) P + (HEADS) = 1/2 (3) P + (HEADS) = P(HEADS MONDAY) (4) P(HEADS not-monday) = 0 (5) 0 < P(MONDAY) < 1 But these propositions are mutually inconsistent, given the probability calculus. Proof P(HEADS) = P(HEADS MONDAY) P(MONDAY) + P(HEADS not- MONDAY) P(not-MONDAY), by (5). P(HEADS) = P(HEADS MONDAY) P(MONDAY), by (4). Analysis 62.4, October 2002, pp. 292 96. Cian Dorr

sleeping beauty: in defence of elga 293 P(HEADS) = P + (HEADS) P(MONDAY), by (3). 1/2 = 1/2 P(MONDAY) by (1) and (2). So P(MONDAY) = 1, contradicting (5). Elga (2000) and Lewis (2001) both accept (3), (4) and (5), and I agree. Elga advocates giving up (1): he claims that P(HEADS) is 1/3, not 1/2. Lewis advocates giving up (2): he claims that P + (HEADS) is 2/3, not 1/2. Elga s case for (2) is based on the principle that when one is certain that a fair coin will be tossed in the future, one ought to believe to degree 1/2 that the outcome will be Heads. I agree that this principle gives us a strong prima facie reason to accept (2). (As Lewis points out, there are certain exotic possibilities, involving prophets, crystal balls and the like, in which this principle seems to fail; but any analogy between these strange cases and Beauty s situation is, to say the least, not obvious.) Nevertheless, I don t think that Elga has given us any reason to accept (2) instead of (1). One s beliefs about the temporal location of a coin-toss are relevant to the question what one should believe about its outcome only because (in the absence of crystal balls) we are limited in the sorts of evidence we can have about future coin-tosses. But often our evidence about coin-tosses we believe to be in the past is limited in the same way, and, when it is, our credence about the outcome of the toss is subject to the same constraint. For example, if I learn from a history-book that a certain fair coin was tossed, but am not told what the outcome was, or given any other information about matters causally connected to the outcome, I should believe to degree 1/2 that this coin landed Heads. So Elga s principle is plausible only because it is derived from a more general, if harder to state, principle to the effect that when one lacks evidence of a certain sort ( inadmissible evidence, in the terminology of Lewis 1980) about the toss of a coin which one knows to be fair, one should believe to degree 1/2 that it lands Heads. Unfortunately, however we fill in the details of this more general principle, it is hard to see how it could support (2) any more strongly than it supports (1). When Beauty is told that it is Monday, it seems intuitively that she gains new evidence without losing any. So however plausible it is that she lacks inadmissible evidence about the coin-toss afterwards, it is at least as plausible that she also lacked inadmissible evidence about the coin-toss to begin with. Thus, we should not expect our intuitive judgments about the constraints on rational belief about coin-tosses to decide between (1) and (2): it is these intuitive judgments that lead to the paradox in the first place. Nevertheless, I am persuaded that Elga s answer is the correct one. What persuades me is the following variation on the story: Again, Sleeping Beauty knows for certain on Sunday that she is to be the subject of an experiment. This time, the experimenters will defi-

294 cian dorr nitely wake her both on Monday and on Tuesday, administering an amnesia-inducing drug between the two awakenings. However, they have two amnesia-inducing drugs, and they will decide which one to administer by tossing a fair coin on Monday night. If the outcome of the toss is Tails, they will administer the amnesia-inducing drug that was used in the original version of the experiment. If the outcome is Heads, they will administer a much weaker amnesia-inducing drug, which merely delays the onset of memories from the previous day, rather than destroying them entirely. If Beauty receives this weaker drug, the first minute of her awakening on Tuesday will be just as it would have been if she had received the stronger drug, but after that the memories of Monday s awakening will come flooding back. She will then realize that it is Tuesday, and that the outcome of the toss must have been Heads. Let Q - be Beauty s credence function immediately after being woken on Monday in the variant case. Clearly Q - should give positive credence to each of the following four hypotheses: H 1 The coin lands Heads and it s Monday H 2 The coin lands Heads and it s Tuesday T 1 The coin lands Tails and it s Monday T 2 The coin lands Tails and it s Tuesday How should this credence be distributed? It seems to me that only one answer to this question is remotely credible: namely, Q - (H 1 ) = Q - (H 2 ) = Q - (T 1 ) = Q - (T 2 ) = 1/4. For during the first minute after she has woken up, the difference between the strong and the weak amnesia drugs is completely irrelevant from Beauty s point of view. Her credences should be just as they would have been if the experimenters had resolved to administer the strong drug in any case, so that nothing at all depended on the outcome of the coin-toss. And surely we must agree that in that case, the four hypotheses should get equal credence. Let Q be Beauty s credence function after a minute has passed on Monday. On the assumption that she has sufficient introspective powers to be absolutely certain that she has not experienced the flooding-back of memories she would have experienced had H 2 been true, Q(H 2 ) = 0. But nothing in her experience during the first minute does anything to discriminate between the other three hypotheses. So the ratio of her credences in H 1, T 1 and T 2 will remain unchanged: that is, her credences in these hypotheses will be updated by conditionalizing on the negation of H 2. Hence, Q(H 1 ) = Q(T 1 ) = Q(T 2 ) = 1/3; so Q(HEADS) = Q(H 1 ) = 1/3. This strikes me as a decisive reason to side with Elga s view about the rational distribution of credence in the original case. Of course, the evi-

sleeping beauty: in defence of elga 295 dence Beauty has after a minute has gone by in the variant case is not exactly the same as the evidence she has immediately after she has woken up in the original case. In the variant case, her evidence includes memories of the minute that has passed since waking up, as well as memories of having been told that the variant experiment, rather than the original one, was to be performed. But could these differences really be relevant to the question what Beauty s credence in HEADS ought to be? I can t see how they could: once a minute has passed, the question whether it is the variant experiment or the original one that is being performed seems utterly immaterial from Beauty s point of view. To support this judgment, we can imagine a series of cases, in which the weaker amnesia drug is made successively weaker and weaker, shortening the time period required for the return of the memories from the previous day; until eventually it is reduced to zero, so that the drug does nothing at all. It is hard to see how any of these steps other than the last one could be decisive in abruptly changing the final distribution of credence from 1/3 2/3 to 1/2 1/2. But it would be crazy to maintain that the difference between an awakening in which one s memories from the previous day are delayed by, say, a tenth of a second, and one in which they are present from the beginning, can have such a pronounced effect on what it is rational for one to believe once one has fully woken up. Moreover, any attempt to draw a significant distinction between this case and the original Sleeping Beauty case seems deeply unfaithful to the phenomenology of waking up. Waking up, even in the absence of amnesia drugs, very often is quite a gradual process; it can take time for one to summon up all the memories relevant to one s current situation (to convince yourself of this, see Proust 1913: 1 9). A credible theory of rationality in belief should not make the facts about the credences one ought to have at the end of this process depend on the precise facts about how the process works. Lewis (2001) argues for (1), on the grounds that on Sunday night Beauty s credence in HEADS was 1/2, and she gains no new evidence relevant to HEADS between Sunday night and Monday morning: in other words, the difference between these two states of evidence is irrelevant to the question to what degree one ought to believe HEADS. By considering the variant case, we can see what is wrong with Lewis s premiss. In the variant case, Beauty s continued failure to remember anything from Monday after the first minute is evidence relevant to HEADS: it decreases her credence in HEADS from 1/2 to 1/3. In Lewis s terms, it is evidence about the future namely, that if the outcome of the toss is Heads, she is not now in it. If something as unspectacular as a lack of memories of a certain sort can constitute evidence relevant to HEADS in the variant case, presumably it can also do so in the original case. The only difference is that

296 eric wiland in the original case, there is no intervening period when she is unsure about her temporal location while still having degree of belief 1/2 in HEADS. But why should that matter? 1 New York University New York, NY 10003-6688, USA cian.dorr@nyu.edu References Elga, A. 2000. Self-locating belief and the Sleeping Beauty problem. Analysis 60: 143 47. Lewis, D. 1980. A subjectivist s guide to objective chance. In Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability, ed. R. C. Jeffrey, vol. 2, 263 93. Berkeley: University of California Press. Repr. in D. Lewis, Philosophical Papers, vol. 2, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986. Lewis, D. 2001. Sleeping Beauty: reply to Elga. Analysis 61: 171 76. Proust, M. 1913. Swann s Way, vol. 1 of In Search of Lost Time. Tr. C. K. S. Moncrieff and T. Kilmartin. Rev. ed. by D. J. Enright. New York: The Modern Library, 1992. 1 Thanks to Adam Elga for several helpful discussions. My greatest debt of gratitude is to David Lewis.