DISCUSSION NOTE JUSTIFICATIONS AND EXCUSES: MUTUALLY EXCLUSIVE?



Similar documents
Does rationality consist in responding correctly to reasons? John Broome Journal of Moral Philosophy, 4 (2007), pp

MILD DILEMMAS. Keywords: standard moral dilemmas, mild dilemmas, blame

Title 17-A: MAINE CRIMINAL CODE

The Right of a State to Control Immigration

IN THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE EASTERN DISTRICT OF PENNSYLVANIA. Memorandum and Order

Scanlon and the claims of the many versus the one

SUPREME COURT OF ARIZONA En Banc

A Primer on the Distinction between Justification and Excuse

or conventional implicature [1]. If the implication is only pragmatic, explicating logical truth, and, thus, also consequence and inconsistency.

Negligence. [Forthcoming in Hugh LaFollette, ed., The International Encyclopedia of Ethics (Wiley-Blackwell)]

Excuses, Moral and Legal: A Comment on Marcia Baron s Excuses, Excuses. R A Duff

Defining Aggregate Settlements: the Road Not to Take. By: Peter R. Jarvis and Trisha M. Rich. Summary and Introduction

The Foundation of Juvenile Practice Part 1: You are Adversary Counsel, NOT a GAL! Private Bar Certification Forensic Exercise November 19, 2014

But Then They Are Told. Michael Gorman School of Philosophy The Catholic University of America Washington, D.C

Are Skill Selective Immigration Policies Just?

[THIS IS A PRE-PRINT VERSION OF THE PAPER. THE PUBLISHED VERSION IS AVAILABLE ONLINE AT

Indemnification Clauses, Part 1* Discussion from a/e ProNet's Risk Management and Contract Guide. J. Kent Holland, Jr., Esq.

TRIPARTITE STRUCTURES OF CRIMINAL LAW IN GERMANY AND OTHER CIVIL LAW JURISDICTIONS

A&E Briefings. Indemnification Clauses: Uninsurable Contractual Liability. Structuring risk management solutions

CONCEPTUAL CONTINGENCY AND ABSTRACT EXISTENCE

Weiler, Maloney, Nelson

Inquiry of a Client s Lawyer Concerning Litigation, Claims, and Assessments: Auditing Interpretations of Section 337

2012 Updates in Employment Law Gerald T. Husch December 18, 2012

IMPLIES 'CAN' 'OUGHT' CONVERSATIONALLY. Walter Sinnott-Armstrong

Employing the Advance Credit Settlement Device. Michael J. Ford Krista L. Durrwachter James S. McAlpine Quinlivan & Hughes, P.A. St.

Advisory Committee on Professional Ethics. Appointed by the Supreme Court of New Jersey

Are you ever afraid to be around the person when he or she is drinking or using drugs because of the possibility of verbal or physical abuse?

The Legalization of Drugs

case 1:11-cv JTM-RBC document 35 filed 11/29/12 page 1 of 6 UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT NORTHERN DISTRICT OF INDIANA FORT WAYNE DIVISION

The John Locke Lectures Being Realistic about Reasons. T. M. Scanlon. Lecture 3: Motivation and the Appeal of Expressivism

Critical Study David Benatar. Better Never To Have Been: The Harm of Coming into Existence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006)

KENTUCKY BAR ASSOCIATION Ethics Opinion KBA E-275 Issued: July 1983

TESTIFYING ABOUT SELF-DEFENSE AND PREDOMINANT AGGRESSORS 1

MORAL LIMITS OF DWORKIN S THEORY OF LAW AND LEGAL INTERPRETATION

Chapter I. 1. Purpose. 2. Your Representations. 3. Cancellations. 4. Mandatory Administrative Proceeding. dotversicherung-registry GmbH

GENERAL PRACTICE LEGAL MALPRACTICE IN LIGHT OF TOGSTAD LIABILITY FOR CURBSTONE OPINIONS?

Tort Liability and Taking Responsibility. David Enoch

Teaching Non-Philosophy Faculty to Teach Critical Thinking about Ethical Issues. Peter Vallentyne and John Accordino, Virginia Commonwealth University

Boonin on the Future-Like-Ours Argument against Abortion. Pedro Galvão Centro de Filosofia da Universidade de Lisboa

Samples of Opening Paragraphs for a Short Philosophy Paper

PUBLISHED UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE FOURTH CIRCUIT. No

RECOGNIZING AND MANAGING SERIAL LITIGATION. John L. Tate, Esq. 1. Among the challenges facing product manufacturers in the 21 st century

Ethical Standards for Publication of Aeronautics and Astronautics Research

IN THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE EASTERN DISTRICT OF PENNSYLVANIA MEMORANDUM. Ludwig. J. July 9, 2010

Case 1:08-cv Document 45 Filed 10/19/2009 Page 1 of 7 IN THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE NORTHERN DISTRICT OF ILLINOIS EASTERN DIVISION

In Defense of Kantian Moral Theory Nader Shoaibi University of California, Berkeley

Legislation to encourage medical innovation a consultation. British Medical Association response. Executive Summary

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics

Drug development for children: how adequate is the current European ethical guidance?

MPRE Sample Test Questions

MEMORANDUM. advice. Defendants are encouraged to engage their own counsel before relying on anything contained herein.

Conceiving What Is Not There

RACING APPEALS TRIBUNAL NEW SOUTH WALES EX TEMPORE DECISION

Analyzing Research Articles: A Guide for Readers and Writers 1. Sam Mathews, Ph.D. Department of Psychology The University of West Florida

HARVEY KRUSE, P.C. BAD FAITH

Any Non-welfarist Method of Policy Assessment Violates the Pareto Principle. Louis Kaplow and Steven Shavell

POLICY NO LEGAL DEFENSE BENEFIT

Three ways to sue health care providers

Self-Defense and Predominant Aggressor Training Materials

WHERE ARE THE BORDERS OF THE ACCEPTABLE LAWYER S PATERNALISM? A CLIENT S INFORMED CONSENT IN BOSNIA AND HERZEGOVINA

The Role of Dispute Settlement Procedures in International Trade Agreements: Online Appendix

What is, and to what Purpose do we Study, International Business? 1. Klaus E. Meyer. China Europe International Business School (CEIBS)

Case 1:13-cv NMG Document 41 Filed 09/29/14 Page 1 of 12. United States District Court District of Massachusetts

See Snyman 5 th ed,

Best Practices for Addressing the Confluence of Campus Complaints with Criminal Trials

THIRTY FOURTH JUDICIAL DISTRICT COURT PARISH OF ST. BERNARD STATE OF LOUISIANA TERRENCE FEDELE VERSUS CHALMETTE MEDICAL CENTER, INC.

Chapter 4 Legal Ethics


DEPARTMENT OF JUSTICE

FILED December 8, 2015 Carla Bender 4 th District Appellate Court, IL

Other Insurance and the CGL Policy

So Your Client Wants to be an Additional Insured

CUR CURWOODS NEWS BULLETIN SECTION 81 NOTICES: THE LANDSCAPE FOLLOWING AMENDMENT TO THE CLAIMS ASSESSMENT GUIDELINES

Administered Arbitration Rules

NOT RECOMMENDED FOR FULL-TEXT PUBLICATION File Name: 13a0347n.06. No UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE SIXTH CIRCUIT ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) ) )

What to Do When Your Witness Testimony Doesn t Match His or Her Declaration

But For Causation in Defective Drug and Toxic Exposure Cases: California s Form Jury Instruction CACI 430

SHANA J. SHUTLER OPINION BY v. Record No JUSTICE LAWRENCE L. KOONTZ, JR. June 8, 2006 AUGUSTA HEALTH CARE FOR WOMEN, P.L.C.

Case 2:12-cv BSJ Document 588 Filed 01/23/14 Page 1 of 7

When Betting Odds and Credences Come Apart: More Worries for Dutch Book Arguments

IN THE DISTRICT COURT OF THE UNITED STATES FOR THE WESTERN DISTRICT OF NORTH CAROLINA ASHEVILLE DIVISION. CIVIL CASE NO. 1:06cv97

Thompsons Solicitors response to the interim report of the Insurance Fraud Taskforce May 2015

Increasing the risk of injury and proof of causation on the balance of probabilities. Sandy Steel

Challenging Your College s Speech Code

Chapter 7 Tort Law and Product Liability

SUPERIOR COURT OF THE STATE OF DELAWARE JUDGE 500 NORTH KING STREET, SUITE WILMINGTON, DE TELEPHONE (302)

Scope of Workplace Violence Program 2, 3. Types of Workplace Violence Events 4, 5. Preventative Measures 6, 7. Responding to Workplace Violence 8, 9

Case 2:10-cv JAR Document 98 Filed 05/04/11 Page 1 of 8 IN THE UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE DISTRICT OF KANSAS

INDEX OF TEMPLATES INTRODUCING WHAT THEY SAY

Case 0:14-cv JIC Document 44 Entered on FLSD Docket 09/30/2015 Page 1 of 12 UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT SOUTHERN DISTRICT OF FLORIDA

Read this syllabus very carefully. If there are any reasons why you cannot comply with what I am requiring, then talk with me about this at once.

Case 3:07-cv MLC-JJH Document 80 Filed 09/10/2008 Page 1 of 15

PATIENT TRANSFER AGREEMENT

DA IN THE SUPREME COURT OF THE STATE OF MONTANA 2009 MT 387

Review article. A challenge to the reigning theory. of the just war

Food Law and Due Diligence Defence

GAIL EDWARDS a/k/a GAIL RAFIANI, Chapter 13 Case No.: Debtor. GAIL EDWARDS a/k/a GAIL RAFFIANI, Plaintiff, v. Adversary No.

3.10 ASSAULT AND BATTERY (Approved prior to 1984; Revised 03/2015) A. Definition

The Common Public License (CPL)

Where can I get help after a sexual assault?

Transcription:

DISCUSSION NOTE BY MARK MCBRIDE JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE JUNE 2011 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT MARK MCBRIDE 2011

Justifications and Excuses: Mutually Exclusive? V IRTUALLY EVERY PHILOSOPHER of the criminal law with the exception of Doug Husak (2010) answers this question, yes. I want to join Husak in answering, no. Indeed I want to use an overdetermination case of Husak s to illustrate a crippling problem for philosophers answering, yes. Where I go beyond Husak beyond, that is, his denial of mutual exclusivity is in offering a novel positive account of the relationship between justifications and excuses: If one s conduct is justified, one s conduct is excused. The converse entailment, however, does not hold. 1. The Standard View and the Overdetermination Problem 1.1 We need a working set of definitions of justifications and excuses which capture, and explain, the essence of the standard view. (Inevitably, our working set of definitions, which are pitched at a high level of abstraction, will not be able to finesse the details of particular theorists accounts.) On the standard view, say one s conduct is justified iff one s conduct, which may be prima facie wrongful, is not ultima facie wrongful. 1 And say one s conduct is excused iff one s wrongful conduct 2 is not blameworthy. Straightforwardly, on these definitions, justifications and excuses are mutually exclusive. 1.2 Now consider Husak s (298-9) overdetermination case: Suppose, for example, that a defendant is threatened with serious bodily harm unless he inflicts a somewhat greater harm on the next person to walk into his office. By chance, this next person happens to be a personal enemy who begins to attack the defendant. In this example, the defendant has two independent, sufficient reasons to inflict personal injury, each of which constitutes a defense from liability. His first reason, duress, is generally categorized as an excuse; his second reason, self-defense, is almost always categorized as a justification. (footnotes omitted) 1 Standard theorists might instead propose: One s conduct is justified iff one s prima facie wrongful conduct is not ultima facie wrongful. Although my core claims would go through operating with this biconditional, insofar as we seek a fully general account of justified conduct, its right-hand side is palpably too strong. For example, my waking up in the morning is, suppose, a case of justified, though not prima facie wrongful, conduct. (Likewise for non-conduct, such as my believing that I have hands.) To be sure, a claim to justifiedness will often be odd in the absence of any suggestion of wrongfulness; but that oddness is best explained pragmatically (e.g. on grounds of relevance), rather than semantically. Sadly, it is a theme of the vast literature on justifications (and, mutatis mutandis, excuses) that the distinction between justifiedness and claims to justifiedness is often slurred over. 2 Here, and in what follows, wrongful conduct is equivalent to ultima facie wrongful conduct.

Like Husak, I view this as a crippling problem for the standard view: The defendant, assuming he acts on the basis of each sufficient reason, 3 appears to have both a justification and an excuse for inflicting personal injury. And, like Husak (299-302), I find no dialectical response on behalf of the standard view to be convincing: Genuine cases of overdetermination seem possible. 4 2. The Solution 2.1 The solution is obvious. We should retain the standard definition of justifications, yet weaken that of excuses to: one s conduct is excused iff one s conduct is not blameworthy (whether wrongful or not). 5 Assuming that conduct which is not wrongful (i.e. justified conduct) is not blameworthy, we would then have justifications entailing excuses 6 ; but not the converse entailment (on account of blameless wrongdoing). 7 Now, returning to Husak s problematic overdetermination case: A successful selfdefense justification ensures the defendant s conduct is not wrongful. By itself, given our revised set of definitions and our assumption, this also excuses the defendant (from blame). The self-defense justification itself, thus, plays a complementary excusatory role. 8 And, on our revised account, this will be a general feature of justifications. Independently, however, a successful duress defense excuses the defendant from blame for what is here, ex hypothesi, not wrongful conduct. 9 Nonetheless, standard 3 Neither reason would be a but-for cause of the defendant s action. 4 A novel standard view response: Instead of there being a single act that is overdetermined, there are two acts, each individuated by its cause. Thus we have one act which is justified but not excused, and one which is excused but not justified, even though they are both acts of personal injury. I leave the plausibility of this response to the reader. 5 Husak (292) does consider, without there committing on (cf. Husak 1992), a similar, though not fully general, revised set of definitions. 6 Can we make this assumption and also allow Scanlon s (2008: 125) claim that it can be appropriate to blame a person who has done what was in fact the right thing if he or she did it for an extremely bad reason? Yes. What this person, if blameworthy, did wrong was doing the right thing for the wrong reason. (Though such wrongs will not usually be a proper concern of the criminal law, consider a putative self-defense case where the defendant is solely motivated by revenge.) To fail to make this assumption would enforce withdrawing my claim that justifications entail excuses but would not, given our revised set of definitions, jeopardize my allowing the defendant in Husak s problematic overdetermination case both a justification and an excuse for inflicting personal injury. 7 There is, I recognize, room for debate over the scope, and indeed existence, of cases of blameless wrongdoing. 8 The excusatory duress component of Husak s case, while a necessary feature of its status as an overdetermination case, is, of course, a contingent feature in general: Not all, indeed few, instances of self-defense are instances of duress. 9 We are assuming, recall, if conduct is not wrongful, it is not blameworthy. However, as this duress defense is, ex hypothesi, being run independently of the self-defense justification, the resultant finding that the defendant is excused from blame is non-trivial. Indeed, the point generalizes: We may often wish, or need, to assess conduct for excusedness independently of an assessment of its wrongfulness. 2

successful duress defenses will excuse the defendant from blame for wrongful conduct. 10 Objection: My account is hostage to the characterization, and availability, of certain defenses. Suppose, for example, we characterize necessity as a justification. Now suppose that a seaman throws marijuana overboard in order to avoid capsizing, and that he claims to be justified on the basis of necessity when he is later charged with importing a controlled substance. What excuse is available to the seaman? Arguably, given these two suppositions and given current characterizations of defenses, no extant excuse is available. Reply: If necessity indeed justifies the seaman s action, our revised account will have necessity itself playing a complementary excusatory role. My account is, thus, flexible with respect to defense characterizations: We can allow that necessity is a justification consistently with no distinct extant excuse being available. 11 And answering this objection prompts a brief reflection on a point of method. Our starting point was a working set of definitions of justifications and excuses, pitched at a general level. We then considered Husak s overdetermination case a thoughtexperiment which contained fairly uncontroversial classifications of a specific justification (self-defense) and a specific excuse (duress). And specific justifications and excuses are what criminal law practice trades in. Husak s case prompted conceptual revision of the relationship between justifications and excuses at a general level (cf. my coming consideration of etiquette). Finally, revision at a general level fed back into the theoretical operation of the criminal law: Specific justifications come to play a dual role of justifying and excusing conduct. Overall, as I see things, conceptual revision at a general level, while here prompted by reflection on extant characterizations of specific defenses, ought not to be rigidly bound thereby. At the same time, conceptual revision at a general level ought not to do thoroughgoing violence to extant characterizations of specific defenses. One might think of this method as endeavoring to reach a form of reflective equilibrium between the general and the specific in this domain. 2.2 I take it the foregoing solution to the overdetermination problem has not been adopted principally for fear of overinclusiveness of the resulting concept of excuse. But any such concern would be misplaced. As Husak (293) himself points out, one may aptly request an excuse the aptness of such a request constituting prima facie evidence for the truth-conditions of the general category of an excuse if one sneezes or coughs in public, yet there is no suggestion that one must 12 have thereby 10 The justificatory self-defense component of Husak s case, while a necessary feature of its status as an overdetermination case, is, of course, a contingent feature in general: Not all, indeed few, instances of duress are instances of self-defense. 11 The flexibility of my account is not boundless: We cannot allow both that necessity is a justification and that it fails to play a complementary excusatory role. But, if my account is right, such inflexibility is no loss. 12 In sneezing or coughing around other people, one may have disturbed them and/or exposed them to the non-negligible chance of getting sick. But this need not be the case. Consistently with all this, one could allow that sneezing without an excuse is wrong, as it 3

committed a wrong. 13 (Of course, if the standard view is correct, and if one has not done anything wrong in sneezing or coughing, then it follows that one is mistaken in thinking that one may aptly ask for an excuse. But one person s modus ponens is another s modus tollens. I suggest we reason from aptly requesting an excuse in such circumstances, combined with the assumption that one has not done anything wrong, to coming to have reason to doubt the standard view.) Moreover to counter fear of overinclusiveness in the domain of the criminal law one will only need to invoke an excuse in the event of a suggestion of the wrongfulness of one s conduct. 3. Practical Upshot(s) My proposal about the relationship between justifications and excuses is, at root, a conceptual one. Ultimately its success will hang on how well it does in capturing those two concepts and situating them within their neighboring conceptual terrain a task I have endeavored to begin in this note. Nonetheless, we might expect conceptual revision in this area of philosophy to have practical upshots. Let me, thus, explicitly note one concrete normative upshot there are doubtless more of my proposal for criminal procedure. 14 Husak (298, n.52) points out: Courts and commentators have long debated whether and under what circumstances two defenses are actually inconsistent. See the confusing discussion in Henderson v. US 237 F2d 169, 172 (1956), in which allegedly inconsistent defenses are said to be permitted or not permitted... depend[ing] upon the degree of inconsistency as though inconsistency could admit of degrees. On our revised account, there would be no inconsistency, at a conceptual level, 15 in simultaneously running a justification and an excuse defense. Resultantly, no question of the impermissibility of running such defenses on account of their inconsistency could arise. Put differently, no positive reasons e.g. fairness to defendants (cf. Husak 299-300) need be invoked to render the running of such defenses permissible. Moreover, there would be no need to run such defenses in the alternative. Indeed recognition that, not only are justifications and excuses not mutually exviolates the rules of etiquette. But, in allowing this, it would not be the sneezing per se that constitutes the wrongness. Finally, we should recall (cf. n.2 supra) that by wrong we mean ultima facie wrong. 13 Thus, for example, my waking up in the morning will, suppose, count as excused conduct. (Likewise for non-conduct, such as my believing that I have hands.) To be sure, a claim to excusedness will often be odd in the absence of any suggestion of wrongfulness; but, again, that oddness is best explained pragmatically (e.g. on grounds of relevance), rather than semantically (cf. n.1 supra). 14 To be sure, the coming upshot does not principally concern the realit[y] of criminal practice (Husak 299) on which, standardly, a defendant may simultaneously plead a justification and an excuse defense but rather principally concerns the justification of that reality (though cf. my coming point about running defenses in the alternative). 15 Here, and in what follows, I stipulate away the possibility of inconsistencies at a factual level, with respect to the details of any particular defendant s defense case. 4

clusive, but that, additionally, justifications entail excuses, can only serve to bolster this concrete normative upshot. 16 Oxford University Faculty of Philosophy mark.mcbride@philosophy.ox.ac.uk References Husak, D. 1992. The Serial View of Criminal Law Defenses. Criminal Law Forum 3: 369-400.. 2010. On the Supposed Priority of Justification to Excuse. In The Philosophy of Criminal Law: Selected Essays (Oxford: OUP). Scanlon, T. 2008. Moral Dimensions. (Belknap: Harvard University Press). 16 Thanks to Lee Walters for stimulating discussion, and to a JESP referee for helpful comments. 5