A Note on Proebsting s Paradox



Similar documents
Probability and Expected Value

arxiv: v1 [math.pr] 5 Dec 2011

Betting with the Kelly Criterion

Gambling and Data Compression

Economics 1011a: Intermediate Microeconomics

1. (First passage/hitting times/gambler s ruin problem:) Suppose that X has a discrete state space and let i be a fixed state. Let

Pascal is here expressing a kind of skepticism about the ability of human reason to deliver an answer to this question.

National Sun Yat-Sen University CSE Course: Information Theory. Gambling And Entropy

Lecture 25: Money Management Steven Skiena. skiena

Choice Under Uncertainty

Linear Risk Management and Optimal Selection of a Limited Number

Wald s Identity. by Jeffery Hein. Dartmouth College, Math 100

An Innocent Investigation

How to bet and win: and why not to trust a winner. Niall MacKay. Department of Mathematics

Fund Manager s Portfolio Choice

Review Horse Race Gambling and Side Information Dependent horse races and the entropy rate. Gambling. Besma Smida. ES250: Lecture 9.

Week 4: Gambler s ruin and bold play

In the situations that we will encounter, we may generally calculate the probability of an event

Part I. Gambling and Information Theory. Information Theory and Networks. Section 1. Horse Racing. Lecture 16: Gambling and Information Theory

SOME ASPECTS OF GAMBLING WITH THE KELLY CRITERION. School of Mathematical Sciences. Monash University, Clayton, Victoria, Australia 3168

Fixed odds bookmaking with stochastic betting demands

If A is divided by B the result is 2/3. If B is divided by C the result is 4/7. What is the result if A is divided by C?

6.042/18.062J Mathematics for Computer Science. Expected Value I

Notes on Factoring. MA 206 Kurt Bryan

Randomized algorithms

1 Introduction to Option Pricing

Statistics 100A Homework 3 Solutions

Kelly s Criterion for Option Investment. Ron Shonkwiler (shonkwiler@math.gatech.edu)

The overall size of these chance errors is measured by their RMS HALF THE NUMBER OF TOSSES NUMBER OF HEADS MINUS NUMBER OF TOSSES

A Simple Parrondo Paradox. Michael Stutzer, Professor of Finance. 419 UCB, University of Colorado, Boulder, CO

Perpetuities and Annuities EC Borja Larrain

Betting systems: how not to lose your money gambling

Expected Value and the Game of Craps

Volume 30, Issue 4. Market Efficiency and the NHL totals betting market: Is there an under bias?

Probability Models.S1 Introduction to Probability

Math Review. for the Quantitative Reasoning Measure of the GRE revised General Test

6.042/18.062J Mathematics for Computer Science December 12, 2006 Tom Leighton and Ronitt Rubinfeld. Random Walks

= = 106.

1. Overconfidence {health care discussion at JD s} 2. Biased Judgments. 3. Herding. 4. Loss Aversion

Combining player statistics to predict outcomes of tennis matches

Gambling with Information Theory

The Kelly Betting System for Favorable Games.

1 Short Introduction to Time Series

1. Probabilities lie between 0 and 1 inclusive. 2. Certainty implies unity probability. 3. Probabilities of exclusive events add. 4. Bayes s rule.

STATISTICS 8: CHAPTERS 7 TO 10, SAMPLE MULTIPLE CHOICE QUESTIONS

Information Theory and Coding Prof. S. N. Merchant Department of Electrical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay

Moral Hazard. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

6.852: Distributed Algorithms Fall, Class 2

A Failure of the No-Arbitrage Principle

Lecture 3: Finding integer solutions to systems of linear equations

3.2 Roulette and Markov Chains

WRITING PROOFS. Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology

The Effects of Informed Bettors on Bookmaker Behavior

A New Interpretation of Information Rate

פרויקט מסכם לתואר בוגר במדעים )B.Sc( במתמטיקה שימושית

A Portfolio Model of Insurance Demand. April Kalamazoo, MI East Lansing, MI 48824

Prices, Point Spreads and Profits: Evidence from the National Football League

Homework Assignment #1: Answer Key

Computational Finance Options

MAS113 Introduction to Probability and Statistics

THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF ARBITRAGE PRICING

If, under a given assumption, the of a particular observed is extremely. , we conclude that the is probably not

Binomial lattice model for stock prices

On the Efficiency of Competitive Stock Markets Where Traders Have Diverse Information

Why is Insurance Good? An Example Jon Bakija, Williams College (Revised October 2013)

Some Polynomial Theorems. John Kennedy Mathematics Department Santa Monica College 1900 Pico Blvd. Santa Monica, CA

Economics 1011a: Intermediate Microeconomics

The Mathematics of Gambling

Chapter 22. Markets and Information

Notes on Determinant

A Quick Algebra Review

FIN FINANCIAL INSTRUMENTS SPRING 2008

Double Deck Blackjack

MONEY MANAGEMENT. Guy Bower delves into a topic every trader should endeavour to master - money management.

Gaming the Law of Large Numbers

IEOR 6711: Stochastic Models I Fall 2012, Professor Whitt, Tuesday, September 11 Normal Approximations and the Central Limit Theorem

Spread Betting and The Law Will This Affect YOU?

The Kelly Criterion. A closer look at how estimation errors affect portfolio performance. by Adrian Halhjem Sælen. Advisor: Professor Steinar Ekern

Sleeping Beauty, as described on wikipedia, citing Arnold

Published in 2003 by High Stakes Publishing, 21 Great Ormond Street, London, WC1N 3JB Copyright Joseph Buchdahl

Factoring & Primality

The Games of Gambling - Arbitrage

Random Fibonacci-type Sequences in Online Gambling

Lecture 13: Factoring Integers

Reinforcement Learning

People have thought about, and defined, probability in different ways. important to note the consequences of the definition:

The Assumptions and Math Behind WACC and APV Calculations

Lecture 15. Ranking Payoff Distributions: Stochastic Dominance. First-Order Stochastic Dominance: higher distribution

11 Ideals Revisiting Z

Practical Probability:

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 10

Hacking-proofness and Stability in a Model of Information Security Networks

Club Accounts Question 6.

The Binomial Distribution

Chapter ML:IV. IV. Statistical Learning. Probability Basics Bayes Classification Maximum a-posteriori Hypotheses

The Binomial Option Pricing Model André Farber

CMSC 858T: Randomized Algorithms Spring 2003 Handout 8: The Local Lemma

Stochastic Inventory Control

Transcription:

A Note on Proebsting s Paradox Leonid Pekelis March 8, 2012 Abstract Proebsting s Paradox is two-stage bet where the naive Kelly gambler (wealth growth rate maximizing) can be manipulated in some disconcertingly non-optimal ways. We extend this result to k-stage and the limiting -stage bets, and give a few comments. Suppose someone offers us a bet. At some time in the future a p coin is flipped, and if the coin is heads, we get σ-for-1, and 0 otherwise. How much should we invest in the bet? In other words, let X be a Bernoulli-p random variable, the random wealth observed after betting b proportion of total wealth is S = b + bσx with b = 1 b. There is sizable evidence to support choosing b to maximize IE[ln(S)] as the right answer, with the solution given by b = pσ 1 σ 1 This strategy maximizes the growth rate of wealth, and protects against bankrupcy no matter what σ and p are. It goes by the name Kelly gambling. So why would you ever doubt Kelly gambling? The short answer is you wouldn t, most of the time. Key words and phrases. Proebsting Paradox, Kelly betting, multi stage gambling Written with guidance and commentary from Thomas Cover 1

One apparent issue has been floating around under the name Proebsting s paradox, first encountered in an email exchange between Ed Thorp and Todd Proebsting in 2008. The idea is before the outcome of the coin flip, the same bookie offers the opportunity to wager more money, this time at odds σ 2 -for- 1. Investing b 2 more of total wealth trades S for a new random variable S 2 = b 2 + (bσ + b 2 σ 2 )X with b 2 = 1 b b 2. Maximizing IE[ln(S 2 )], treating the initial investment of b as fixed, gives, after a little rearranging b 2 = p(σ 2 σ) (1 b). σ 2 1 So as long as the bookie gives better odds than before (σ 2 > σ), we will bet a positive amount. Note that we still have all the benefits of Kelly working for us. The combined bet (b, b 2 ) gives the largest growth rate over many repetitions of the same (σ, σ 2 )-for-1, 2 stage bet. Also we ll never bet more than p fraction of b at the second round, and a bound for the total amount bet is B 2 = b + b 2 < p + p(1 p) 1 with equality iff p = 1. We are still protected from betting all of our money, though the bound is suspiciously greater than B 1 = b < p. A disconcerning consequence of the sequential bet is that the Kelly bettor will bet more if offered, say, 6-for-1 after 3-for-1 odds on a p =.5 bet, than if only offered the 6-for-1 odds (.475 vs.40 of wealth). In fact, this turns out to hold generally for any p and σ 2 > σ 1. Here I m adding the subscript to σ 1 to avoid confusion. Lemma 0.1. Let B k (σ) denote the total Kelly bet for a k-stage bet with odds σ = (σ 1,..., σ k ), then for any positive expected value bet (σ 2 > σ 1 > 1/p) B 2 (σ 1, σ 2 ) B 1 (σ 2 ) = p(1 p)(σ 2 σ 1 )(σ 1 1/p) (σ 1 1)(σ 2 1) Proof. Substituting for (1 b) gives B 2 B 1 = p(σ 1 1/p) σ 1 1 + p(σ 2 σ 1 )(1 p)σ 1 (σ 2 1)(σ 1 1) p(σ 2 1/p) σ 2 1 After combining fractions the numerator simplifies to that of (1). 2 > 0 (1)

Why does this happen? One explanation [wikipedia] is that the bettor s share of the σ 1 -for-1 bet devalues in the presence of the σ 2 -for-1 bet, much in the same way an investor feels less wealthy when the price of an owned stock goes down. The bettor still bets the optimal Kelly amount B 1 (σ 2 ) at the second stage, but now with respect to an implied total wealth less than 1. Specifically, the bσ 1 X variable can be replicated at the second stage by setting b 2 = b(σ 1 /σ 2 ). Since the b s can be considered the deterministic cost of the random variable, and σ 2 > σ 1, the value of the original bet drops from b to b 2, and the betters total wealth in the second stage falls to (1 b) + b 2 = 1 b(1 σ 1 /σ 2 ). Even though the explanation is logical, the result still makes us feel uneasy. Somehow the nearsighted Kelly gambler isn t able to protect his wealth from a (possibly) manipulating bookie. These results extend, and become even more exteme, in the general k- stage bet, and especialy so for the limiting -stage bet. We start with an equation for B k (σ). Lemma 0.2. For a general N-stage bet with σ i > 1 for all i, Kelly betting at each stage invests b k = pα k bk (2) proportion of total wealth with cumulative proportion invested where α k = σ k σ k 1 σ k 1 B k = pα i (1 pα i+1 )... (1 pα k ) (3) and b k = 1 k 1 b i, the proportion of remaining wealth. Proof. The first order condition for IE[ln(S 2 )] holding b fixed gives the optimal b 2. b 2 = pσ 2(1 b) qσ 1 b (1 b) σ 1 1 Adding and subtracting pσ 1 (1 b) in the numerator gives b 2 as in (2) plus a remainder that can be shown to equal 0. At any subsequent stage k, 3

( ) S k = b k + b i σ i X. Since all previous bets are fixed, S k is of the same form as S 2, but with updated constants, b b k and bσ k 1 b iσ i, and hence the first order condition as well. The form (2), is found similarly to the case k = 2. For the first stage, b 1 b, can also be written in the form of (2) with σ 0 = 1/p and b 0 = 1. Equation (3) now follows as B k satisfies the following recursive relation B k = (1 pα k )B k 1 + pα k with initial term B 1 = pα 1. Lemma 0.2 gives one interpretation of a Kelly bettor s strategy. At each stage, they invest more of their wealth iff better odds are offered over the previous stage, and the amount of remaining wealth invested is proportional to p times a factor penalizing odds increases over already large odds. Note that 0 α k 1, with equality only in the cases of no change in odds and infinite odds. The total proportion invested is harder to describe, but does set us up to talk about Proebsting s paradox for many stages. First a corrolary on bounds, Corollary 0.3. At each stage the Kelly bettor will not bet more than p proportion of remaining wealth, and using this bound B k < c k 1. Furthermore proportional Kelly gambling does not decrease the bound. Proof. Extending the result for 2 stages it is straightforward to show b i < p(1 p) i 1 and hence c k = p(1 p) i 1 p (1 p) i = 1 For proportional Kelly the bound is now b i < γp(1 γp) i 1 with γ (0, 1) and the same infinite sum gives c k 1. Finally, I ll give 2 examples showing both a case of B = 1 and B < 1. i=0 4

Example 0.4. Suppose the odds are increasing at a constant rate, α k = α for all k and α (0, 1). Then B k = pα (1 pα) k i 1 This is essentially the case of the original Proebsting paradox, σ k = 2 k, where α.5 for large k. Example 0.5. Suppose the odds are increasing, but at a decreasing rate, α k = 2 k, then a really quick bound is B k = p2 i j=i+1 k (1 p2 j ) < and taking 1 more term in the expansion gives p2 i p (4) B k < p2 i (1 p2 i 1 ) = p p2 6. Note that for either expansion to hold, we need p < 1 because if p = 1 the Kelly bettor takes b 1 = 1 and hence all other b i = 0, though the bound (4) in this case still holds. It seems as though a Kelly bettor can find themselves risking most of their wealth, even on low probability bets, as long as the odds are increasing fast enough. One might even imagine an example of Proebsting s paradox in action where a real estate developer invests more and more into a property as housing prices bubble, even though the underlying (known!) sale probability may be low. One solution is of course never to bet more than ρ proportion of your wealth. It is also not hard to imagine a slightly more savvy bettor incorporating prior knowledge on the chance of future stages, and making assumptions on the stochastic nature of odds to get a random bet process, b k (σ). 5