Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Similar documents
Ling 201 Syntax 1. Jirka Hana April 10, 2006

Morphology. Morphology is the study of word formation, of the structure of words. 1. some words can be divided into parts which still have meaning

Syntax: Phrases. 1. The phrase

Syntactic Theory. Background and Transformational Grammar. Dr. Dan Flickinger & PD Dr. Valia Kordoni

LESSON THIRTEEN STRUCTURAL AMBIGUITY. Structural ambiguity is also referred to as syntactic ambiguity or grammatical ambiguity.

SYNTAX: THE ANALYSIS OF SENTENCE STRUCTURE

Noam Chomsky: Aspects of the Theory of Syntax notes

According to the Argentine writer Jorge Luis Borges, in the Celestial Emporium of Benevolent Knowledge, animals are divided

Double Genitives in English

Comparative Analysis on the Armenian and Korean Languages

Chapter 13, Sections Auxiliary Verbs CSLI Publications

Intending, Intention, Intent, Intentional Action, and Acting Intentionally: Comments on Knobe and Burra

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Syntactic and Semantic Differences between Nominal Relative Clauses and Dependent wh-interrogative Clauses

Structure of Clauses. March 9, 2004

Index. 344 Grammar and Language Workbook, Grade 8

A Beautiful Four Days in Berlin Takafumi Maekawa (Ryukoku University)

stress, intonation and pauses and pronounce English sounds correctly. (b) To speak accurately to the listener(s) about one s thoughts and feelings,

Compound Sentences and Coordination

Sentence Structure/Sentence Types HANDOUT

English auxiliary verbs

Rethinking the relationship between transitive and intransitive verbs

The compositional semantics of same

MARY. V NP NP Subject Formation WANT BILL S

Historical Linguistics. Diachronic Analysis. Two Approaches to the Study of Language. Kinds of Language Change. What is Historical Linguistics?

English Descriptive Grammar

English. Universidad Virtual. Curso de sensibilización a la PAEP (Prueba de Admisión a Estudios de Posgrado) Parts of Speech. Nouns.

King Midas & the Golden Touch

Doctoral School of Historical Sciences Dr. Székely Gábor professor Program of Assyiriology Dr. Dezső Tamás habilitate docent

How the Computer Translates. Svetlana Sokolova President and CEO of PROMT, PhD.

How does the problem of relativity relate to Thomas Kuhn s concept of paradigm?

KEY CONCEPTS IN TRANSFORMATIONAL GENERATIVE GRAMMAR

The parts of speech: the basic labels

L130: Chapter 5d. Dr. Shannon Bischoff. Dr. Shannon Bischoff () L130: Chapter 5d 1 / 25

Points of Interference in Learning English as a Second Language

Latin and Greek Elements in English

Morphemes, roots and affixes. 28 October 2011

TERMS. Parts of Speech

The Structure of English Language - Clause Functions

COMPUTATIONAL DATA ANALYSIS FOR SYNTAX

EAP Grammar Competencies Levels 1 6

A System for Labeling Self-Repairs in Speech 1

The syntactic positions of adverbs and the Second Language Acquisition

Structural Ambiguity for English Teachers

Glossary of literacy terms

Understanding Clauses and How to Connect Them to Avoid Fragments, Comma Splices, and Fused Sentences A Grammar Help Handout by Abbie Potter Henry

Paraphrasing controlled English texts

Online Tutoring System For Essay Writing

GUESSING BY LOOKING AT CLUES >> see it

GMAT.cz GMAT.cz KET (Key English Test) Preparating Course Syllabus

How To Understand A Sentence In A Syntactic Analysis

2. PRINCIPLES IN USING CONJUNCTIONS. Conjunction is a word which is used to link or join words, phrases, or clauses.

Electronic offprint from. baltic linguistics. Vol. 3, 2012

Methodological Issues for Interdisciplinary Research

What Is Linguistics? December 1992 Center for Applied Linguistics

Continuous Acceptability, Categorical Grammaticality, and Experimental Syntax

Teaching Vocabulary to Young Learners (Linse, 2005, pp )

SYNTACTIC PATTERNS IN ADVERTISEMENT SLOGANS Vindi Karsita and Aulia Apriana State University of Malang

Cohesive writing 1. Conjunction: linking words What is cohesive writing?

English Syntax: An Introduction

English Appendix 2: Vocabulary, grammar and punctuation

Adjective, Adverb, Noun Clauses. Gerund,Participial and Infinitive Phrases. English Department

Lecture 1: OT An Introduction

Compositionality, of, word-formation

Guidelines for Masters / Magister / MA Theses

TEXT LINGUISTICS: RELEVANT LINGUISTICS? WAM Carstens School of Languages and Arts, Potchefstroom University for CHE

I have eaten. The plums that were in the ice box

Quine on truth by convention

Phrase Structure Rules, Tree Rewriting, and other sources of Recursion Structure within the NP

1. Current situation Describe the problem or opportunity (the need for your proposal).

Generic Proposal Structure

COURSE SYLLABUS ESU 561 ASPECTS OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE. Fall 2014

Transitions between Paragraphs

Linguistics & Cognitive Science

Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DELL AQUILA CENTRO LINGUISTICO DI ATENEO

Elements of Writing Instruction I

Section 8 Foreign Languages. Article 1 OVERALL OBJECTIVE

Useful classroom language for Elementary students. (Fluorescent) light

Teacher training worksheets- Classroom language Pictionary miming definitions game Worksheet 1- General school vocab version

Subordinating Ideas Using Phrases It All Started with Sputnik

Chapter 10 Paraphrasing and Plagiarism

GCSE Speaking Support Meetings. GCSE Polish Speaking. Introduction 2. Guidance 3. Assessment Criteria 4-5. Student 1 - Speaking Commentary 6-7

English Subordinators in Finite Clause: Definition and Classification

Twentieth-century structural linguistics in America *

The Graphical Method: An Example

SHOULD PEOPLE BE ABLE TO TRADEMARK PHRASES?

Outline of today s lecture

Building a Question Classifier for a TREC-Style Question Answering System

Parent Help Booklet. Level 3

LAWS AND GUIDELINES REGARDING YOUR INVOLVEMENT IN SHAPING HEALTH POLICY

TEN RULES OF GRAMMAR AND USAGE THAT YOU SHOULD KNOW

ONLINE ENGLISH LANGUAGE RESOURCES

Efficient Techniques for Improved Data Classification and POS Tagging by Monitoring Extraction, Pruning and Updating of Unknown Foreign Words

Lesson Plan. Date(s)... M Tu W Th F

A Comparative Analysis of Standard American English and British English. with respect to the Auxiliary Verbs

Pupil SPAG Card 1. Terminology for pupils. I Can Date Word

Language Meaning and Use

Parts of Speech. Skills Team, University of Hull

Transcription:

On a Class of Not Ungrammatical Constructions Author(s): D. Terence Langendoen Source: Journal of Linguistics, Vol. 18, No. 1 (Mar., 1982), pp. 107-112 Published by: Cambridge University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4175619 Accessed: 11/05/2009 22:51 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showpublisher?publishercode=cup. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Cambridge University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of Linguistics. http://www.jstor.org

J. Linguistics i8 (I982) 107-112 Printed in Great Britain On a class of not ungrammatical constructions' D. TERENCE LANGENDOEN Brooklyn College and CUNY Graduate Center (Received 3 March I980) Langendoen and Bever (1973) contended that both expressions in (i) are ungrammatical in English, despite the acceptability of the first to native speakers of English. (i) (a) a not unhappy person (b) a not sad person We came to this conclusion because we believed, first, that all grammars of natural languages should be subject to a constraint 'M' that no syntactic rule is able to make use of the morphological structure of lexemes (1973: 402); and, second, that we had shown that no grammar that satisfies M can distinguish the grammaticality of (ia) from that of (ib). Our exact wording of M was as follows: 'no syntactic transformational rule is permitted to make use of the internal'morphological structure of lexical items'. Since the only syntactic rules (of the standard theory, within which we were operating) that are not transformations are base-categorial rules, which by definition make no use of the internal morphological structure of lexical items, the word 'transformational' in our formulation of M is unnecessary. It is also misleading, since it might cause the reader to think that we had in mind only the rules of the transformational component. Rather, we meant all syntactic rules that have transformational power, including lexical-insertion rules. The constraint M, as just formulated, has been incorporated into the more recent versions of the 'lexicalist hypothesis' of Chomsky (1970) and is now widely accepted. It amounts to a doctrine of strict separation between syntax and derivational morphology. Since we could find an explanation in the theory of linguistic performance for the acceptability of (ia) given that it is ungrammatical, but no explanation for the unacceptability of (i b) given that it is grammatical, the conclusion followed that both (ia) and (ib) are ungrammatical, but that (ia) is nonetheless acceptable. Both Aitchison and Bailey (I979) and Bolinger (I980) have disputed this conclusion. Bolinger categorically rejects the possibility that exemplars of a given construction can be both acceptable and ungrammatical. Aitchison and [ I] An earlier version of this paper was read at State University College at Fredonia, New York in December 1979. 0022-2267/82/OOI8-0006$02.00 (? I982 Cambridge University Press 107

D. TERENCE LANGENDOEN Bailey, on the other hand, admit the possibility in principle, but claim that (ia) is not such a case and that a grammar of English that generates (ia) but not (ib) can be constructed. The truth, I believe, lies between these two positions. It may turn out that grammars meeting the stringent requirements of the best linguistic theory (whatever that is) are capable of generating all of the acceptable constructions of each natural language. But this is not something we can know or legislate in advance. Thus, contrary to Bolinger, I prefer to remain open to the possibility of the existence of constructions in a given language whose exemplars are acceptable but ungrammatical. Bach and Harnish (1979: 198-202) also offer discussion and analysis of some other constructions of English whose exemplars are acceptable but possibly ungrammatical. Although I do not accept Bolinger's point of view regarding acceptability and ungrammaticality, I do accept his observation that some of the expressions of a type that Bever and I considered unacceptable are in fact acceptable to native speakers of English, for example a not inordinate amount of money. Some of Bolinger's observations are included in the discussion toward the end of this paper. However, I do not take his claim that the relative acceptability of a not, shall we say, sad turn of events shows that that construction is grammatical to be correct. On the contrary, the amount of 'prosodic schmaltz' (a happy locution for which I am indebted to Bolinger) needed to make that phrase acceptable suggests to me that it is ungrammatical. Aitchison and Bailey, on the other hand, show nothing more than what Bever and I had already shown, namely that there are grammars of English NOT SATISFYING M that generate (Ia) but not (ib). However, their approach to the problem of finding a grammar that generates (I a) but not (ib) can be used to show how such a grammar THAT ALSO SATISFIES M can be constructed. They point out that the only syntactic rule of English that Bever and I claim must make use of the morphological structure of lexemes, if the grammatical status of (I a) is to be distinguished from that of (I b), is RELATIVE-CLAUSE REDUCTION. They then propose that this rule not be considered part of the grammar of English at all, but rather a kind of heuristic device, called a VIA RULE, that merely expresses 'a correspondence between two constructions' (I979: 266). To generate (Ia), they propose the lexical-insertion rule (2). (2) NEG un-adj -+ not un-adj To prevent the derivation of (Ib), they suggest (but do not explicitly propose) the lexical insertion rules in (3). (3) (a) NEG happy -* unhappy NEG sad --happy The resulting grammar has no rule of the transformational component that violates M, but it does have several lexical-insertion rules that do. Thus I08

ON A CLASS OF NOT UNGRAMMATICAL CONSTRUCTIONS Aitchison and Bailey's proposed grammar for generating (ia) but not (ib) also violates M.' However, by turning their lexical analysis around, so that it limits the introduction of prenominal adjectives following not, rather than limiting the introduction of not preceding adjectives, we can come up with a demonstration of how a grammar of English that genuinely satisfies M can be constructed that generates (ia) while at the same time does not generate (ib). Moreover, this ordering of the rules of lexical insertion is consistent with the principles governing lexical insertion in the standard theory (Chomsky, I965). Suppose that prenominal attributive adjective phrases are introduced directly by the base phrase-structure rule schema (4).3 (4) NP -*(DET) (ADJP) N Adjective phrases introduced by (4) may then be expanded by (5). (5) ADJP -4 (NEG) ADJ Among the categorial structures generated by rules in (4) and (5) is (6). (6) NP DET ADJP N NEG ADJ The first lexical-insertion rule that applies to (6) is the rule that inserts not under the category NEG, since that category is the modifier of the most deeply nested constituent in (6). We may now suppose that whether a particular prenominal attributive adjective occurs in the environment of a negative element is determined by a selection restriction.4 Adjectives like unhappy are specified as [ + not N] while adjectives like sad are specified as [- not N]. Accordingly, unhappy, but not sad, may be inserted under the category ADJ in (6). On the next cycle, the determiner a and the head noun person may be inserted, completing the derivation of (ia). Since sadcannot be inserted under the category ADJ in (6), there is no derivation of (ib) with respect to the fragment of English grammar just proposed. This solution to the problem of finding a grammar that generates phrases like (ia), but not those like (ib), is, of course, not the whole story. It remains to (2] Quite possibly, Aitchison & Bailey might have been misled by our original formulation of M, and hence thought that lexical-insertion rules are exempt from it. [1] We do not consider the problem of determining the conditions in English under which attributive adjective phrases follow, rather than precede, the nouns they modify, since it is irrelevant to the questions we are investigating here. [4] Not a strict subcategorization feature, first since not is a lexical item, and second since the environment in which the adjective is inserted is not 'local' to ADJP. IO9

D. TERENCE LANGENDOEN give an account of the distribution of the selectional features [+ not N] and [-not N] among the adjectives of English. The first generalization that must be accounted for is that scalar adjectives that are formed by the addition of one of the negative prefixes un, in, and dis, and perhaps some others, to an adjective stem that occurs independently as a lexeme, and whose meaning is a compositional function of the meanings of the prefix and the stem, are almost all specified as [+not N]. Impious is an exception to this generalization. The second is that nonscalar adjectives, regardless of their morphology, are all specified as [-not N]. Accordingly, both married and umarried have this specification. Finally, of the remaining scalar adjectives, most, but not all, are specified as [-not N]. For example, sad, careless, grateful, untoward, insolent, and industrious, among many others, are all specified as [-not N], while surprising and inordinate, along with a few others, are specified as [+not N]. As Bolinger points out, the specification [+ not N] is almost always associated with an adjective in which the initial syllable is unstressed, but this condition is neither necessary nor sufficient. On the one hand, infinite is specified as [+not N], despite its initial stress; while on the other, industrious is specified as [-not N], despite its lack of initial stress. The subcategorization of adjectives as [+not _N] is paralleled by the subcategorization of sentence adverbs as [ +not ]. Sentence adverb such as unexpectedly and infrequently, which are formed by the addition of the suffix ly to a negatively-prefixed adjective, are specified as [+ not ]. Of the remaining sentence adverbs, only surprisingly is specified as [+not _ ]. The rest, including the near synonym amazingly, are all specified as [-not I. We turn now to a formal account of how the subcategorization features [ +not N] are assigned to adjectives and [? not ] to sentence adverbs. Let us call a lexeme 'simple' if it does not have a lexeme as a proper part, and 'complex' otherwise. Thus, for example, sad and grateful are simple lexemes - note that a simple lexeme need not be monomorphemic - while unhappy (containing the lexeme happy) and surprising (containing the lexeme surprise) are complex ones. Simple lexemes are assigned subcategorizational (including selectional) features directly, whereas complex lexemes are assigned those features on the basis of the features of the lexemes they contain. Both the direct assignment of features to simple lexemes and the indirect assignment of features to complex lexemes are carried out by rules of the word-formation component of the grammar.5 The fact that simple adjectives in English, with few exceptions, are specified as [- not N] suggests that there is a general rule in English that assigns that feature to simple adjectives. Similarly, there are [51 See Bresnan (I978: 21) for an informal statement of a rule for assigning subcategorizational features to past participles in English on the basis of the subcategorization features of the verbs they contain. I IO

ON A CLASS OF NOT UNGRAMMATICAL CONSTRUCTIONS general rules that assign the feature [+not N] to complex adjectives of the form (7), and the feature [-not N] to complex adjectives not of that form.6 (7) [ADJ X[ADJ Y, [+ N],... ]ADJ... ]ADJ, where X is one of the prefixes in, un, dis, and a few others, and Y is a scalar adjective. The result of applying the relevant rule to complex adjectives of the form (7) is given in (8). (8) [ADJ X [ADJ Y, [+ N],... ]ADJ[+not N],.. ]ADJ Nevertheless, a few complex adjectives of the form (7), such as impious, are idiosyncratically assigned the feature [- not N]; and a few complex adjectives not of the form (7), such as surprising and inordinate, are idiosyncratically assigned the feature [+not _N]. These word-formation rules make a subtle prediction concerning structurally ambiguous complex adjectives such as unbendable. They assign to that adjective the structureshown in (9) and (io). (9) [ADJ [vun[vbend]v]v able, [ + N], [-not N],. ]ADJ 'able to be unbent' (I0) [ADJun [ADJ [vbend]vable, [+ N], [-not [+not N],... ]ADJ'unable to be bent' N],... ]ADJ [+ N], In (9), the feature [-not ] is assigned by the rule for complex lexemes that are not of the form (7). In (Io), the feature [-not ] is assigned by the same rule to the contained adjective stem bendable, but the feature [+ not N] is assigned to the lexeme as a whole by the rule for complex lexemes that are of the form (7). Accordingly, while sentence (I I) is ambiguous, (I2) is not; in the latter, unbendable has only the interpretation 'unable to be bent'. (I I) They handed me an unbendable ruler. (12) They handed me a not unbendable ruler. Similar word-formation rules can be set up to account for the assignment of the features [? not _] to sentence adverbs. The feature [+ not ] is assigned to all sentence adverbs that are of the form (I 3), and the feature [-not ] is assigned to all sentence adverbs that are not of that form. (13) [ADV [ADJ X, [+not N],. I.y..]ADV According to this rule, unexpectedly, infrequently, and surprisingly are all assigned the feature [+not ], while sadly, frequently, and amazingly are all assigned the feature [-not ]. The specification of the sentence adverb surprisingly as [+not ], rather than being exceptional, is a consequence of [6] The feature [+ N] in (7) is associated with the contained adjective Y, and is not a feature of the entire adjective XY.

D. TERENCE LANGENDOEN the fact that the adjective stem it contains is a lexeme that is idiosyncratically specified as [+not N]. One may further wonder why the subcategorization of sentence adverbs depends on the subcategorization of the adjective stems they contain. The reason may be the semantic equivalence of sentence adverbs to expressions in which the adjective occurs prenominally (for example, infrequently can be glossed 'at infrequent intervals'). REFERENCES Aitchison, J. & Bailey, G. (I979). Unhappiness about not unhappy people. JL I5. 245-266. Bach, K. & Harnish, R. M. (I979). Linguistic communication and speech acts. Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press. Bolinger, D. L. (I980). A not impartial review of a not impeachable theory: some new adventures of ungrammaticality. In Shuy, R. W. & Shnukal, A. (eds.), Language use and the uses of language. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press. Bresnan, J. (I978). A realistic transformational grammar. In Halle, M., Bresnan, J. & Miller, G. A. (eds.), Linguistic theory and psychological reality. Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press. I-59. Chomsky, N. (I965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press. Chomsky, N. (1970). Remarks on nominalization. In Jacobs, R. A. & Rosenbaum, P. S. (eds.), Readings in English transformational grammar. Waltham, Mass.: Ginn-Blaisdell. 184-221. Langendoen, D. T. & Bever, T. G. (1973). Can a not unhappy person be called a not sad one? In Anderson, S. & Kiparsky, P. (eds.), A Festschriftfor Morris Halle. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston. 392-409. 112