Apparent judicial difficulties with applying an objective test literally



Similar documents
Liability for dishonest assistance in a breach of fiduciary duty

Medical Schools Conference

Handling Professional Indemnity Coverage Issues in Cases of Suspected Fraud. Part I: Update - Coverage Tips and Traps

Trustees liability 8.0 /35

NATIONAL COLLEGE FOR TEACHING AND LEADERSHIP PROFESSIONAL CONDUCT PANEL DECISION AND RECOMMENDATIONS AND DECISION ON BEHALF OF THE SECRETARY OF STATE

4. In Dymocks Franchise Systems (NSW) Pty Ltd v Todd [2004] UKPC 39 Lord Brown clarified:

1. My remarks this morning, which are directed to the professional. negligence of financial advisers, will extend to the proposed new

OFFICE-HOLDER CLAIMS AGAINST DIRECTORS AND THIRD PARTIES

PROFESSIONAL NEGLIGENCE LEGAL UPDATE. Talk by Rachel Robertson on 3 June 2010

LIMITATION UPDATE. 1. Recently, the Courts have been looking at three areas of limitation law and

Legal Watch: Personal Injury

Fitness to Practise Determination

EMPLOYERS LIABILITY AND THE ENTERPRISE AND REGULATORY REFORM ACT 2013

Greene Wood & McLean v Templeton Insurance Ltd [2008] APP.L.R. 07/10

IN THE COURT OF APPEAL SPARKASSE BREGENZ BANK AG. and. In The Matter of ASSOCIATED CAPITAL CORPORATION

Before : Mr Justice Morgan Between :

BACK TO BASICS: TAX AND PROFESSIONAL NEGLIGENCE

Akers and others v Samba Financial Group [2014] EWCA Civ 1516; [2014] WLR (D) 521

Financing and refinancing in s11 of the Consumer Credit Act 1974: Consolidated Finance Ltd v Collins [2013] EWCA Civ 475

Limiting liability for professional firms

UNFAIR DISMISSAL: WHEN WILL THE COURTS ALLOW EXTENDED TIME LIMITS?

Commercial trusts law

Pankhurst v White and MIB grotesque fee arrangements both sides paid the cost

Causation in Equitable Compensation Case Comment. Aleksi Ollikainen

United Kingdom. Tristan Hall Sarah Hills Sedgwick Detert, Moran & Arnold LLP. 1. Directors duties

Trustee indemnity insurance

By Elizabeth Darlington

Before : THE HONOURABLE MR JUSTICE TUGENDHAT Between :

Civil Law (Wrongs) (Proportionate Liability and Professional Standards) Amendment Act 2004

NEGLIGENT SETTLEMENT ADVICE. Daniel Crowley and Leona Powell consider the Court s approach to negligent settlement advice.

JAMAICA THE HON MR JUSTICE MORRISON JA THE HON MR JUSTICE BROOKS JA THE HON MS JUSTICE LAWRENCE-BESWICK JA (AG) BETWEEN GODFREY THOMPSON APPELLANT

Companies Act No. 71 of 2008 Duties and Liabilities of Directors

SOLICITORS DISCIPLINARY TRIBUNAL. IN THE MATTER OF THE SOLICITORS ACT 1974 Case No and. Before:

GARETH DAVID CODD (an infant suing by Mr T Griffiths his Uncle and Next Friend) v THOMSONS TOUR OPERATORS LIMITED

CGT / IHT Tax Trap & Professional Negligence

Legal Watch: Personal Injury. February 2014 Issue 007

Problematic Probate (Part 1)

Queensland WHISTLEBLOWERS PROTECTION ACT 1994

TORT LAW SUMMARY LAWSKOOL UK

AS APPROVED BY CONVOCATION, MARCH 25, (new/amended rules and commentary for rule 2.02)

Management liability - Employment practices liability Policy wording

Fraud Prevention and Deterrence

Directors Duties in association with the Institute of Directors Ireland. MHC.ie

COMPLAINTS WHICH ACCA WILL INVESTIGATE

Broad specifications and use requirements: competition and bad faith considerations

Freedom of information guidance Exemptions guidance Section 41 Information provided in confidence

A Paper for the Falcon Chambers Symposium: Property Law in the Recession 4 March Guy Fetherstonhaugh QC FALCON CHAMBERS

Court of Protection Note. The Court of Protection and Personal Injury Claims. Simon Edwards

Step in Proceedings: A Step Too Far?

Subject to, notwithstanding and without prejudice to what do they all mean?

ARE WE DOING ENOUGH TO PROTECT PROTECTED PARTIES? LESSONS FOR PERSONAL INJURY LAWYERS FROM THE SUPREME COURT JUDGMENT IN DUNHILL V BURGIN

FOR THE GREATER GOOD? SUMMARY DISMISSAL, PSYCHIATRIC INJURY AND REMOTENESS

Fiduciary Duties 3. Skill and Care 3

Claims As Commodities Paying For Claims Robert Marven

Personal Injury? What to Do?

DISCIPLINARY BYE-LAWS

LENDER BREACH OF TRUST CLAIMS GRANT CRAWFORD Radcliffe Chambers

At a directors meeting attended by Ann, Bob, Dotty and Evan, with Frank attending by telephone, the directors passed the following resolutions.

Office of Bar Counsel 525 West Jefferson P. O. Box 895 Boise, Idaho (208) Fax: (208)

Expert Evidence In Professional Negligence Claims

FIRE ON THE ICE: RECENT DEVELOPMENTS IN THE LAW OF NEGLIGENCE REGARDING CAUSATION

JUDGMENT. TLM Company Limited (Appellant) v Bedasie and another (Respondent)

Williams v. University of Birmingham [2011] EWCA Civ 1242 Court of Appeal, 28 October 2011

Good faith is there a new implied duty in English contract law?

Fiduciary relationships and constructive trusts in a commercial context Panesar, S. Published version deposited in CURVE March 2012

JENNIFER LEE. Withdrawal of Pre- Action Admissions: Woodland v Stopford, PIBULJ (July 2011).

Accountants' liability for negligence. Accountancy Ireland, 33 (5):

Fraud Act 2006 CHAPTER 35 CONTENTS

DUTIES OF DIRECTORS IN RELATION TO COMPANIES FACING FINANCIAL DIFFICULTIES

Paper in response to the issues raised in the Panel on Administration of Justice and Legal Services meeting on 26 April 2004

BAKER. - and

Claim shall mean each Claim or series of Claims (whether by one or more than one Claimant) arising from or in connection with or attributable to any

When does the clock start ticking?

NO. 03-B-0910 IN RE: HARRY E. CANTRELL, JR. ATTORNEY DISCIPLINARY PROCEEDINGS

REPUBLIC OF SOUTH AFRICA

Professional liability of accountants and auditors

Defense of State Employees: LIABILITY AND LAWSUITS. UNCW Office of General Counsel January 2010

In The Supreme Court of Bermuda

The Civil Law of Bribery

Things you may not know about trustee liability

This helpsheet is for ICAEW Chartered Accountants in both business and public practice.

CUBIC ENERGY, INC. Code of Business Conduct and Ethics

Motor fraud update a legal perspective on the issue of tainting in road traffic accidents. Sarah Hill Partner, BLM Birmingham

Beattie v Secretary of State for Social Security,

Higher National Unit specification. General information for centres. Unit title: Legal and Ethical Issues. Unit code: F50D 35

REHABILITATION OF OFFENDERS CHAPTER 100 REHABILITATION OF OFFENDERS ARRANGEMENT OF SECTIONS

CORPORATE GOVERNANCE AND KEY COMPANY LAW ISSUES IN CHALLENGING ECONOMIC TIMES

CIVIL FRAUD BACK TO BASICS

Client Alert. Good Faith Obligations in English Law. 8 July By Alistair Maughan and Sarah Wells

Fiscal Policies and Procedures Fraud, Waste & Abuse

Insurance Contracts Bill

GUIDANCE FOR EMPLOYED BARRISTERS. Part 1. General

The Fraud Act and the Future of Fraud Prosecutions

CIS/3066/1998 OF THE COMMISSIONER

Role of Executors (and Trustees) in claims

AGGREGATION OF CLAIMS AGAINST SOLICITORS AND SURVEYORS

NOT TO BE PUBLISHED IN THE OFFICIAL REPORTS IN THE COURT OF APPEAL OF THE STATE OF CALIFORNIA SECOND APPELLATE DISTRICT DIVISION TWO

The Duty of Solicitors to Give Tax Advice - A Rebuttal of the Reply

VERSUS 9th JUDICIAL DISTRICT COURT. LOUISIANA COLLEGE and JOE AGUILLARD RAPIDES PARISH, LOUISIANA PETITION FOR DAMAGES

Transcription:

Persistent problems with the objective dishonesty test The cases following the admirably clear decision in Barlow Clowes v Eurotrust have proved themselves broadly incapable of applying the equally admirably clear test in Royal Brunei Airlines v Tan. The sections to follow consider some more recent decisions which have experienced problems with its application. It is an odd thing that even though Lord Nicholls was so very clear in Royal Brunei Airlines v Tan that the test for dishonesty in dishonest assistance was an entirely objective test, and even despite the confirmation of that position by the Privy Council in Barlow Clowes v Eurotrust, there have nevertheless been a surprising number of cases which have assumed that the test is comprised of two elements: the first, a requirement that the defendant must have been demonstrated to have been dishonest by the standards of honest people and, secondly, that the defendant herself must have realised that. This was the approach seemingly taken by Arden LJ in Abou Rahmah v Abacha, even though she purported to be applying an objective test. It is suggested that her ladyship s approach is simply wrong both because it misapplies the test in Royal Brunei Airlines v Tan and because it is wrong philosophically. I shall take each in turn. First, these cases avowedly follow the decisions in Royal Brunei Airlines v Tan and in Barlow Clowes v Eurotrust and therefore they ought not to permit any reference to whether or not the defendant appreciated that honest people would consider her behaviour to have been dishonest: they are considered in the next section. Secondly, it is too easy for a defendant to escape liability simply by saying that she had not realised that reasonable people would consider them to be dishonest. In this way, the more immoral a defendant is, the less likely she is to be found dishonest. Apparent judicial difficulties with applying an objective test literally A slightly different, third approach to the test for dishonesty has been suggested by Sir Anthony Clarke MR in an article to the effect that the test is an objective one but that nevertheless the court should take into account the circumstances in which the defendant was acting and the level of experience which the defendant had. His lordship suggested in that article as follows: 1 The test is an objective one, but an objective one which takes account of the individual in question s characteristics, experience, knowledge etc.. It is a test which requires a court to assess an individual s conduct according to an objective standard of dishonesty. In doing so, a court has to take account of what the individual knew, his experience, intelligence and reasons for acting as he did. Whether the individual was aware that his conduct fell below the objective standard is not part of the test. This approach is still inserting subjectivity into the test. What is one supposed to do having decided that the defendant is experienced and intelligent? Presumably, one is to be held liable because of one s experience and intelligence, whereas the stupid and 1 Clarke, Claims against professionals: negligence, dishonesty and fraud [2006] 22 Professional Negligence 70-85. 1

inexperienced are to escape liability because of their stupidity and inexperience, even though their actions would by definition have been considered to be dishonest by honest and reasonable people. The purpose of this area of law is to protect the position of beneficiaries of fiduciary arrangements: therefore the risk of the stupidity of third parties dealing with the trust is thrown onto the beneficiaries. That has never been the approach of equity. Nevertheless, in AG Zambia v Meer Care & Desai & Others 2 Peter Smith J held that this was the proper approach, and this approach was followed in Markel International Insurance Co Ltd v Surety Guarantee Consultants Ltd. 3 So in Markel the defendant contended that he was not dishonest because of the circumstances in which he was acting: i.e. he asked the experienced bond traders with whom he was dealing whether or not all was well with a series of bond transactions and contended that he was entitled simply to rely on their answers without considering the matter further himself. The defendant contended therefore that he had not been dishonest because he had relied on the answers given to his questions by the professionals whom he was entitled to trust with those transactions. It is suggested that this is a question which goes to the question of whether or not honest and reasonable people would have thought his behaviour had been dishonest. That is simply a part of the decision as to whether or not in those circumstances an honest person would have acted as the defendant acted. It is definitively not a question as to whether or not the defendant subjectively appreciated that her own behaviour was dishonest according to social mores. Therefore, it is suggested that this should not be considered to be a distinct, third approach to the question of dishonesty at all but rather that it should be considered to be necessarily a part of the question as to whether or not the defendant was dishonest by the lights of honest and reasonable people, as required by Lord Nicholls in Tan. Nevertheless, in Markel the judge, Tearse J, spent a large amount of the latter stages of his judgment considering what the defendant honestly thought and did not think, as opposed to deciding objectively what did the judge consider an honest person would have thought. So, despite his lordship s analysis of the law, his approach lapsed almost absentmindedly into a subjective examination of the defendant s own state of mind. 4 In that judgment many pages were spent on analysing the appropriate objectivity of the test for dishonesty and then, remarkably enough, many more pages considering the evidence as to what the defendant subjectively thought. This was his lordship s error. If the test is one of objective dishonesty, then it cannot matter at all what the defendant thought subjectively because objective dishonesty (as set out in Tan) requires asking only what an honest and reasonable person would have done in the circumstances. 2 [2007] EWHC 952 (Ch). 3 [2008] EWHC 1135 (Comm), [2008] All ER (D) 10. 4 See, for example, ibid., para [209]: For these reasons I have reached the conclusion that he did not honestly believe that his conduct in signing bonds in excess of the stated limits was justifiable and more generally the defendant s motive of taking this role that he wanted a quiet life : none of this can matter because all that matters is what would an honest person have done in the circumstances. Elsewhere in the same case, where two other defendants were demonstrated to have assisted a breach of a company s fiduciary duties dishonestly (without there being any real question that they had been dishonest on any basis), then those two defendants were held liable for knowingly assisting [sic] to the beneficiary of that fiduciary relationship; see para [237]. 2

So, our first persistent problem with the application of the objective test in the cases is that the judges often lapse into questioning the subjective mind-set of the defendant even though the test requires that we do not consider it. What would be acceptable is to ask what an honest person would have done in those circumstances; what is not acceptable is to ask what the defendant subjectively thought would have been honest in the circumstances. An objective test requires that the judge decide what an honest person would have done in the circumstances; or perhaps if there is a formal regulatory code in existence the judge should ask whether the defendant complied with it because such a regulatory code could be taken as a statement of what a person should have done in the circumstances. 5 The objective test requires only that the view of the honest person be established. What the defendant thought does not matter: as was made clear in Barlow Clowes v Eurotrust. There are other cases in which High Court judges have tried to gloss the objective test in other ways. For example, in Attorney General of Zambia v Meer Care & Desai 6 Peter Smith J constructed a peculiar test for dishonesty to the effect that it is essentially a question of fact whereby the state of mind of the Defendant had to be judged in the light of his subjective knowledge but by reference to an objective standard of honesty 7 and that [t]he test is clearly an objective test but the breach involves a subjective assessment of the person in question in the light of what he knew at the time as distinct from what a reasonable person would have known or appreciated. It is not at all apparent from the leading authorities considered above why anyone should think that this is so. If the test is an objective test then it definitively does not require questioning the defendant s subjective state of mind. If one nevertheless wants this hybrid test to be the test in English law then one must stop pretending that one is applying the test set out by Lord Nicholls in Royal Brunei Airlines v Tan or in Dubai Aluminium v Salaam or the Privy Council in Barlow Clowes v Eurotrust, as considered above. On appeal, the Court of Appeal in Attorney General of Zambia v Meer Care & Desai 8 observed Smith J s use of this odd test in relation to dishonest assistance but did not cite any of the House of Lords, Privy Council or even Court of Appeal decisions considered thus far in its own deliberations as to the nature of the liability, which is really quite odd. This is of a piece with the frankly mistaken approach of Arden LJ in Abou-Rahmah v Abacha discussed above. There are decisions of the High Court which purport to be using an objective test but which nevertheless cannot stop themselves from delving into the subjective state of the defendant s own attitudes, knowledge and beliefs. The meaning of dishonesty in other contexts relating to professionals 5 See Alastair Hudson, The Law of Finance (Sweet & Maxwell, 2009), Chapter 3. 6 [2007] EWHC 952 (Ch). 7 Ibid, para [334]. 8 [2008] EWCA Civ 1007, para [151] et seq. The Court of Appeal ultimately failed to find any dishonesty on the facts of the case. 3

In Bryant v Law Society 9 an interesting example of the test of dishonesty arose before the Divisional Court in relation to two solicitors who were involved, in contravention of the Law Society s regulatory system on money laundering and other fraudulent transactions, in what was allegedly professional misconduct involving dishonesty. The solicitors clients organised for large payments to be made through their solicitors instead of through a bank as the parties contracts required without the solicitors asking any questions of their clients. The circumstances of the payments bore all the hallmarks of money laundering and were exactly the sort of transactions described as being prohibited in the relevant Law Society circulars. The criminal law test of dishonesty set out famously in R v Ghosh 10 requires first that one identify what is objectively dishonest, and secondly that one ask whether or not the defendant was aware that his conduct was dishonest. In Bryant v Law Society one of the solicitors in question suggested that he honestly believed that what he was doing was honest and reasonable. The court considered that the test of dishonesty to be applied by the tribunal was a test which took into account the solicitor s own perspective on what was honest. The solicitors were found, on the application of the subjective test, nevertheless to have committed professional misconduct. The question remains as to the operation of this test in the abstract. As with Barlow Clowes v Eurotrust, what of the situation in which the professional contends that her behaviour was subjectively reasonable and honest. The concern must be that because the defendant was so anti-social as to have an inappropriate sense of the proprieties of life and thus to have a personal morality which meant that she considered her objectively dishonest behaviour to be subjectively honest, then she would escape liability. Without wishing to over-dramatize, this is the attitude of sociopaths: I think what I am doing is acceptable, even though the rest of you say you think something else. What the court should have found in Bryant was that because this person by his own admission had no understanding of the requirements of proper behaviour then he should be held liable for dishonesty. In Twinsectra v Yardley the majority of the House of Lords excused a solicitor from liability on the basis that it was a serious thing to condemn a professional man for dishonesty if he had not appreciated subjectively that that would be considered to be the case; and in Bryant v Law Society the court expressed concern at the notion that a solicitor might otherwise be subjected to liability when he might not have realised that his actions would have been considered to have been dishonest by honest people. A better approach, it is suggested, would be to hold professional people (above all others) to an objective standard of honest behaviour. Professional people acting in their professional capacities should be expected to be rational and compliant with the appropriate professional ethics and regulatory rulebooks in the conduct of their duties. To excuse them on the basis of their imperfect understanding of what other people expect is for the law to demonstrate a sort of moral cowardice. This urge to protect professional people on account of their own moral weakness must stop. Leaving the criminal context aside for a moment, the question for private law is to identify what the law considers to be honest in the abstract (that is, objectively) and then 9 [2009] 1 WLR 163. 10 [1982] QB 1053. 4

to measure individual defendants up against that standard. One of the principal roles of law is to judge. Another role (of property law and contract law in particular) is to offer models to the citizenry by reference to which they can organise their communal activities. In either event, the role of the law is to judge which structures and activities are worthy of the support of law and which are not. Therefore, the law does not need to pander to the subjective standards of honesty and dishonesty of any individual defendant. Instead, the law stands in judgment over them. It is a matter for the criminal law to decide how squeamish it is about criminalising people who did not realise that ordinary decent people would have considered their behaviour to be dishonest, but there is no reason why anyone (solicitor or not) should escape liability to compensate a claimant under private law simply because they were similarly unconscious of the standards of the society around them. Ignorance of the law is generally considered to be no defence; so why should ignorance of the standards of honest conduct be similarly a defence. This urge to require that the defendant must realise that what she was doing was contrary to social mores is weak-kneed liberalism of the most obvious kind. Liberalism is tolerant and open-minded: it is therefore weak when it is confronted by people who simply refuse to play the game, to recognise ordinary standards of common decency, and so forth. So, instead of condemning people who would be thought dishonest by the reasonable person, liberalism of this weak sort excuses them from liability if they had failed to notice what was evident to honest people and apologises for having troubled them. Our private law should condemn such people so as to protect those objective standards simply for the ethical imperative of preventing unconscionable benefit being taken from inappropriate behaviour and also pour encourager les autres. 5