Perception & the external world

Similar documents
Skepticism about the external world & the problem of other minds

One natural response would be to cite evidence of past mornings, and give something like the following argument:

Primary and Secondary Qualities Charles Kaijo

You will by now not be surprised that a version of the teleological argument can be found in the writings of Thomas Aquinas.

Reality in the Eyes of Descartes and Berkeley. By: Nada Shokry 5/21/2013 AUC - Philosophy

1/9. Locke 1: Critique of Innate Ideas

The Slate Is Not Empty: Descartes and Locke on Innate Ideas

Writing Thesis Defense Papers

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican, Hertford College. Lecture 3: Induction

How does the problem of relativity relate to Thomas Kuhn s concept of paradigm?

WHAT IS NLP: A MODEL OF COMMUNICATION AND PERSONALITY

Last time we had arrived at the following provisional interpretation of Aquinas second way:

Philosophical argument

Acts 11 : 1-18 Sermon

Reply to French and Genone Symposium on Naïve Realism and Illusion The Brains Blog, January Boyd Millar

In Defense of Kantian Moral Theory Nader Shoaibi University of California, Berkeley

Problem-Based Group Activities for a Sensation & Perception Course. David S. Kreiner. University of Central Missouri

Common Mistakes in Data Presentation Stephen Few September 4, 2004

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2010

They Say, I Say: The Moves That Matter in Academic Writing

Is there a problem about nonconceptual content?

Processing the Image or Can you Believe what you see? Light and Color for Nonscientists PHYS 1230

The Big Picture. Part One: The Nature of Knowledge Weeks 2-3: What is Knowledge? Week 4: What is Justification?

Pascal is here expressing a kind of skepticism about the ability of human reason to deliver an answer to this question.

Chapter 5: Fallacies. 23 February 2015

3. Mathematical Induction

Quantitative vs. Categorical Data: A Difference Worth Knowing Stephen Few April 2005

Against Zangwill s Extreme Formalism About Inorganic Nature

P R I M A R Y A N D S E C O N D A R Y Q U A L I T I E S

Cultural Relativism. 1. What is Cultural Relativism? 2. Is Cultural Relativism true? 3. What can we learn from Cultural Relativism?

Divine command theory

BBC Learning English Talk about English Business Language To Go Part 1 - Interviews

Locke s psychological theory of personal identity

Time and Causation in Gödel s Universe.

EPISTEMOLOGY. PHILOSOPHY FOR AS.indb 23 16/07/ :10

Using sentence fragments

A Short Course in Logic Example 8

Linear Programming Notes VII Sensitivity Analysis

Read this syllabus very carefully. If there are any reasons why you cannot comply with what I am requiring, then talk with me about this at once.

Locke. Reading Questions Introduction to Locke An Essay Concerning Human Understanding Summary of Locke. Reading Questions

How To Understand The Unity Thesis

Managerial Economics Prof. Trupti Mishra S.J.M. School of Management Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay. Lecture - 13 Consumer Behaviour (Contd )

Math vocabulary can be taught with what Montessorians call the Three Period Lesson.

Objective: Count 10 objects and move between all configurations.

CRITICAL THINKING REASONS FOR BELIEF AND DOUBT (VAUGHN CH. 4)

Nikki White Children s Occupational Therapist Barnet Community Services

Augmented reality enhances learning at Manchester School of Medicine

AN OPINION COMPOSITION

P1. All of the students will understand validity P2. You are one of the students C. You will understand validity

Lecture 2, Human cognition

Perceptual Positions. By Sarah Frossell Published in Rapport Magazine Summer A map is not the territory...

What is knowledge? An exploration of the Justified True Belief model and the challenges introduced by Edmond Gettier.

Quality Meets the CEO

Neutrality s Much Needed Place In Dewey s Two-Part Criterion For Democratic Education

EPISTEMOLOGY: Foundationalism

Plato gives another argument for this claiming, relating to the nature of knowledge, which we will return to in the next section.

ON EXTERNAL OBJECTS By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

Boonin on the Future-Like-Ours Argument against Abortion. Pedro Galvão Centro de Filosofia da Universidade de Lisboa

Planning and Writing Essays

Audit Rotation: Impact on Accountants, Firms & India Inc?

A quick, little online search will tell you that Portland, Oregon, is ranked fifth city in the nation

A Short Course in Logic Zeno s Paradox

The Refutation of Relativism

BERKELEY S ASSESSMENT OF LOCKE S EPISTEMOLOGY 1, 2. George S. Pappas

How should we think about the testimony of others? Is it reducible to other kinds of evidence?

A Step By Step Guide On How To Attract Your Dream Life Now

Practical Jealousy Management

A simpler version of this lesson is covered in the basic version of these teacher notes.

The Top 5 Tips for Being Well Prepared using the Circle of Excellence

Kant s deontological ethics

Building a Better Argument

Polynomial Invariants

Critical Analysis So what does that REALLY mean?

Science and Scientific Reasoning. Critical Thinking

Quine on truth by convention

BUYER S GUIDE. The Unified Communications Buyer s Guide: Four Steps to Prepare for the Modern, Mobile Workforce

SPIN Selling SITUATION PROBLEM IMPLICATION NEED-PAYOFF By Neil Rackham

Materials: Student-paper, pencil, circle manipulatives, white boards, markers Teacher- paper, pencil, circle manipulatives, worksheet

Computational Finance Options

How To Understand The Theory Of Active Portfolio Management

5. Color is used to make the image more appealing by making the city more colorful than it actually is.

Argument Mapping 2: Claims and Reasons

Inductive Reasoning Page 1 of 7. Inductive Reasoning

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 2

Planning a Class Session

In mathematics, there are four attainment targets: using and applying mathematics; number and algebra; shape, space and measures, and handling data.

Self-help guide to recovery for Chronic Fatigue Syndrome and Fibromyalgia

Behavior & Sensory Strategies for Individuals with ASD

The last three chapters introduced three major proof techniques: direct,

Definitions, Identification, and Supportive Professionals

LESSON TITLE: Taming the Tongue. THEME: God wants us to watch what we say. SCRIPTURE: James 3:1-12 CHILDREN S DEVOTIONS FOR THE WEEK OF:

ONLINE SAFETY TEACHER S GUIDE:

English 10 Of Mice and Men Chapter 1 Questions (16pts) 2. List words that describe Lennie. What animal is he compared to?

Ep #19: Thought Management

WRITING PROOFS. Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology

Decimal Notations for Fractions Number and Operations Fractions /4.NF

Maslow s Hierarchy of Needs and Purchasing

Through Faith. Lesson Text: Ephesians 2:8-10

Design Analysis of Everyday Thing: Nintendo Wii Remote

CONCEPTUAL CONTINGENCY AND ABSTRACT EXISTENCE

Transcription:

Perception & the external world

Over the course of the last few weeks of class, we have been discussing a variety of questions about the nature of human beings -- these have included questions about the nature of persons, and the nature of human free will. Beginning today we will be spending a few classes on the nature of the relationship between human beings and the world we (seem to) inhabit. The first question we will address is: what, if anything, can we know about the world outside of ourselves? It is natural to think that, if we do know anything about the world outside of us, we have this knowledge through perceptual experience of the world -- by seeing, hearing, tasting, smelling, and feeling it. Accordingly, we will begin our discussion of our knowledge of the external world by asking a few questions about perception. In particular, we will be asking: given that a perceptual experience is an awareness of something, what sorts of things are we directly aware of in perceptual experience? This might seem to be an easy question. In visual experiences, we are aware of (among other things) colors and shapes; in auditory perception we are aware of loudness, pitch, and timbre; in tactile experience we are aware of texture and temperature; and so on.

The first question we will address is: what, if anything, can we know about the world outside of ourselves? It is natural to think that, if we do know anything about the world outside of us, we have this knowledge through perceptual experience of the world -- by seeing, hearing, tasting, smelling, and feeling it. Accordingly, we will begin our discussion of our knowledge of the external world by asking a few questions about perception. In particular, we will be asking: given that a perceptual experience is an awareness of something, what sorts of things are we directly aware of in perceptual experience? This might seem to be an easy question. In visual experiences, we are aware of (among other things) colors and shapes; in auditory perception we are aware of loudness, pitch, and timbre; in tactile experience we are aware of texture and temperature; and so on. However, this is not the hard part about understanding perceptual awareness. Let s use sensible qualities as a term for the properties that we are aware of in sense experience. Then we can concede that it is pretty easy to list the sensible qualities; what is hard is to understand what these sensible qualities are. Here there seem to be two ways we could go: Objectivism about sensible qualities Sensible qualities are properties of things in the environment around the perceiver. Whether or not those things exist, and have those properties, is independent of their being perceived. Subjectivism about sensible qualities While sensible qualities seem to be properties which things could have independently of their being perceived, in fact they are in our minds -- they are properties of our perceptual experiences, and not of anything which could exist independently of being perceived.

However, this is not the hard part about understanding perceptual awareness. Let s use sensible qualities as a term for the properties that we are aware of in sense experience. Then we can concede that it is pretty easy to list the sensible qualities; what is hard is to understand what these sensible qualities are. Objectivism about sensible qualities Sensible qualities are properties of things in the environment around the perceiver. Whether or not those things exist, and have those properties, is independent of their being perceived. Subjectivism about sensible qualities While sensible qualities seem to be properties which things could have independently of their being perceived, in fact they are in our minds -- they are properties of our perceptual experiences, and not properties things could have independently of their being perceived. Objectivism certainly has a good claim to being the common sense view of sense perception. Indeed, it might be hard to understand what the subjectivist view even means. A few examples of cases in which sensible qualities really do seem to be in the mind might help.

The Hermann grid illusion

However, this is not the hard part about understanding perceptual awareness. Let s use sensible qualities as a term for the properties that we are aware of in sense experience. Then we can concede that it is pretty easy to list the sensible qualities; what is hard is to understand what these sensible qualities are. Objectivism about sensible qualities Sensible qualities are properties of things in the environment around the perceiver. Whether or not those things exist, and have those properties, is independent of their being perceived. Subjectivism about sensible qualities While sensible qualities seem to be properties which things could have independently of their being perceived, in fact they are in our minds -- they are properties of our perceptual experiences, and not properties things could have independently of their being perceived. Objectivism certainly has a good claim to being the common sense view of sense perception. Indeed, it might be hard to understand what the subjectivist view even means. A few examples of cases in which sensible qualities really do seem to be in the mind might help. In each of these cases, we seem to be visually aware of some sensible quality -- for example, the changing colors of the dots on the grid in the second case, or the movement of the concentric circles in the third case -- which is not a property which the object being perceived has independently of being perceived. In such a case, we might say that our sensory systems are projecting the property onto the object. Or, in other words, that the sensible quality is just in our minds.

Objectivism about sensible qualities Sensible qualities are properties of things in the environment around the perceiver. Whether or not those things exist, and have those properties, is independent of their being perceived. Subjectivism about sensible qualities While sensible qualities seem to be properties which things could have independently of their being perceived, in fact they are in our minds -- they are properties of our perceptual experiences, and not properties things could have independently of their being perceived. Objectivism certainly has a good claim to being the common sense view of sense perception. Indeed, it might be hard to understand what the subjectivist view even means. A few examples of cases in which sensible qualities really do seem to be in the mind might help. In each of these cases, we seem to be visually aware of some sensible quality -- for example, the changing colors of the dots on the grid in the second case, or the movement of the concentric circles in the third case -- which is not a property which the object being perceived has independently of being perceived. In such a case, we might say that our sensory systems are projecting the property onto the object. Or, in other words, that the sensible quality is just in our minds. The subjectivist can be understood as saying that all perception of sensible qualities is like this: every time we, for example, see color, we are seeing something which is, strictly speaking, just in our minds, and which we only project onto the world. One reason for endorsing subjectivism is given by George Berkeley, in the optional reading for today.

Objectivism about sensible qualities Sensible qualities are properties of things in the environment around the perceiver. Whether or not those things exist, and have those properties, is independent of their being perceived. Subjectivism about sensible qualities While sensible qualities seem to be properties which things could have independently of their being perceived, in fact they are in our minds -- they are properties of our perceptual experiences, and not properties things could have independently of their being perceived. One reason for endorsing subjectivism is given by George Berkeley, in the optional reading for today. Focusing on the case of the perception of color, Berkeley emphasized the relativity of perception, using examples like the colors of clouds. Clouds might appear from the ground to be red and purple at sunset, but a moment earlier appear to be a very different color; and, from close up, they might look different still. But if the clouds really have a color, at most one of these perceptual experiences must be accurate. Berkeley s challenge is to come up with a nonarbitrary way of distinguishing the real from the apparent colors of things.

Objectivism about sensible qualities Sensible qualities are properties of things in the environment around the perceiver. Whether or not those things exist, and have those properties, is independent of their being perceived. Subjectivism about sensible qualities While sensible qualities seem to be properties which things could have independently of their being perceived, in fact they are in our minds -- they are properties of our perceptual experiences, and not properties things could have independently of their being perceived. One reason for endorsing subjectivism is given by George Berkeley, in the optional reading for today. Clouds might appear from the ground to be red and purple at sunset, but a moment earlier appear to be a very different color; and, from close up, they might look different still. But if the clouds really have a color, at most one of these perceptual experiences must be accurate. Berkeley s challenge is to come up with a nonarbitrary way of distinguishing the real from the apparent colors of things. This is harder to do than one might think, especially when one thinks about the colors that things appear to have under microscopes, and the colors of things as perceived by non-human animals. Is one of these ways of perceiving color really the right way? If not, it is hard to escape subjectivism about color: the view that when we are seeing colors, we are seeing something in our mind rather than a property of external objects.

Objectivism about sensible qualities Sensible qualities are properties of things in the environment around the perceiver. Whether or not those things exist, and have those properties, is independent of their being perceived. Subjectivism about sensible qualities While sensible qualities seem to be properties which things could have independently of their being perceived, in fact they are in our minds -- they are properties of our perceptual experiences, and not properties things could have independently of their being perceived. Let s think a bit more about what subjectivism about color might mean. If colors are not properties of external objects, then what are they properties of? What things really are red, if not objects in my environment? A natural answer to this question is: they are properties of our own ideas. In sense perception, on this sort of view, we are really only immediately aware of our own ideas and their properties. These ideas are often called sense data, and the accompanying theory of perception the sense datum theory of perception. This theory is also suggested by cases of illusion, like the ones discussed earlier. Remember the experience in which the concentric circles seemed to be moving relative to each other. When you were having that experience, you were aware of something which was moving; but this thing cannot be the images of the concentric circles flashed on the screen, since those were not moving. So whatever was moving must have been something internal to your mind -- a sense datum. And it seems odd to think that in this case you were perceiving one of your own ideas, whereas in the moment before the circles seem to move, you weren t. Hence reflection on cases of illusion, as well as normal cases of color perception, seems to lead us to the sense datum theory of perception.

The sense datum theory of perception: the theory that in perceptual experiences, we are only immediately aware of our own ideas (called sense data ). Let s think about some of the consequences of this theory of perception for our knowledge of the world around us. How, on this sort of view, might perceptual experiences give us knowledge of our environments? Imagine that I am having a visual experience of an apple. Really, if the sense datum theory is correct, I am having a visual experience of a sense datum. So our question is: how can my awareness of the properties of that sense datum give me knowledge of the properties of the external object, the apple? It seems that to get such knowledge, I must know something of the form: if I am experiencing a sense datum which is such-and-such, then this is (probably) caused by an external object which is so-and-so. In this case, for example, I might know that if I am aware of a reddish circular sense datum, then this is probably caused by a ripe apple. But, as Nagel says, it is hard to see how we could know this sort of thing.

The sense datum theory of perception: the theory that in perceptual experiences, we are only immediately aware of our own ideas (called sense data ). It seems that to get such knowledge, I must know something of the form: if I am experiencing a sense datum which is such-and-such, then this is (probably) caused by an external object which is so-and-so. In this case, for example, I might know that if I am aware of a reddish circular sense datum, then this is probably caused by a ripe apple. But, as Nagel says, it is hard to see how we could know this sort of thing.

The sense datum theory of perception: the theory that in perceptual experiences, we are only immediately aware of our own ideas (called sense data ). It seems that to get such knowledge, I must know something of the form: if I am experiencing a sense datum which is such-and-such, then this is (probably) caused by an external object which is so-and-so. In this case, for example, I might know that if I am aware of a reddish circular sense datum, then this is probably caused by a ripe apple. But, as Nagel says, it is hard to see how we could know this sort of thing. The worry is this: if I only get information about my environment through sense perception, and if sense perception only ever gives me awareness of my own sense data, how can I know anything about the relationship between those sense data and external objects? How, for example, can I know that sense data of a certain sort are usually caused by ripe apples? A tempting reply is: because in the past when I have seen sense data of this sort, this has been followed by a biting sensation, followed by pleasant taste sensations. Does this answer the challenge?

This line of reasoning seems to show that the sense datum theory of perception leads to a surprising skeptical conclusion: Skepticism about our knowledge of the external world We have no knowledge of the properties of things outside our own minds. Nagel also discusses another powerful line of argument for this skeptical conclusion which, unlike the argument we just discussed, does not assume the sense datum theory of perception. This argument begins with the invocation of a familiar sort of thought experiment.

Skepticism about our knowledge of the external world We have no knowledge of the properties of things outside our own minds. This argument begins with the invocation of a familiar sort of thought experiment.

Skepticism about our knowledge of the external world We have no knowledge of the properties of things outside our own minds. This argument begins with the invocation of a familiar sort of thought experiment. The question posed in this passage is one which was posed by Descartes: how do you know that your perceptual experiences are not a kind of dream, or complex illusion? But why, you might ask, is this supposed to be such a hard question to answer? Nagel s answer is evident from question which begins the passage we just read. He asks: Would things seem any different to you if in fact you were having a very long and detailed dream? His implied answer is: No. We can imagine having a dream which was, in every way, indistinguishable from our present experiences. The question we now want to ask is: if Nagel is right in this claim about indistinguishability, why would this indicate that we have no knowledge of the existence of an external world? What is the connection between indistinguishability and knowledge?

Skepticism about our knowledge of the external world We have no knowledge of the properties of things outside our own minds. This argument begins with the invocation of a familiar sort of thought experiment. The question we now want to ask is: if Nagel is right in this claim about indistinguishability, why would this indicate that we have no knowledge of the existence of an external world? What is the connection between indistinguishability and knowledge? The connection seems to be something like this: If I cannot distinguish between situation A and situation B, then I cannot know which of situation A and situation B I am in. Can you think of any examples which would count in favor of, or against, this sort of principle connecting indistinguishability and knowledge?

Skepticism about our knowledge of the external world We have no knowledge of the properties of things outside our own minds. To see how a principle of this sort might lead to the skeptical conclusion, let s imagine two scenarios of the sort that Nagel and Descartes had in mind. If I cannot distinguish between situation A and situation B, then I cannot know which of situation A and situation B I am in. Imagine that you are having a visual experience which seems to be a visual experience of your hands. Let s use REALITY and DREAMWORLD as names for the following two possible scenarios: let REALITY be a world in which I have just the experiences I have had, and these more or less accurately reflect a world of external objects -- so, in particular, I am now accurately perceiving my hands; let DREAMWORLD be a world in which I have just the experiences I have had, but that these are a part of a long and detailed dream, and so do not reflect the existence of any world of external objects -- and, in particular, I have no hands, so that my current visual experience is an illusion. We can then argue as follows: 1. REALITY and DREAMWORLD are indistinguishable. 2. If I cannot distinguish between two situations, then I do not know which of those situations I am in. 3. I do not know which of REALITY and DREAMWORLD I am in. (1,2) C. I do not know whether I have hands. (3) Obviously, this argument does not rely on any special features of my hands; it could be generalized to show that I can t know anything about any object external to my mind. So it appears to be a strong argument for skepticism.

Skepticism about our knowledge of the external world We have no knowledge of the properties of things outside our own minds. 1. REALITY and DREAMWORLD are indistinguishable. 2. If I cannot distinguish between two situations, then I do not know which of those situations I am in. 3. I do not know which of REALITY and DREAMWORLD I am in. (1,2) C. I do not know whether I have hands. (3) If I cannot distinguish between situation A and situation B, then I cannot know which of situation A and situation B I am in. One response to this argument is simply to grant the conclusion: maybe we don t really know that we have hands -- but maybe it is still rational for us to go on believing that we do. This is difficult to believe -- outside the philosophy classroom, we do really take ourselves to have knowledge of the existence of our hands. But there is also a further problem: just as the above principle about indistinguishability and knowledge, which figures in the argument as premise (2), seems plausible, the following principles seem plausible: 2A. If I cannot distinguish between two situations, then I have no justification for believing that I am in one rather than the other. 2B. If I cannot distinguish between two situations, then it is irrational for me to form the belief that I am in one rather than the other. But these lead to some strong conclusions: C-A. I have no justification for believing that I have hands. (3) C-B. It is irrational for me to form the belief that I have hands. (3)

Skepticism about our knowledge of the external world We have no knowledge of the properties of things outside our own minds. 1. REALITY and DREAMWORLD are indistinguishable. 2. If I cannot distinguish between two situations, then I do not know which of those situations I am in. 3. I do not know which of REALITY and DREAMWORLD I am in. (1,2) C. I do not know whether I have hands. (3) It is therefore hard to grant the conclusion of this skeptical argument while holding on to the idea that there is something OK about my belief that I have hands. It might be instructive to compare the skeptical argument above to the following argument: 1*. I know that I have hands. 2*. I know which of REALITY and DREAMWORLD I am in. (1*) 3*. REALITY and DREAMWORLD are indistinguishable. C*. Sometimes I cannot distinguish between two situations, but can know which of those situations I am in. (1*, 2*)

Skepticism about our knowledge of the external world We have no knowledge of the properties of things outside our own minds. 1. REALITY and DREAMWORLD are indistinguishable. 2. If I cannot distinguish between two situations, then I do not know which of those situations I am in. 3. I do not know which of REALITY and DREAMWORLD I am in. (1,2) C. I do not know whether I have hands. (3) 1*. I know that I have hands. 2*. I know which of REALITY and DREAMWORLD I am in. (1*) 3*. REALITY and DREAMWORLD are indistinguishable. C*. Sometimes I cannot distinguish between two situations, but can know which of those situations I am in. (1*, 2*) These two arguments are closely related. They share a premise -- (2)/(3*). Moreover, each argument has only one other independent premise; and in each case this premise is the negation of the conclusion of the other argument. Which argument is more convincing? Another way to put this question is: is the skeptical argument on the left a convincing argument for skepticism, or a convincing reductio of the second premise? How would you decide this question?