MARXISM AND THE UNO SCHOOL. by John Bellamy Foster

Similar documents
REVIEW of Marxian Political Economy: Theory, History and Contemporary Relevance

Contending Economic Theories

The Adventures of Our Friend, Mr. Moneybags: The Marxist Theory of Capitalism

Michael Heinrich Marx s State Theory after Grundrisse and Capital (Athens, September 2007, Draft version)

Reviewer(s): Source: Published by:

*Heinemann, London, 1979

MONEY HAS NO PRICE: MARX S THEORY OF MONEY AND THE TRANSFORMATION PROBLEM. by Fred Moseley

The Slate Is Not Empty: Descartes and Locke on Innate Ideas

WRITING A CRITICAL ARTICLE REVIEW

It has been contended that it would be possible for a socialist economy to solve

Organizing an essay the basics 2. Cause and effect essay (shorter version) 3. Compare/contrast essay (shorter version) 4

Group Members: Leslie-Ann Bolden, Michela Bowman, Sarah Kaufman, Danielle Jeanne Lindemann Selections from: The Marx-Engels Reader

Critical Analysis So what does that REALLY mean?

Smith on Natural Wages and Profits (Chapters VIII and IX of The Wealth of Nations 1 ) Allin Cottrell

Cosmological Arguments for the Existence of God S. Clarke

Positive Philosophy by August Comte

AN INTRODUCTION TO SOCIOLOGICAL THEORIES

In Defense of Kantian Moral Theory Nader Shoaibi University of California, Berkeley

THE CULTURE OF INNOVATION AND THE BUILDING OF KNOWLEDGE SOCIETIES. - Issue Paper -

The dispute is about the sale of a payment protection insurance (PPI) policy in connection with a credit card account with the firm in April 2007.

1/9. Locke 1: Critique of Innate Ideas

BA (Hons) International Labour and Trade Union Studies (ILTUS)

Market Economy and Socialist Road

ESMT BUSINESS BRIEF. Exploitative Abuses. Lars-Hendrik Röller, ESMT. ESMT No. BB ISSN

Arguments and Dialogues

Levels of Measurement. 1. Purely by the numbers numerical criteria 2. Theoretical considerations conceptual criteria

Five High Order Thinking Skills

Hegemony, subalternity and subjectivity

Modern Political Thought: From Hobbes to. Write a 1500 word textual analysis and commentary on Locke's Second Treatise of Government, Chapter V, 39.

Higher and Rising (Figure 1)

Stages of development

Justice and Ethics. Jimmy Rising. October 18, 2002

Philippe Van Parijs. Analytical Marxism

FROM TERRIBLE TO TERRIFIC UNDERGRADUATE

PUBLIC INTEREST IN POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY. A NECESSARY ETHICAL AND REGULATORY CONCEPT FOR TERRITORIAL PLANNING

Current Situations and Issues of Occupational Classification Commonly. Used by Private and Public Sectors. Summary

They Say, I Say: The Moves That Matter in Academic Writing

GRANT OBINWA NWAOGU UD3094HEA7419 PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION THE SCHOOL OF HUMAN AND SOCIAL STUDIES ATLANTIC INTERNATIONAL UNIVERSITY

Read this syllabus very carefully. If there are any reasons why you cannot comply with what I am requiring, then talk with me about this at once.

7 AGGREGATE SUPPLY AND AGGREGATE DEMAND* Chapter. Key Concepts

The Dangers of Using Correlation to Measure Dependence

Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, New York: Modern Library Edition, [1776] 1994, page 19.

Why economics needs ethical theory by John Broome, University of Oxford

How does the problem of relativity relate to Thomas Kuhn s concept of paradigm?

THE CONTROVERSY OVER GLOBALIZATION A CONSPIRACY THEORY APPROACH -SUMMARY-

Working Paper 5. The Luxembourg Process Five Years On Bernhard Jansen

Kant on Time. Diana Mertz Hsieh Kant (Phil 5010, Hanna) 28 September 2004

A Review of the Literature of Real Business Cycle theory. By Student E XXXXXXX

Moral Hazard. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Course Description. Course Objectives. <> Sociology 710: Intermediate Social Theory Fall 2004 W 2:00-4:30 17 Newcomb Hall

Writing an essay. This seems obvious - but it is surprising how many people don't really do this.

CHAPTER 3. Methods of Proofs. 1. Logical Arguments and Formal Proofs

Sources of International Law: An Introduction. Professor Christopher Greenwood

E-commerce in Developing Countries. Judy Young School of Information Systems University of Tasmania

BLACK SWANS AND KNIGHT S EPISTEMOLOGICAL UNCERTAINTY: ARE THESE CONCEPTS ALSO UNDERLYING BEHAVIORAL AND POST WALRASIAN THEORY?

How To Understand The Relation Between The Worker And The Owner Of A Commodity

Planning and Writing Essays

PROFESSIONAL ETHICS AS VIEWED BY THE SECURITIES AND EXCHANGE COMMISSION. Address. Earle C. King. Chief Accountant, Securities and Exchange Commission

Convention: An interdisciplinary study

MA Thesis Handbook AY Program on International Relations New York University. Fifth Floor 19 University Place New York, New York 10003

Adam Smith: Managerial Insights from the Father of Economics

EAST-WEST Journal of ECONOMICS AND BUSINESS. Journal of Economics and Business Vol. XIIΙ 2010, No 2 ( ) BOOK REVIEW

DEPARTMENT OF THE TREASURY INTERNAL REVENUE SERVICE WASHINGTON, D.C

2. Argument Structure & Standardization

Marxism and Race. 1) Emergence of Ethnicity and Class Conflict Theories of Race

1 Annex 11: Market failure in broadcasting

Necessity? Is The Narrator Necessary? In all narratives?

The Nature of Mind. David M. Armstrong. Morgan Osborn

Book Review of Rosenhouse, The Monty Hall Problem. Leslie Burkholder 1

A catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress

PART A: For each worker, determine that worker's marginal product of labor.

Cost-Benefit Analysis. 131 Undergraduate Public Economics Emmanuel Saez UC Berkeley

A LEVEL ECONOMICS. ECON1/Unit 1 Markets and Market Failure Mark scheme June Version 0.1 Final

CRITICAL WRITING WORKSHOP

ThinkReliability. Six Common Errors when Solving Problems. Solve Problems. Prevent Problems.

Briefing on Personnel Leasing in the European Union

Economic Research Division

CONSTRUCTING A LOGICAL ARGUMENT

What Is a Case Study? series of related events) which the analyst believes exhibits (or exhibit) the operation of

MARX S THEORY OF MONEY AND MONETARY PRODUCTION ECONOMY. Abstract

A. Majchrzak & M. L. Markus

POLITICAL ECONOM Y WORKINGPAPER SERIES. Comments on Aaron Yelowitz, "Santa Fe's Living Wage Ordinance and the Labor Market"

Aristotle and citizenship: the responsibilities of the citizen in the Politics

SYMPOSIUM ON MULTIPLE PERSONALITY DISORDER AND CRIMINAL RESPONSIBILITY INTRODUCTION

Analytical Essay, APA Style (Sociology)

Remodelling the Big Bang

An entity issues a debt instrument for CU1000. The instrument has a stated maturity date. At maturity, the issuer must deliver a variable

INTRODUCTION OVERVIEW CONCEPT OF UNEMPLOYMENT

Class on Hedley Bull. 1. Some general points about Bull s view

Plato gives another argument for this claiming, relating to the nature of knowledge, which we will return to in the next section.

Metaphysics and the Question of Being

Institutional Marxian Political Economy: A Conceptual Marriage between Marx and Veblen

Methodological Issues for Interdisciplinary Research

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Note on growth and growth accounting

INDEX OF TEMPLATES INTRODUCING WHAT THEY SAY

USES OF CONSUMER PRICE INDICES

Appendix B Data Quality Dimensions

GUIDE TO WRITING YOUR RESEARCH PAPER Ashley Leeds Rice University

Research on the Income Volatility of Listed Banks in China: Based on the Fair Value Measurement

Transcription:

MARXISM AND THE UNO SCHOOL by John Bellamy Foster The Basic Theory of Capitalism: The Forms and Substance cif the Capitalist Economy, by Makoto Itoh. Totowa, New Jersey: Barnes and Noble Books, 1988.432 pp. $28.50. In an 1859 review of Marx's Contribution to a Critique if Political Economy, Engels provided the following description of the economic method of historical materialism, frequently labeled the "logicalhistorical method": [T]he critique of economics could.., be exercised in two ways: historically or logically... History moves often in leaps and bounds and in a zigzag line, and as this would have to be followed throughout, it would mean not only that a considerable amount of material of slight importance would have to be included, but also that the train of thought would frequently have to be interrupted; it would, moreover, be impossible to write the history of economy without that of bourgeois society, and the task would thus become immense, because of the absence of all preliminary studies. The logical method of approach was therefore the only suitable one. This, however, is indeed nothing but the historical method, only stripped of the historical form and diverting chance occurrences... [W]ith this method the logical exposition need by no means be confined to the purely abstract sphere. On the contra?, it requires historical illustration and continuous contact with reality. In my view, this understanding of the relation between the logical and the historical constitutes the essential key to the method Marx employed in his Critique if Political Economy (which was also the subtitle of Capital). In contrast, for the Japanese school of Marxism inspired by the work of Kozo Uno, and brilliantly represented by Makoto Itoh's ambitious new study, Marx's economic method (when John Bellamy Foster teaches sociology at the University of Oregon and is a frequent contributor to Monthly Review. 51

52 MONTHLY REVIEW I JANUARY 1990 properly criticized and corrected) is almost completely at odds with what Engels describes in this passage. Instead, the proper method, according to the Unoists, requires a sharp division between levels of "pure theory" (or "basic theory"), stage theory (or the analysis of the mercantilist, liberal-competitive, and imperialist stages of capitalist development), and empirical analysis. To intermingle these levels of inquiry-as Marx himself did both theoretically and by incorporating a great deal ofhistorical material in all his economic writings-is, according to Uno and his followers, to risk mixing science with ideology? There is no doubt that the Uno school, through the sheer elegance of its analysis, has highlighted much of the logic of Marx's Capital, and has helped clarify the role of stage theory, as reflected in Hilferding's Finance Capital and Lenin's Imperialism. But at the same time it has severed the organic connection between theory and history that was integral to all these works. The major weakness of this tradition is that we are presented, in the form of the division between pure theory, stage theory, and empirical analysis, with a threefold theoretical hierarchy and no obvious way of getting from one to the other. Naturally, this leads to some rather peculiar results. Thus Uno himself, starting from the notion of a "purely capitalist society," designated 1917 as the end of capitalism and the beginning of a transitional society; while his stage theory tended to associate each stage with a particular use value such as cotton or steel. Makoto Itch's Basic Theory of Capitalism represents a serious attempt to overcome some of these problems in ways that embody a critique of Uno himself. Thus, rather than following Uno in conceiving the liberal stage as the sale foundation for the pure theory, I toh contends that the pure theory must provide an abstracted analysis that takes into account developments in all three stages of capitalism-mercantilism, liberalism, and imperialism-although still resting primarily on the second. Moreover, the imperialist stage is not arbitrarily cut off, as in orthodox Unoist analysis, at 1917, but is seen as extending into the present. Finally, in incorporating (in contrast to Uno) the analysis of joint stock companies within the basic theory, Itoh has taken a major step toward bridging the gap between the pure theory and the theory of the monopoly stage. Still, Itoh, in my view, has not succeeded in overcoming the major dilemmas of the Unoist tradition. A single example will suffice to illustrate this point. Marx mainly left scattered observations on economic crises and never wrote his originally planned volume on the

BOOKS 53 world market and crisis. Yet, on the subject of crisis Itoh begins by claiming, in line with Uno, that the pure theory is incomplete unless a theory of the necessity of crises is provided. He then goes on to suggest that the only argument on the necessity of periodic crises to be found in the basic theory is the one that is commonly known as the "profit squeeze" perspective, which assumes an industrial reserve army of the unemployed that becomes too small to contain wage increases at the peak of the business cycle. But in order to reinforce this interpretation, I toh finds it essential to argue that Marx was wrong in his contention-which constituted a key part of his "absolute general law of capitalist accumulation"-that there was a secular trend toward a large and growing industrial reserve army (or relative surplus population), arising out of the very nature of capitalist accumulation. What caused Marx to make this mistake, Itoh tells us, is that he confused the temporary effects of the transition to industrial capitalism with the inner logic of the system, and thus "in this respect Marx was in fact not analyzing pure capitalism even in the first volume of Capital" (p. 299). Hence, in the process of privileging one strand of Marxian crisis theory within the pure theory (in contrast to other strands like the realization crisis perspective and the classical falling-rate-of-profit hypothesis), Itoh finds himself compelled to rely on controversial historical assumptions that require the jettisoning of much of Marx's own history and theory. The central issue here is not so much that Itoh has taken some questionable steps in his argument or that he has departed fundamentally from Marx, but rather that the basic theory cannot stand on its own: an analytical framework that divorces itself from the roughand-tumble of history will nonetheless be forced to revert, at crucial points in the argument, to relying on some historical facts and excluding others, all the while justifying this procedure by the alleged necessity to "purify the basic theory." The concrete problem of the working out of Marx's "absolute general law of capitalist accumulation" cannot be settled by designing a purer conception of capitalism, but has meaning only in terms of the subsequent development of monopoly capitalism and imperialism. If the purpose of theory is to understand history in order to change it, it is important to keep in mind the simple truth that capitalism is nothing apart from its historical development. The notion of a purely capitalist society is always in danger of becoming a lifeless abstraction divorced from the necessity to provide a way to penetrate the logic of the accumulation process which lies at the center of the

54 MONTHLY REVIEW / JANUARY 1990 unfolding history of capitalism from its birth to its ultimate transcendence. To divide the theoretical analysis too sharply from concrete history is to fetishize theory, "as if the task were the dialectic balancing of concepts, and not the grasping of real relationsl' ' * * * Although MR is clearly not the place to engage in a detailed discussion of technical economics, it is important to record that Itch's study, which provides a succinct summary of the history of economic analysis and a thought-provoking discussion on the inapplicability of the law of value under socialism, is also noteworthy from an economic standpoint for the contributions that it makes with respect to the most recent ("Marx After Sraffa,") round of discussions surrounding the so-called" transformation problem.t'" This longs tanding can troversy involves debates taking place on two theoretical planes. The chief plane of discussion in the past, the problem of the transformation of values into prices of production, still revolves around the famous Bortkiewicz solution (modified in various ways by subsequent theorists), which, according to Itoh, has stood up logically over the course of time despite a myriad of assaults by orthodox economists. Meanwhile, a more fundamental plane of discussion, the contemporary phase of which has been introduced by neo-ricardian thinkers like Ian Steedman, has tended, Itoh tells us, "to inquire more and more basically into the soundness, consistency and relevancy of Marx's labour theory of value itself." (p. 211). In this realm, two of the central issues have been the status within Marxian value theory of skilled labor (when compared to simple labor) and the compatibility of the labor theory of value with the reality ofjoint-production (when a single production process like raising cattle produces two products-beef and hide). I t is here, in relation to this second, deeper plane of discussion, that Itoh himselfhas the most to add to the overall debate. Moreover, his answers are essentially simple, since they derive their coherence from the fact that they throw out all those considerations that do not relate to the nature and logic of capitalism. Thus the alleged problem for value theory of technically sorting out Marx's reduction of complex (or skilled) to simple labor is overcome by Itoh on the grounds that, as both the Uno school and Harry Braverman have pointed out, there is "a strong tendency towards the degradation of labour.... We may thus erase the problem of how to evaluate skilled labour in terms of simple labour, by abstracting the labour theory of value upon

BOOKS 55 the basis of an historical tendency of capitalism in this direction." (p, 160) Similarly, the joint-production problem presented by Steedman in Marx After Sroffa, in which it is presumably shown to be technically feasible for production to occur with negative values and negative surplus value, demonstrates in Itoh's view nothing so much as "the neo-ricardians' one-sidedly abstract, technological approach to the theory of value. " (pp, 177-78) Such artificial constructions can easily be dealt with by an analysis that takes into account the "historically specific forms and mechanisms of the capitalist economy (including the role of market), which fix the allocation of labour-substance among the joint products (even though this allocation is technically indeterminate)." (p. 178) In short, Itoh is able to intervene effectively in these value theory debates simply because he (unlike neoclassical and neo-ricardian thinkers) is able to turn to the Marxist understanding of capitalism as an historical entity. There is of course a strange irony here. Even though it is, I believe, crucial to criticize the Uno school for its exaggerated attempt to divorce concrete history from theory within its "basic theory of capitalism," nevertheless where political-economic discussions have typically occurred on a very abstract plane, as in the case of the "transformation problem," the Uno school, and Itoh's work in particular, has the advantage over neo-ricardian and neoclassical analysis that, in the process of abstracting from historical contingency, it never entirely loses sight of the fact that the object of the analysis is to understand the historically specific reality of capitalism, and not to deduce laws applicable to economic forms in general. These strengths can be traced, however, not to the Uno school's tendency to separate theory from history, but to the deeper Marxist respect for historical understanding that remains a shadowy part of its analysis. NOTES I. Engels in Marx, A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy (New York: International, 1970), pp. 225-27. 2. See Kozo Uno, Principles of Political Economy (Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press, 1980); Makoto Itoh, Valueand Crisis (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1980); and Robert Albritton, A Japanese Reconstruction oj Marxist Theory (New York: Macmillan, 1986). For a critical viewpoint see John Lie, "Reactionary Marxism," Monthly Review, April 1987, pp. 45-51. 3. Marx, Grundrisse (New York: Vintage, 1973), p. 90. 4. See Ian Steedman, et. ai., The Value Controversy (London: Verso, 1982).