Adverse Selection. Chapter 3

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Adverse Selection. Chapter 3"

Transcription

1 Chapter 3 Adverse Selection Adverse selection, sometimes known as The Winner s Curse or Buyer s Remorse, is based on the observation that it can be bad news when an o er is accepted. Suppose that a buyer makes an o er to buy a good from a seller who knows more about its value than the buyer does. This is called a situation of asymmetric information. The buyer must beware because a seller with a high-quality good will probably not sell it at a given price, while a seller with a low-quality good will be happy to unload it at the same price. There are two related approaches to equilibrium analysis in the context of adverse selection. A general equilibrium analysis requires assumptions about the relative market power for buyers and sellers; these assumptions specify the division of gains from trade, if any, and thus identify equilibrium price(s). It is still necessary to adjust the re ne the description of general equilibrium to incorporate the buyer s uncertainty about the quality of products she wishes to buy. 1 As a result, some of the properties of general equilibrium (e.g. the First Welfare Theorem) do not hold in the context of adverse selection, and in particular, equilibrium outcomes may not be Pareto optimal for buyer and seller. A game theoretic analysis requires speci c information about the nature of interactions between buyers and sellers so that it is possible to translate that information into an extensiveform game and solve for a Nash equilibrium. The game theoretic analysis does not directly 1 Note that with a random selection of goods sold at any price (so that there is no correlation between the availability of a good at a given price and the quality that good), uncertainty could be incorporated into a general equilibrium analysis that allows for risk aversion in individual preferences. 92

2 specify the relative market power of buyers and sellers. Instead, the nature of market power emerges endogenously on the basis of the order of moves within the extensive form game. These two distinct approaches to equilibrium analysis tend to coincide in their results. However, both require quite speci c assumptions in order to identify an equilibrium. It is also possible to consider a third approach, simply identifying all market prices and allocations of goods that yield gains from trade to both buyer and seller. This third approach identi es all outcomes that could plausibly result in equilibrium for some de nition of market power or description of the trading game played between buyer and seller. We utilize all three approaches during the course of this chapter, emphasizing the similarities and di erences between the game theory and general equilibrium predictions. 3.1 Motivating Examples We consider three classic examples of adverse selection where a buyer values a good more than its current owner (the seller). We use the most general approach - identifying the range of possible equilibrium prices without specifying market power (as necessary for a general equilibrium approach) or the order of moves (as necessary for a game theory approach) in the rst two examples, but revert to a more speci c approach for the third example of insurance to ease algebraic computation The Market for Lemons Suppose that the buyer is a consumer without a car and the seller is a used car owner. This example was originally suggested by George Akerlof in a paper that is so widely read that this example is sometimes called Akerlof s Lemons Market. With probability, the used car is high quality (a Peach ) while with probability 1 the used car is low quality (a Lemon ). A Peach is worth $3,000 to a buyer and $2,500 to a seller. A Lemon is worth $2,000 to a buyer and $1,000 to a seller. 2 If the car is sold at price p, then the buyer s payo is v b p, where v b is the true value to the buyer, and the seller s payo is p v s, where v s is the true value to the seller. 2 These values match the ones given in Kreps (1990). Akerlof (1970) did not analyze the two-type case in any detail, considering instead an example that more closely resembles the Takeover Game. 93

3 We begin with a general analysis to identify possible equilibrium prices without specifying the exact game that the buyer and seller play to arrive at a particular equilibrium price. Since the buyer cannot distinguish between a Peach and a Lemon, the market price must be the same for peaches and lemons. 3 A seller who owns a Peach will only sell it if the market price is at least $2,500, while a seller who owns a Lemon will sell it if the market price is at least $1, With only two types of cars, there is a discontinuity in the expected value of cars sold as a function of the price, as shown in Figure 3-1. The average value of a car for a buyer conditional on a sale at a price of $2,501 (a combination of Lemons and Peaches) is much higher than the average value of a car for a buyer conditional on a sale at a price of $2,499 (just Lemons). At a price of $2,500 or more, owners of Lemons and owners of Peaches will sell their cars, so the average value to buyers is (1 ) 2000 = : At a price between $1,000 and $2,499, owners of Lemons will sell their cars, but owners of peaches will not, so the average value to buyers is simply the value of a lemon, $2,000. Finally, at a price below $1,000, no owners will sell their cars (but if there existed some car even worse than a lemon, its owner might sell it at this price, so it is appropriate to graph a value below $2,000 for these market prices). A market price is a possible equilibrium price with positive probability of trade if 1) each type of seller trades only if the price is greater than the value of the car to the owner and at least one type of seller accepts the o er; 5 2) the price yields an expected pro t to the buyer given the knowlege of which types of sellers will transact at that price. The requirement that the buyer anticipates the decisions of sellers at the time that she formulates her o er is commonly known in general equilibrium analysis as a Rational Expectations condition. Rational expectations is already implicit in the best response requirement for Nash equilibrium in a game theoretic formulation. Thus Rational Expectations Equilibrium (REE) and Nash Equilibrium should be expected to produce similar predictions for super cially di erent approaches to analyzing the bilateral interaction between buyer and seller. 3 In the remainder of this example, we describe the trading outcome as though there are many buyers and many sellers. The same calculations apply for the case of one buyer and one seller. 4 For simplicity, we assume that the seller with a peach will accept an o er of exactly $2,500, while a seller with a lemon will accept an o er of exactly $1, With a continuous distribution of types for the seller, we would rephrase this requirement to say that the seller accepts the price with positive probability. 94

4 Value to Buyer E(v v < x) $( q) $2000 Bid (x) $1000 $2500 Figure 3-1: Expected Value of Cars Sold We now consider each price range in turn to identify the set of possible equilibrium prices these are prices that could result in a Rational Expectations Equilibrium or a Nash Equilibrium if we provided enough information to specify a particular REE or Nash outcome. A market price below $1,000 cannot produce an equilibrium with positive probability of trade because the price is not su ciently high for either type of seller to trade. A market price between $1,000 and $2,499 will induce sales of Lemons but will be rejected by owners of Peaches: the pro t to buyers at price p in this range is then $2,000 - p. So, if the price is between $1,000 and $2,000, it yields an expected pro t to the buyer, who recognizes that any car that is available at this price must be a lemon but is still willing to pay up to $2,000 for it. But if the price is between $2,001 and $2,499, the same logic implies that the buyer will lose money on any purchase. So market prices between $1,000 and $2,000 could produce an equilibrium where only lemons are sold, but market prices between $2,001 to $2,499 do not produce an equilibrium. 6 A market price of $2,500 or more will induce sales of both types of cars. Then buyer s expected value of a car conditional on a sale depends on the parameter : E(v b ) = (3; 000) + 6 The given de nition of an equilibrium requires that the buyer be willing to transact at the equilibrium price. So, while there is no trade at a price less than $1,000 and also that there would be no trade at a price between $2,001 and $2,499, prices less than $1,000 are equilibrium prices because buyers would be willing to transact at those prices. 95

5 (1 )(2; 000) = 1; ; 000:Subtracting the sale price, the buyer makes an expected pro t at price p if 1, ; 000 > p. At the minimum price in this range, p = $2,500, the buyer makes an expected pro t if > 1/2. So if < 1/2, then the buyer loses money for each price of $2,500 or more. If > 1=2, then there is a range of possible equilibrium prices from p = $2,500 to p = $(1, ,000). But if < 1/2, then no price of $2,500 produces an equilibrium because buyers lose money on average at these prices. The conclusion is that if < 1/2, then the only possible equilibrium outcomes are 1) only lemons are traded and the equilibrium price is between $1,000 and $2,000; 2) no cars are traded and the equilibrium price is between $0 and $999. Yet, both types of cars are worth more to the buyer and the seller, so the outcome is economically ine cient if < 1/2. If 1/2, there is a third possibility: 3) both peaches and lemons are traded and the equilibrium price is between $2,500 and $3,000. In this case, trade is assured and the outcome is e cient, but peach owners gain less than lemon owners from trade since the transaction price is the same for both types of cars. This is known as cross-subsidization. The price of a peach is arti cially depressed and the price of a lemon is arti cially in ated because buyers cannot distinguish one from the other. Price Range Seller s Response Buyer s Pro t p < $1; 000 No Trade Zero Pro t $1; 000 p $2; 000 Trade Lemons Positive $2; 000 < p $2; 500 Trade Lemons Negative $2; 500 p $3; 000 Trade Lemons, Trade Peaches Positive if 1=2 p > $3; 000 Trade Lemons, Trade Peaches Negative Table 1: Prices and Results for the Lemons Market Example Table 1 summarizes the results for the Lemons Market example with these values. Prices between $1,000 and $2,000 are always possible equilibrium prices where only lemons are sold. Prices between $2,500 and $3,000 are possible equilibrium prices where both types of cars are traded, but only if the proportion of peaches is su ciently high. The condition 1=2 highlights the tradeo produced by adverse selection. Whether the car is a lemon or a peach, the buyer values it more than the seller, so there are possible gains from trade from 96

6 transacting. However, these gains are reduced from the buyer s perspective because of the buyer s informational disadvantage. There can be an equilibrium where both types are traded so long as the buyer s gains from trading both cars are large enough to overcome the costs of adverse selection for the buyer which occurs when the proportion of peaches is su ciently large. 7 The Takeover Game Suppose that the buyer is a business executive who knows that he can improve the value of an existing company by 50%. The seller knows the exact value of the company, but the buyer does not. The buyer s best assessment is that the current value, v, is equally likely to be any number between 0 and 100. That is, v is uniformly distributed on (0; 100). We say that v is the seller s type, which is private information to the seller. If the seller of type v accepts an o er of price p to sell the company, then the buyer receives a payo of 1:5v p, while the seller receives a payo of v. If the seller rejects the o er, the buyer receives a payo of 0 and the seller retains the company at its current value for a payo of v. Both parties are assumed to be risk neutral. On average, the company is worth E(v) = 50 to the seller and E(1:5v) = 75 to the buyer. Since the value of the company always increases after a sale, it is natural to imagine a solution where the buyer pays 62.5 to the seller and each side gets an average pro t of 12.5 because of the gain in e ciency - transferring the company to the more e ective management team. But adverse selection precludes this option, for the seller will not accept any o er unless p > v, so sellers of types 62.5 or more would not sell at a price of The only market price that ensures a transaction is p = 100, but this price cannot be sustained in an equilibrium. At price p = 100, the buyer loses an average of 25 because he is paying 100 for a company with expected value 75 after accounting for the 50% gain in value due to the sale. In fact, no positive market price can be sustained as an equilibrium. At any positive price 7 Note that the cost of adverse selection is a function of downside risk (i.e. the probability of a Lemon) rather than of uncertainty. For example, a distribution with 80% probability of a Lemon and 20% probability of a Peach has the same variance for the seller s value as does a distribution with 80% probability of a Peach and 20% probability of a Lemon. So these distributions of types embody similar levels of uncertainty, but only the more favorable distribution can produce an equilibrium where Peaches are traded. 97

7 p, the seller accepts the o er only if his type is less than or equal to p: 8 Conditional on the seller s willingness to sell at a price of p, the buyer updates his assessment to conclude that v is uniformly distributed between 0 and p. This is the bad news element of adverse selection - for any o er, the buyer only receives the lowest quality goods. In expected value, the buyer s anticipates the seller s decision rule; at a market price of p, the buyer s rational expectation is that the expected value of v for a company that is available at a price of p is p=2 (the expected value for a uniform distribution ranging from 0 to p). 9 Similarly, the average pro t to the buyer at market price p is E((p)) = [Probability(p is accepted) [E(1:5vjp is accepted) p] = ( p ) [E(1:5vjx > p) 100 p] = ( p 100 ) (3p 4 p) = p : That is, the buyer loses money on average for each p > 0 and loses even more money the higher the o er. Although the company is known to be worth more to the buyer than to the seller, there is no equilibrium with a positive probability of trade - regardless of whether the interaction is modeled as a game with a Nash equilibrium or as a general equilibrium trading market with a Rational Expectations Equilibrium. Adverse selection provides such a large obstacle that it precludes trade in this example despite the obvious bene ts from improving the management of the company. bene ts were even larger, then trade could occur. But if the For example, if the new management would triple the value of the company, then a price of 100 would be accepted by each type of seller and would provide the buyer with an expected pro t of 50, since the expected value of the company would be 150 with new management. from trade and cost from informational asymmetries. This highlights, once again, the tradeo between gains If the gains from trade are su ciently 8 We assume that values and o ers can take any real value from 0 to 100. Then the seller s action when v = p does not a ect the overall average payo s because v = p occurs with probability 0. 9 Similarly, the buyer s assessment of v jumps to (1 + x)=2 if the seller rejects the o er, but this conditional expected value has no e ect on the payo s in the game. 98

8 large, then an e cient outcome (trade with probability 1) would still result despite the buyer s losses due to adverse selection if v is close to zero. Experimental Evidence: The term "Takeover Game" indicates that this situation has been commonly modeled as a sequential move game with the buyer making a take it or leave it o er to the seller. The only Nash (or subgame perfect) equilibrium is for the buyer to make no o er at all, and so the company is never sold. Samuelson and Bazerman (1985) tested the equilibrium prediction of this model with MBA students making bids for the company. More than 70% of the students made bids of 50 or more; fewer than 10% of the students bid A Simple Insurance Market Suppose that a risk averse consumer has wealth W and faces a risk of losing it all with probability t. The consumer has utility function u(w) = p w. Since she is risk averse, the consumer would like to insure against a loss with a (risk neutral) insurance company. The di culty is that the consumer knows t, but the insurance company does not. Suppose that the insurance company assesses a uniform distribution on t across all values from 0 to 1. Once again, there are obvious gains from trade for these two parties, but the gains are imperiled by the presence of asymmetric information. Suppose that all insurance is full insurance and that the market price is p. If the consumer accepts the policy, she receives a nal wealth of W p whether or not she has a loss. (If there is a loss of wealth W, the consumer pays p to the company as a premium and is reimbursed for the entire loss.) If the consumer does not accept the policy, she receives a nal wealth of W if there is no loss and a nal wealth of 0 if there is a loss. Given a price of p, the consumer will buy insurance if 10 These experimental results provide a strong critique of the Rational Expectations requirement; it is not clear that participants understand that they should reduce their assessment of v when a bid for the company is accepted. See Thaler, "The Winner s Curse," chapter 5, for broad discussion of this phenomenon and Eyster and Rabin, "Cursed Equilibrium" for a recent technical paper that summarizes relevant experimental results and provides an alternative model to Rational Expectations / Nash equilibrium. 99

9 p W p (1 t) p W + t p 0 r W W p 1 t t 1 r W W p That is, the consumer chooses full insurance at price p if the risk is high enough. This phenomenon poses a problem for the insurance company, because the company can rationally anticipate that the consumer will only buy insurance if she is a relatively bad risk. Note that adverse selection occurs in this example because the seller (the insurance company) lacks information about the buyer (the consumer), in contrast to the Lemons and Takeover examples. But the company can adjust the price to manage the tradeo between sales and adverse selection. At a price p = W, the consumer never buys insurance (the condition for purchase simpli es to t 1), while at a price p = 0, the consumer always buys insurance (the condition for purchase simpli es to t 0). 11 So, at a market price of p for full insurance, the consumer will accept if t is between 1 p (W p)=w and 1. The market price necessary to guarantee that all consumers will insure is p = 0, but at this price, the insurance company loses money for certain. So there cannot be an equilibrium where every type of consumer would buy insurance. For any price p > 0; not all types of consumers buy insurance. With a uniform distribution on 0 to 1 for t, the consumer accepts the o er p with probability p (W t)=w. Further, the expected value of t conditional on purchasing insurance is therefore: E(t j bought insurance, price p) = 1 r 1 W 2 W p Given a sale, the company expects to pay an average value of W E(t j bought insurance) to the consumer in exchange for the consumer s insurance premium of p. For the company to 11 In practice, the insurance company can also o er partial insurance of losses or can add stipulations, such as a deductible, to the policy to discourage some types of consumers from buying insurance. 100

10 at least break even on insurance, then the price must satisfy: p W 1 r 1 W 2 W! p This is a complicated equation (it can be expanded into a fourth-order polynomial in p) with the solution that p 3W 4, meaning that the possible equilibrium prices all involve relatively high prices. Insurance is limited to consumers with t 1 2 if p = 3W 4, or to even fewer consumers if p > 3W Summary of Examples These examples illustrate the principal tradeo involved with Adverse Selection. Two parties can conduct a trade that would obviously be bene cial to both of them - if only they can agree on a price. But due to asymmetric information, the choice of the price limits the bene ts to one side, which may even lose on the transaction in some instances with a poor choice of price. The nature of the resulting equilibrium depends on the relative importance of the gains from trade in comparison to the severity of asymmetric information. The general model in the next section highlights this tradeo. 3.2 A General Model We now present a general model that encompasses each of the examples above. A seller has a good that is valued by buyers. The seller s value is V, drawn from a known distribution f(v) with corresponding cumulative distribution F (v) = P (V < v). We use V to denote the random variable for the seller s value and v to denote speci c values of V. We say that v is the seller s type and we assume that the seller is male and that the buyer is female. If the seller s value is v, then any buyer s value for the same good is b = h(v), where h is a (weakly) increasing function. The seller knows the true value v, while the buyer just knows 12 Of course, consumers with t < 1=2 are technically able to purchase insurance, but the price they would have to pay is too high to make it worthwhile for them. In an e cient market, these individuals would be able to buy full insurance at a fair price for their particular value of p. 101

11 its distribution f(v), with a minimum value of v L and a maximum value of v H. If a buyer and seller trade at price p then the buyer receives a payo of h(v) p and the seller receives a payo of p. If the o er is rejected, the buyer receives a payo of 0 and the seller receives a payo of v. 13 Combining the outcomes for buyer and seller, the net surplus of the transaction is h(v) v. From the perspective of social e ciency, the good should be sold if h(v) > v: In the examples discussed above, h(v) > v for all possible values of s, but this is not a necessary characteristic of all adverse selection models, and we do not assume it here. This formulation incorporates each of the examples described above, with the caveat that the insurance case requires negative values for v and h(v). To simplify exposition, we will assume that there are many buyers competing to make a purchase from a single seller, thereby giving full market power to the seller. We consider two di erent de nitions of equilibrium. The assumption of complete market power for the seller reduces the set of possible equilibrium prices in the motivating examples (using either equilibrium concept) to those where the buyer receives zero expected pro t. 14 In a Rational Expectations Equilibrium, the transaction price equals the expected value to buyers conditional on a trade; the seller enjoys all of the gains from trade in equilibrium as pro ts. Thus, any price that satis es the zero-pro t condition for buyers produces a Rational Expectations Equilibrium. The game theoretic approach incorporates the market power of the seller by assuming that the buyers move rst and making simultaneous price o ers to the seller. Formally, there are I buyers, with buyer i o ering price p i. The seller identi es the higher o er p, and rejects all lower o ers. In (a Nash) equilibrium, the seller accepts the highest o er p if p v. 15 If more than one buyer makes that highest o er, then the seller randomizes among them with equal probability (assuming p v). This is a sequential move game and so the appropriate 13 It would be equilvalent to assume that the seller s payo is p v for a sale at price p and 0 for no trade. In either case, the seller pro ts only by selling at a price with p > v. 14 For example, if > 1=2 in the Lemons example, then the equilibrium price when all goods are traded and the seller has full market power is p = 1; : At this price, all buyers, including the one who is able to buy a car at this price, make zero expected pro ts. 15 The same result would occur if there are many buyers and many sellers, but the number of buyers is su ciently large to give complete market power to the sellers. 102

12 solution concept is either Bayes Nash equilibrium or subgame perfect equilibrium. 16 While buyers have incomplete information about the seller s type, they do not have to respond to an action by the seller so we do not use Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium as the solution concept. Proposition 1 There may be multiple Rational Expectations Equilibria. In almost every case, there is a unique subgame perfect equilibrium with price equal to the highest Rational Expectations Equilibrium price. Subgame perfect equilibrium analysis of this game is straightforward because it is a weakly dominant strategy for the seller to accept a price p if p > v, so the seller follows this strategy in every subgame perfect equilibrium; however, it is possible that the seller deviates from this strategy o the equilibrium path in a Bayes-Nash equilibrium. 17 In either case, if the higher price o ered by a buyer is p, then the probability that the o er is accepted is equal to F (p ), the probability that the seller has a value that is lower than p. Given price p, then the expected value to the buyer conditional on a sale is E(h(v) j v p ). Combining these values, the expected pro t to the buyer who makes the highest price o er, p, is (p ) = P (seller accepts o er p ) E( b j seller accepts bid) (p ) = F (p ) [E(h(v)jV p ) p ]. Thus, the buyer who o ers the highest price, p, makes an expected pro t if (p ) is positive, meaning that the conditional expected value E(h(v)jV p ), is greater than the bid price p. There cannot be a Subgame Perfect equilibrium with expected pro ts to the buyers, for otherwise some buyer would do better by deviating from the proposed equilibrium strategy to an o er of p + ". So the price in any SPE is a zero-pro t price for buyers. 16 We use the terms Bayes-Nash equilibrium and Nash equilibrium interchangeably in this chapter. Note that in the case of adverse selection, the seller s type in uences the payo to the buyer even given the seller s action - a contrast to the discussion of Bayes-Nash equilibrium in the previous chapter. 17 We assume that the seller accepts the o er if v = p, which makes the seller indi erent between accepting and rejecting the o er. As in the earlier example, this tiebreaking rule has no e ect on expected pro ts if f is continuous. assumes that the seller accepts the o er in the case of a tie with v = p. As in the earlier example, the tiebreaking rule has no e ect on expected pro ts if f is continuous. 103

13 In fact, in almost every instance, there is a unique SPE price equal to the highest zero-pro t price for buyers. If there are multiple zero-pro t prices, p 1 and p 2 with p 2 > p 1 then both then p 1 and p 2 are REE prices, but there is almost always a price between p 1 and p 2 that yields an expected pro t to buyers. In this case, there cannot be a subgame perfect equilibrium with equilibrium price p 1 because buyers would have a pro table deviation to a price between p 1 and p 2. The only exception is if somehow E(h(v)j v p 1 ) = p 1, E(h(v)j v p 2 ) = p 2, but E(h(v)j v < p) < p for all other prices with p > p 1. In this exceptional case there could be multiple subgame perfect equilibria with di erent zero pro t prices. The seller s actions o the equilibrium path are less restricted in a Bayes-Nash equilibrium. For this reason, it is possible to construct a Bayes-Nash equilibrium for any zero-pro t price for the buyers. In fact, it is also possible to use strategies of the form described in the text to produce a Bayes-Nash equilibrium with any price that gives the buyer an expected pro t. For example, we can sustain a Bayes-Nash equilibrium at a price p 0 that is pro table for buyers by assuming that the seller responds appropriately to price p 0, selling if v p 0, but will not accept any other o er Systematic Analysis of the Lemons Model We can produce much of the intuition for our general results in the context of the Lemons model, which does not require complicated notation or computation of conditional expectations. In the Lemons model, there are just two types of sellers, those that own peaches and those that own lemons. The distribution F consists of just one parameter in this case, the probability that any single car is a peach, or P (Peach) =. A Peach is worth b H to a buyer and r H to a seller, while a Lemon is worth b L to a buyer and r L to a seller with b H > b L and r H > r L. We denote the value to the seller by r to indicate the fact this is the seller s "reservation value" for selling a car. We also assume b H > r H otherwise, peaches will never be sold and negotiations between buyer and seller are just about the price for a lemon. In equilibrium with b H > b L and r H > r L, there can be only two possible prices: 1) equilibrium price = the value of a lemon, b L if only lemons are sold; 2) equilibrium price = the buyer s unconditional expected value of a car, E(b), if both lemons and peaches are sold. Thus, there are two possible two zero-pro t prices (for buyers) with a positive probability of sale: p = b L and p = E(v). In addition, 104

14 there is always the possibility of an equilibrium with no sale technically all prices p < r L are zero-pro t prices because neither type of seller would accept a price in this range. We focus on the possibility of a no-trade equilibrium with price just below the seller s reservation value for a lemon, p = r L. We distinguish between two types of zero-pro t REE s in our analysis. An REE is unstable if a small deviation in the price o ered by one buyer would increase the payo s for both that buyer and the seller. 18 An REE is stable if no small deviation in price by one buyer would increase the payo s for both that buyer and the seller. If a single buyer deviates to a price o er slightly below a given REE level, no seller would consider this o er. For this reason, we only need to check whether a buyer could pro t by o ering a price slightly higher than a given REE level to determine if each REE price is stable or unstable. No trade with p = r L is always an REE, but it is only stable if b L r L. Otherwise, a small deviation to a price slightly more than r L would lead to sales of lemons that produce gains from trade to both buyer and seller. Similarly, trade of lemons with p = b L produces an REE if b L r L and r H > b L. Under both of these conditions, a seller who owns a lemon will sell it at price b L, but a seller who owns a peach will not sell at that price. Then a small increase in price will not produce a pro t for the buyer, since this would only cause the buyer to overpay for a lemon, and is not a pro table deviation for a buyer from an REE with p = b L. Trade of both types of cars with p = E(b) is an REE if E(b) r H. This is always a stable equilibrium because a small increase in price would simply guarantee a sale at a price greater than the expected value to buyers. Note that if r H b L, which precludes an REE with sale of lemons only, then E(b) > b L > r H and so there must be an REE with sale of both types of cars. Summarizing these results: 1) if b L < r L and E(b) < r H, then there is a unique REE with p = r L and no trade, and this equilibrium is stable; 2) if b L < r L and E(b) > r H, then there are two stable REE s, one with with p = r L and no trade and one with p = E(b) where both types of cars are traded; 3) if b L > r L and E(b) < r H, there is an unstable REE with p = r L 18 By de nition, an unstable Nash equilibrium is based on actions o the equilibrium path that are not best responses for small changes in price. Otherwise, at least one buyer would o er a slightly di erent price to increase payo from the equilibrium result. 105

15 and a stable REE with p = r L where only lemons are sold; 4) if b L > r L and E(b) > r H, there is an unstable REE with p = r L and two stable Nash equilibria, one with p = r L where only lemons are sold and one with p = E(b) where both types of cars are traded. Subgame perfect equilibrium requires buyers to anticipate the pro t-maximizing responses by the seller to all possible deviations in price. In cases 1) and 3) above where there is a unique stable REE, then this is also the unique SPE, because this is the highest possible zero-pro t price. In 2) and 4) above, where there are multiple stable REE s, then there is a unique SPE at the highest REE price. When there are multiple equilibria, the lower price generally fails because a deviation to a slightly higher price would be pro table for one of the buyers. 19 As mentioned above, any REE price can be sustained in a Nash equilibrium, The comparison between E(b) and r H summarizes the tradeo s inherent in the adverse selection model. Here, E(b) = b H + (1 )b L, so the condition for both types of cars to be traded is b H + (1 )b L r H. By rearranging this condition, we can highlight the importance of each of several parameters. Isolating, the condition for trade of all cars is (r H b L ) =(b H b L ). So for any xed values r H ; b H, and b L satsifying r H > b L and b H > b L, there is a cuto value between 0 and 1 so that the condition for full trade can be written as >. 20 Translated into words, if the number of peaches is su ciently large relative to the number of lemons, then there is a subgame perfect equilibrium where all cars are sold. Similarly, xing other factors and isolating either b H or b L, the condition for trade of all cars can be written as b H [r H (1 )b L ]= or as b L (r H b H )=(1 ). So there are cuto values b H and b L such that b H > b H ( xing and b L) or b L b L ( xing and b H) is su cient for all cars to be sold. These conditions indicate that if the gains from trade are su ciently large, then adverse selection does not prevent the trade of all cars. In the numerical example at the start of the chapter, b L > r L and b H > r H, so when a fulltrade equilibrium exists, it is e cient. However, if b L < r L, it is possible to have a full-trade equilibrium that is ine cient. In this case, it is e cient for peaches but not for lemons to be traded. Regardless of and the speci c values to buyer and seller, no Nash equilibrium in the 19 The one exception to this statement occurs when one of the equilibrium conditions holds with equality. For example, if b L > r L and E(b) = r H, then there are two REE outcomes, p = r L and p = E(b), which can both be sustained in SPE s. Given the strict equality, E(b) = r H, a deviation from price p = r L to a price just below E(b) will be unpro table because it will not induce peach owners to sell. 20 As noted above, if r H < b L, then the condition for full trade holds for any. 106

16 adverse selection game is e cient if b L < r L and b H > r H. Systematic Analysis of the Continuous Case The intuition from the two-type lemons market case carries over to the continuous case with an in nite number of types. The main point is that adverse selection involves tradeo s between 1) gains from trade and 2) cross-subsidization. If the gains from trade are large enough, then it is possible to sustain an equilibrium with a positive probability (possibly a certainty) of trade despite the problems due to adverse selection. We now proceed with equilibrium analysis for the continuous model. We focus on Rational Expectations equilibrium analysis in the discussion below because this is su cient to identify the subgame perfect equilibrium price as well. As we described in our general analysis for the Lemons market example, any REE is also a Nash equilibrium where all buyers o er the equilibrium price and the seller accepts that o er. 21 However, only the highest REE price can be sustained in a subgame perfect equilibrium except for the unusual case where there are multiple zero-pro t REE prices, but no prices between them where the buyer pro ts on average from trade. Boundary Equilibrium There are two possible boundary outcomes, one with (Rational Expectations) equilibrium price equal to the lowest possible value for the seller, v L, and another where the (Rational Expectations) equilibrium price is at least as large as the highest possible value for the seller, v H. In the rst case, p i = v L, the good is sold with probability zero 22 If h(v L ) > v L, then it would be pro table for one buyer to deviate to an o er slightly higher than v L, but still less than h(v L ). Thus, the condition for a stable REE with no one buying the good is simply h(v L ) < v L. In the second case, the good is sold with probability one. The average value to the buyers is then the unconditional expected value E(b) = E[h(v)]. If E[h(v)] v H, then it is unpro table 21 It is also possible for some buyers to o er prices less than the equilibrium price, p, in a Nash Equilibrium. But there must be at least two buyers who o er the REE price OR the seller must refuse all o ers below the REE price, for otherwise there would be a pro table deviation to a price below p. 22 Technically, the good would be sold if the seller s value is exactly v L, but this occurs with probability zero. 107

17 for a buyer to buy the good with probability 1 (at a price p = v H ). Thus, the condition for a stable REE in which the good is always sold is E[h(v)] v H, and the corresponding equilibrium price is p = E[h(v)]. The intuition implicit in this REE is that while all types of sellers would be willing to trade at p = v H, competition among buyers will drive the price to the higher zero-pro t price, p = E[h(v)]. Interior Equilibrium In an interior (Rational Expectations) equilibrium, the price falls in the range between v L and v H, meaning that some types of sellers will trade and others will not. Then there is a probability between 0 and 1 of a sale at price p, and the zero pro t condition for a REE is E[h(s)jS p ] = p : 23 This condition identi es a stable REE if a small deviation to a higher price is unpro table and an unstable Nash equilibrium if a small deviation to a higher price is pro table. If E[h(v)jV p] lies above p just to the left of equilibrium price p and lies below p just to the right of equilibrium price p, we call the intersection a "crossing from above", referring to the fact that the expected value curve lies above the price just before the intersection of these two curves. A "crossing from above" corresponds to a stable equilibrium, whereas a "crossing from below" corresponds to an unstable equilibrium, where the buyer could make a pro t at a price slightly higher than p Examples of Rational Expectations Equilibria with Adverse Selection The set of Rational Expectations outcomes can take any of several di erent forms, as shown in the following gures. In each of these gures, the position of the function E[h(v)jV p ] relative to p (the 45 line) determines whether an o er of p would be pro table to the buyers if that is the highest 23 Note that E[h(v)jV p ] p is the expected pro t-per-sale to the buyer, not the overall expected pro t for the buyer. The overall expected pro t to the buyer who makes the highest o er p takes into account the probablity that the o er is accepted by the seller: (p ) = P (V b ) [E(h(v)jV p ) p ]. 108

18 $ h(v) E[h(v) V< b*] 45 v L v H b* Figure 3-2: Adverse Selection Case #1 o er. If E[h(v)jV p ] lies above p, an o er of p would be pro table, while if E[h(v)jV p ] lies below p, an o er of p would be unpro table. Figures 3-2 through 3-4 depict three common cases when h(v L ) < v L. In Case 1, E[h(v)jV p ] < p for each value p in the range from v L to v H. the buyer, so there is a unique stable REE with p = v L : Every possible price is unpro table for In Case 2, E[h(v)jV p ] = p at two values, v 1 and v 2. Prices between v 1 and v 2 are pro table, while o ers below v 1 and above v 2 are unpro table for the buyer. There is a boundary REE with p = v L and two interior equilibria, one at p = v 1 and another at p = v 2. The equilibria at p = v L and p = v 2 are stable, while the equilibrium at p = v 1 is unstable. In Case 3, E[h(v)jV p ] = p at v 1. Prices below v 1 are unpro table for the buyer while prices between v 1 and v H are pro table for the buyer. There is a boundary REE with p = v L and an interior equilibrium with p = v 1. In addition, there is a REE with p = E[h(v)], with certainty (i.e. probability 1) of trade at the expected value to the buyer. The two boundary equilibria are stable, while the interior equilibrium is unstable. Figures 3-5 through 3-7 depict three common cases when h(v L ) > v L. In Case 4, E[h(v)jV p ] is greater than p for each value b p in the range from v L to v H. Every possible price in this range is pro table for the buyer, so there is a unique stable REE with p = E[h(v)] 109

19 $ h(v) E[h(v) V< b*] 45 v L v 1 * v 2 * v H b* Figure 3-3: Adverse Selection Case #2 $ h(v) E[h(v) V< b*] 45 v L v 1 * v H b* Figure 3-4: Adverse Selection Case #3 110

20 $ h(v) E[h(v) V< b*] 45 v L v H b* Figure 3-5: Adverse Selection Case #4 and probability 1 of a sale. (Technically there is also an unstable boundary equilibrium with p = v L.) In Case 5, E[h(v)jV p ] = p at a single value v1. Prices below v 1 are pro table for the buyer, while prices above v1 are unpro table for the buyer. There is a unique stable REE with p = v1. In Case 6, E[h(v)jV p ] = p at two values, v1 and v 2. Prices below v 1 and prices between v2 and v H are pro table for the buyer, prices between v1 and v 2 are unpro table for the buyer. In this case, there are two interior equilibria at p = v1 and p = v2 and a boundary equilibrium at p = E[h(v)]. The rst interior equilibrium and the boundary equilibrium are stable, while the second interior equilibrium is unstable Comparison to E cient Benchmark: The First-Best Outcome With perfect information, competition among the buyers would drive the price to h(v) when the seller has a value of v. The seller would accept an o er of h(v) if h(v) v and reject it otherwise. This would be socially e cient because the good would always be allocated to the person with the highest value for it. This socially e cient equilibrium is sometimes called the First-Best equilibrium, to distinguish it from ine cient equilibrium - the Second-Best - that 111

21 $ h(v) E[h(v) V< b*] 45 v L v 1 * v H b* Figure 3-6: Adverse Selection Case #5 $ h(v) E[h(v) V< b*] 45 v L v 1 * v 2 * v H b* Figure 3-7: Adverse Selection Case #6 112

22 results from the information asymmetry. In general, an REE with incomplete information is socially ine cient, as shown in Figures 3-2 through 3-7. The socially e cient outcome calls for a sale whenever h(v) v, but each REE consists of a cuto v (which is sometimes v L or v H ), with sales occurring whenever v v. In Case 1, h(v) > v for some values, but the good is never sold. Similarly, in Cases 2 and 3, there is an ine cient equilibrium with b = v L. In addition, each equilibrium with a positive probability of sales in Cases 2 and 3 involves sales of goods with values close to v L, yet h(v L ) < v L so those sales are ine cient. The most common cases of e cient transactions are the simplest ones. For example, in Case 4, h(v) > v for each v. The unique stable REE calls for a certain sale at price p = E[h(v)] and that is e cient because the buyer is known to value the good more than the seller at any price. Similarly, if h(v) < v for each v, any REE will have a price p < v L and that equilibrium will be e cient because there is no possibility of a sale Determinants of Adverse Selection Figures 3-2 through 3-7 subsume the calculation of E[h(v)jV p ]. This placement of this conditional expectation relative to v determines the e ect of adverse selection in a Nash equilibrium. In turn, this conditional expectation depends on the magnitude of h(v) and the nature of the distribution function f(v). For any o er p that the seller accepts, the buyer gets a pro t of h(v) p. Thus, the buyer prefers: 1) functions h that give large di erences between h(v) and v; 2) distribution functions that place maximum weight on higher values of v since h(v) is increasing in v. In the Takeover Game example, h(v) > v for each v, but the di erence h(v) v was not large enough to overcome the degree of adverse selection inherent in the uniform distribution f(v). To see the e ect of the interplay between h(v) and f(v), consider a version of the Takeover Game where v L = 0 and v H = 1, h(v) = av, and f(v) = 1 c+2cv, where a and c are constants with a 1 and 1 c 1. Here, we have two parameters. The constant a determines the degree of surplus available from trade. Higher values of a increase the value to the buyer, relative to the seller, thereby reducing adverse selection. The value of c adjusts the slope of the distribution of v. The 113

23 F(v) F(v) 2 2 c = 1 1 v c = 1 1 v Figure 3-8: Distribution of Payo s distribution is always linear in c, but it can have a positive or negative slope. For c < 0, higher values of v are progressively less likely than lower values of v. For c > 0, higher values of v are more likely than lower values. As c increases, the conditional expectation E[h(v)jV p ] increases for each p, once again reducing adverse selection. The distribution is still not completely exible: The cases with lowest and highest values are given by c = 1 and c = 1, depicted in Figure 3-8. In the Takeover Game discussed at the outset of this chapter, h(v) = 1:5v, meaning a = 1:5, and f(v) = 1, meaning c = 0. To see the general relationship between the buyer s valuation function and the distribution 114

24 function, consider the expected pro t to a buyer at price p: b (p) = (E[h(v)jV p ] p ) P (v p ) R p! 0 h(v) f(v)dv = R b 0 f(v)dv p P (v p ) R p! 0 av[1 c + 2cv]dv = R p 0 [1 c + 2cv]dv p P (v p ) 0" 1 2 a(1 # 1 c)v2 + 2 p 3 acv3 (1 c)v + cv 2 p A P (v b ) = a(1! c)p ac(p ) 2 (1 c) + cp p P (v p ) = 1 3a(1 c)p + 4ac(p ) 2 6p (1 c) 6c(p ) 2 6 (1 c) + cp P (v p ) The denominator is always positive for p v H = 1, given that 1 c 1. Furthermore, P (v b ) must be between 0 and 1 since it is a probability. Overall, then, (p) 0 if: 3a(1 c)p + 4ac(p ) 2 6p (1 c) 6c(p ) 2 0 p (3a 6)(1 c) + (4ac 6c)(p ) 2 0 Full E ciency: When a > 1, the e cient outcome is for the buyer to purchase the good in all cases - i.e. p = 1. This is pro table if: (3a 6)(1 c) + (4ac 6c) 0 3a 6 3ac + 6c + 4ac 6c 0 3a 6 + ac 0 115

25 So, when the following condition holds a c or c 6 3a a competition will drive the price to E[h(v)] and the good will be sold with probability 1 in a stable REE. That is, adverse selection disappears in the equilibrium if a and c are jointly large enough to reduce the problem. Note that a larger value of c (which reduces adverse selection) reduces the cuto needed for the value of a to achieve full e ciency and vice versa. In the case of a uniform distribution, c = 0, and then a 2 is the condition for e ciency. Similarly, if a = 1:5, then c 1 is the condition for full e ciency. So the combination of a = 1:5 and c = 0 corresponding to the Takeover Game described at the outset of the chapter - does not yield the e cient outcome Commentary on Subgame Perfect Equilibrium The discussion of Cases 1 through 6 of the general model identi ed Nash equilibrium outcomes without solving for strategies o the equilibrium path. In a subgame perfect equilibrium, the seller s follows her dominant strategy both on and o the equilibrium path, accepting any o er b v. Working backwards, a zero-pro t price cannot yield a subgame perfect equilibrium if a higher price would yields pro ts to the buyers. This rules out all but the highest zero pro t price, which is the unique subgame perfect equilibrium (SPE). Note that a subgame perfect equilibrium must exist in this case. Once the seller s strategy is xed to accept o ers b v, it is possible to calculate net pro ts (b ) to buyers for each price (the highest o er) b. If (v H ) > 0, then E[h(v)] > v H and the subgame perfect equilibrium calls for a boundary solution with b = E[h(v)]. If (v H ) < 0, then the subgame perfect equilibrium simply calls for the highest price b < v H that gives zero expected pro ts to the buyers. If there is no such price, then b = v L, and no trades occur. If there are multiple Nash equilibria with ascending prices b 1, b 2, b 3,..., b n, then each of the equilibria with prices below b n requires noncredible beliefs by the buyers. For example, b 1 is a Nash equilibrium price based on a threat by the seller(s) not to accept any o er if v > b 1. But subgame perfection rules out buyers believing this empty threat, so that there is a pro table 116

26 deviation (generally to just below b n) for buyers Pareto E ciency If there are multiple Nash equilibrium prices, the highest equilibrium price Pareto dominates all lower prices. The buyers receive zero expected pro ts at any equilibrium price, so they do not have a preference among these outcomes. The sellers on the other hand, are better o when o ered higher prices, so they (at least the ones who accept the o er) strictly prefer the highest equilibrium price. That is, subgame perfection selects the most preferred equilibrium based on the Pareto criterion. 3.3 Labor Market Adverse Selection An alternate formulation reverses the relationship between seller s and buyer s valuation. In this model, the value to the buyer is, while the value to the seller is r(). Of course, the results in this formulation are identical to the above results, though recast from h(v) and v to and r(). MWG presents adverse selection in the context of workers and rms who do not know the qualities of each worker. In e ect, the rms are the buyers and the workers are the sellers, where each worker is hoping to sell his own labor to the rm. Formally, each worker has an ability (or type), where worker i knows i. The rms cannot observe the individual i s, but they know what the overall distribution of s in the workforce looks like. Suppose that ranges from L to H according to continuous distribution f() and that productivity of worker i is exactly i. Firms maximize total pro ts, which can be written for each rm j as (j) = (# of workers at rm j) [E j () E j (w)] where E j () is the average productivity of the workers at rm j and E j (w) is the average wage of the workers at rm j. Firms compete in Bertrand fashion for workers. The rm that o ers 24 In an extreme case, it is possible that b n gives a local maximum in expected pro ts to the buyer so that expected pro ts are negative for all prices greater than b n 1, except for b n. In this unusual instance, both b n and b n 1 can be sustained as subgame perfect equilibrium prices. 117

EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Cheap Talk

EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Cheap Talk EconS 53 - Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Cheap Talk. Cheap talk with Stockbrokers (From Tadelis, Ch. 8, Exercise 8.) A stockbroker can give his client one of three recommendations regarding a certain

More information

Quality differentiation and entry choice between online and offline markets

Quality differentiation and entry choice between online and offline markets Quality differentiation and entry choice between online and offline markets Yijuan Chen Australian National University Xiangting u Renmin University of China Sanxi Li Renmin University of China ANU Working

More information

Optimal insurance contracts with adverse selection and comonotonic background risk

Optimal insurance contracts with adverse selection and comonotonic background risk Optimal insurance contracts with adverse selection and comonotonic background risk Alary D. Bien F. TSE (LERNA) University Paris Dauphine Abstract In this note, we consider an adverse selection problem

More information

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Nathaniel Hendren January, 2014 Abstract Both Akerlof (1970) and Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976) show that

More information

Discussion of Self-ful lling Fire Sales: Fragility of Collateralised, Short-Term, Debt Markets, by J. C.-F. Kuong

Discussion of Self-ful lling Fire Sales: Fragility of Collateralised, Short-Term, Debt Markets, by J. C.-F. Kuong Discussion of Self-ful lling Fire Sales: Fragility of Collateralised, Short-Term, Debt Markets, by J. C.-F. Kuong 10 July 2015 Coordination games Schelling (1960). Bryant (1980), Diamond and Dybvig (1983)

More information

Midterm March 2015. (a) Consumer i s budget constraint is. c i 0 12 + b i c i H 12 (1 + r)b i c i L 12 (1 + r)b i ;

Midterm March 2015. (a) Consumer i s budget constraint is. c i 0 12 + b i c i H 12 (1 + r)b i c i L 12 (1 + r)b i ; Masters in Economics-UC3M Microeconomics II Midterm March 015 Exercise 1. In an economy that extends over two periods, today and tomorrow, there are two consumers, A and B; and a single perishable good,

More information

The Prison S Dilemma and Its Connections

The Prison S Dilemma and Its Connections Games Played in a Contracting Environment V. Bhaskar Department of Economics University College London Gower Street London WC1 6BT February 2008 Abstract We analyze normal form games where a player has

More information

2. Information Economics

2. Information Economics 2. Information Economics In General Equilibrium Theory all agents had full information regarding any variable of interest (prices, commodities, state of nature, cost function, preferences, etc.) In many

More information

Costs and Bene ts of Dynamic Trading in a Lemons Market

Costs and Bene ts of Dynamic Trading in a Lemons Market Costs and Bene ts of Dynamic Trading in a Lemons Market William Fuchs Andrzej Skrzypacz December 1, 01 Abstract We study a dynamic market with asymmetric information that creates the lemons problem. We

More information

Decentralised Bilateral Trading in a Market with Incomplete Information

Decentralised Bilateral Trading in a Market with Incomplete Information Decentralised Bilateral Trading in a Market with Incomplete Information Kalyan Chatterjee 1 Kaustav Das 23 May 28, 2013 1 Department of Economics, The Pennsylvania State University, University Park, Pa.

More information

Chapter 7. Sealed-bid Auctions

Chapter 7. Sealed-bid Auctions Chapter 7 Sealed-bid Auctions An auction is a procedure used for selling and buying items by offering them up for bid. Auctions are often used to sell objects that have a variable price (for example oil)

More information

The Design and Efficiency of Loyalty Rewards Ramon Caminal This version: October 2010 October 2009

The Design and Efficiency of Loyalty Rewards Ramon Caminal This version: October 2010 October 2009 The Design and Efficiency of Loyalty Rewards Ramon Caminal This version: October 010 October 009 Barcelona GSE Working Paper Series Working Paper nº 408 The design and e ciency of loyalty rewards Ramon

More information

Online Appendix Feedback Effects, Asymmetric Trading, and the Limits to Arbitrage

Online Appendix Feedback Effects, Asymmetric Trading, and the Limits to Arbitrage Online Appendix Feedback Effects, Asymmetric Trading, and the Limits to Arbitrage Alex Edmans LBS, NBER, CEPR, and ECGI Itay Goldstein Wharton Wei Jiang Columbia May 8, 05 A Proofs of Propositions and

More information

Online shopping and platform design with ex ante registration requirements

Online shopping and platform design with ex ante registration requirements Online shopping and platform design with ex ante registration requirements Florian Morath Johannes Münster y December 5, 2014 Abstract We study platform design in online markets in which buying involves

More information

Costly Voting when both Information and Preferences Di er: Is Turnout Too High or Too Low?

Costly Voting when both Information and Preferences Di er: Is Turnout Too High or Too Low? Costly Voting when both Information and Preferences Di er: Is Turnout Too High or Too Low? Sayantan Ghosal and Ben Lockwood University of Warwick October, 2008 Abstract We study a model of costly voting

More information

Lecture Notes: Basic Concepts in Option Pricing - The Black and Scholes Model

Lecture Notes: Basic Concepts in Option Pricing - The Black and Scholes Model Brunel University Msc., EC5504, Financial Engineering Prof Menelaos Karanasos Lecture Notes: Basic Concepts in Option Pricing - The Black and Scholes Model Recall that the price of an option is equal to

More information

Information Gatekeepers on the Internet and the Competitiveness of. Homogeneous Product Markets. By Michael R. Baye and John Morgan 1.

Information Gatekeepers on the Internet and the Competitiveness of. Homogeneous Product Markets. By Michael R. Baye and John Morgan 1. Information Gatekeepers on the Internet and the Competitiveness of Homogeneous Product Markets By Michael R. Baye and John Morgan 1 Abstract We examine the equilibrium interaction between a market for

More information

Participating insurance contracts and the Rothschild-Stiglitz equilibrium puzzle

Participating insurance contracts and the Rothschild-Stiglitz equilibrium puzzle Participating insurance contracts and the Rothschild-Stiglitz equilibrium puzzle Pierre Picard y 22 August 2010 Abstract We show that an equilibrium always exists in the Rothschild-Stiglitz insurance market

More information

Customer Value-based Management: Competitive Implications

Customer Value-based Management: Competitive Implications Customer Value-based Management: Competitive Implications Upender Subramanian, Jagmohan S. Raju, Z. John Zhang The Wharton School 700 Jon M. Huntsman Hall 3730 Walnut Street Philadelphia, PA 19104-6340

More information

UCLA. Department of Economics Ph. D. Preliminary Exam Micro-Economic Theory

UCLA. Department of Economics Ph. D. Preliminary Exam Micro-Economic Theory UCLA Department of Economics Ph. D. Preliminary Exam Micro-Economic Theory (SPRING 2011) Instructions: You have 4 hours for the exam Answer any 5 out of the 6 questions. All questions are weighted equally.

More information

Pricing Cloud Computing: Inelasticity and Demand Discovery

Pricing Cloud Computing: Inelasticity and Demand Discovery Pricing Cloud Computing: Inelasticity and Demand Discovery June 7, 203 Abstract The recent growth of the cloud computing market has convinced many businesses and policy makers that cloud-based technologies

More information

Participating insurance contracts and the Rothschild-Stiglitz equilibrium puzzle

Participating insurance contracts and the Rothschild-Stiglitz equilibrium puzzle Participating insurance contracts and the Rothschild-Stiglitz equilibrium puzzle Pierre Picard 24 November 2009 Abstract We show that an equilibrium always exists in the Rothschild-Stiglitz insurance market

More information

Economics of Insurance

Economics of Insurance Economics of Insurance In this last lecture, we cover most topics of Economics of Information within a single application. Through this, you will see how the differential informational assumptions allow

More information

1 Directional Trading Strategies

1 Directional Trading Strategies Brunel University Msc., EC5504, Financial Engineering Prof Menelaos Karanasos Lecture Notes: Directional Trading Strategies 1 Directional Trading Strategies With options you can pro t from correctly predicting

More information

Corporate Income Taxation

Corporate Income Taxation Corporate Income Taxation We have stressed that tax incidence must be traced to people, since corporations cannot bear the burden of a tax. Why then tax corporations at all? There are several possible

More information

The E ect of Trading Commissions on Analysts Forecast Bias

The E ect of Trading Commissions on Analysts Forecast Bias The E ect of Trading Commissions on Analysts Forecast Bias Anne Beyer and Ilan Guttman Stanford University September 2007 Abstract The paper models the interaction between a sell-side analyst and a risk-averse

More information

Optimal Auctions. Jonathan Levin 1. Winter 2009. Economics 285 Market Design. 1 These slides are based on Paul Milgrom s.

Optimal Auctions. Jonathan Levin 1. Winter 2009. Economics 285 Market Design. 1 These slides are based on Paul Milgrom s. Optimal Auctions Jonathan Levin 1 Economics 285 Market Design Winter 29 1 These slides are based on Paul Milgrom s. onathan Levin Optimal Auctions Winter 29 1 / 25 Optimal Auctions What auction rules lead

More information

Economics 101A (Lecture 26) Stefano DellaVigna

Economics 101A (Lecture 26) Stefano DellaVigna Economics 101A (Lecture 26) Stefano DellaVigna April 30, 2015 Outline 1. The Takeover Game 2. Hidden Type (Adverse Selection) 3. Empirical Economics: Intro 4. Empirical Economics: Home Insurance 5. Empirical

More information

A Welfare Criterion for Models with Distorted Beliefs

A Welfare Criterion for Models with Distorted Beliefs A Welfare Criterion for Models with Distorted Beliefs Markus Brunnermeier, Alp Simsek, Wei Xiong August 2012 Markus Brunnermeier, Alp Simsek, Wei Xiong () Welfare Criterion for Distorted Beliefs August

More information

Lesson 5. Risky assets

Lesson 5. Risky assets Lesson 5. Risky assets Prof. Beatriz de Blas May 2006 5. Risky assets 2 Introduction How stock markets serve to allocate risk. Plan of the lesson: 8 >< >: 1. Risk and risk aversion 2. Portfolio risk 3.

More information

Tiered and Value-based Health Care Networks

Tiered and Value-based Health Care Networks Tiered and Value-based Health Care Networks Ching-to Albert Ma Henry Y. Mak Department of Economics Department of Economics Boston Univeristy Indiana University Purdue University Indianapolis 270 Bay State

More information

Buying shares and/or votes for corporate control

Buying shares and/or votes for corporate control Buying shares and/or votes for corporate control Eddie Dekel and Asher Wolinsky 1 July 2010 1 Dekel is at the Department of Economics, Tel Aviv University and Northwestern University, Evanston, IL 60208,

More information

Three Essays on Monopolist Second-degree Discrimination Strategies in the Presence of Positive Network E ects by Gergely Csorba

Three Essays on Monopolist Second-degree Discrimination Strategies in the Presence of Positive Network E ects by Gergely Csorba Three Essays on Monopolist Second-degree Discrimination Strategies in the Presence of Positive Network E ects by Gergely Csorba Submitted to the Economics Department on October 24, 2005, in partial ful

More information

The Timing of Signaling: To Study in High School or in College?

The Timing of Signaling: To Study in High School or in College? The Timing of Signaling: To Study in High School or in College? Sanghoon Lee 1 University of British Columbia, Canada Abstract American students study harder in college than in high school while East Asian

More information

Climate-Change Treaties: A Game-Theoretic Approach Roy Radner Stern School, New York University

Climate-Change Treaties: A Game-Theoretic Approach Roy Radner Stern School, New York University Climate-Change Treaties: A Game-Theoretic Approach Roy Radner Stern School, New York University A Project Progress Report in collaboration with Prajit K. Dutta, Columbia University Sangwon Park, Korea

More information

Paid Placement: Advertising and Search on the Internet

Paid Placement: Advertising and Search on the Internet Paid Placement: Advertising and Search on the Internet Yongmin Chen y Chuan He z August 2006 Abstract Paid placement, where advertisers bid payments to a search engine to have their products appear next

More information

Market Power and Efficiency in Card Payment Systems: A Comment on Rochet and Tirole

Market Power and Efficiency in Card Payment Systems: A Comment on Rochet and Tirole Market Power and Efficiency in Card Payment Systems: A Comment on Rochet and Tirole Luís M. B. Cabral New York University and CEPR November 2005 1 Introduction Beginning with their seminal 2002 paper,

More information

How To Model Vote Trading

How To Model Vote Trading Buying shares and/or votes for corporate control Eddie Dekel and Asher Wolinsky 1 April 2011 1 Dekel (corresponding author) is at the Department of Economics, Tel Aviv University and Northwestern University,

More information

1 Volatility Trading Strategies

1 Volatility Trading Strategies Brunel University Msc., EC5504, Financial Engineering Prof Menelaos Karanasos Lecture Notes: Volatility Trading Strategies 1 Volatility Trading Strategies As previously explained, volatility is essentially

More information

CAPM, Arbitrage, and Linear Factor Models

CAPM, Arbitrage, and Linear Factor Models CAPM, Arbitrage, and Linear Factor Models CAPM, Arbitrage, Linear Factor Models 1/ 41 Introduction We now assume all investors actually choose mean-variance e cient portfolios. By equating these investors

More information

FINAL EXAM, Econ 171, March, 2015, with answers

FINAL EXAM, Econ 171, March, 2015, with answers FINAL EXAM, Econ 171, March, 2015, with answers There are 9 questions. Answer any 8 of them. Good luck! Problem 1. (True or False) If a player has a dominant strategy in a simultaneous-move game, then

More information

Why is Insurance Good? An Example Jon Bakija, Williams College (Revised October 2013)

Why is Insurance Good? An Example Jon Bakija, Williams College (Revised October 2013) Why is Insurance Good? An Example Jon Bakija, Williams College (Revised October 2013) Introduction The United States government is, to a rough approximation, an insurance company with an army. 1 That is

More information

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2015

ECON 459 Game Theory. Lecture Notes Auctions. Luca Anderlini Spring 2015 ECON 459 Game Theory Lecture Notes Auctions Luca Anderlini Spring 2015 These notes have been used before. If you can still spot any errors or have any suggestions for improvement, please let me know. 1

More information

Non-Exclusive Competition in the Market for Lemons

Non-Exclusive Competition in the Market for Lemons Non-Exclusive Competition in the Market for Lemons Andrea Attar Thomas Mariotti François Salanié October 2007 Abstract In order to check the impact of the exclusivity regime on equilibrium allocations,

More information

Week 7 - Game Theory and Industrial Organisation

Week 7 - Game Theory and Industrial Organisation Week 7 - Game Theory and Industrial Organisation The Cournot and Bertrand models are the two basic templates for models of oligopoly; industry structures with a small number of firms. There are a number

More information

Participating insurance contracts and the Rothschild-Stiglitz equilibrium puzzle

Participating insurance contracts and the Rothschild-Stiglitz equilibrium puzzle Participating insurance contracts and the Rothschild-Stiglitz equilibrium puzzle Pierre Picard Ecole Polytechnique July 2009 Pierre Picard (Ecole Polytechnique) July 2009 1 / 25 Overview 1 Motivation and

More information

Price Dispersion. Ed Hopkins Economics University of Edinburgh Edinburgh EH8 9JY, UK. November, 2006. Abstract

Price Dispersion. Ed Hopkins Economics University of Edinburgh Edinburgh EH8 9JY, UK. November, 2006. Abstract Price Dispersion Ed Hopkins Economics University of Edinburgh Edinburgh EH8 9JY, UK November, 2006 Abstract A brief survey of the economics of price dispersion, written for the New Palgrave Dictionary

More information

Market Power, Forward Trading and Supply Function. Competition

Market Power, Forward Trading and Supply Function. Competition Market Power, Forward Trading and Supply Function Competition Matías Herrera Dappe University of Maryland May, 2008 Abstract When rms can produce any level of output, strategic forward trading can enhance

More information

Spot Market Power and Futures Market Trading

Spot Market Power and Futures Market Trading Spot Market Power and Futures Market Trading Alexander Muermann and Stephen H. Shore The Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania March 2005 Abstract When a spot market monopolist participates in the

More information

February 2013. Abstract

February 2013. Abstract Marking to Market and Ine cient Investments Clemens A. Otto and Paolo F. Volpin February 03 Abstract We examine how mark-to-market accounting a ects investment decisions in an agency model with reputation

More information

Modeling Insurance Markets

Modeling Insurance Markets Modeling Insurance Markets Nathaniel Hendren Harvard April, 2015 Nathaniel Hendren (Harvard) Insurance April, 2015 1 / 29 Modeling Competition Insurance Markets is Tough There is no well-agreed upon model

More information

Hedging Using Forward Contracts

Hedging Using Forward Contracts 10 CHAPTER 1 Business Snapshot1.1 Hedge Funds Hedge funds have become major users of derivatives for hedging, speculation, and arbitrage. A hedge fund is similar to a mutual fund in that it invests funds

More information

Short-term Financial Planning and Management.

Short-term Financial Planning and Management. Short-term Financial Planning and Management. This topic discusses the fundamentals of short-term nancial management; the analysis of decisions involving cash ows which occur within a year or less. These

More information

Interlinkages between Payment and Securities. Settlement Systems

Interlinkages between Payment and Securities. Settlement Systems Interlinkages between Payment and Securities Settlement Systems David C. Mills, Jr. y Federal Reserve Board Samia Y. Husain Washington University in Saint Louis September 4, 2009 Abstract Payments systems

More information

Economics II: Micro Fall 2009 Exercise session 5. Market with a sole supplier is Monopolistic.

Economics II: Micro Fall 2009 Exercise session 5. Market with a sole supplier is Monopolistic. Economics II: Micro Fall 009 Exercise session 5 VŠE 1 Review Optimal production: Independent of the level of market concentration, optimal level of production is where MR = MC. Monopoly: Market with a

More information

Technology Licensing by Advertising Supported Media Platforms: An Application to Internet Search Engines

Technology Licensing by Advertising Supported Media Platforms: An Application to Internet Search Engines No 23 Technology Licensing by Advertising Supported Media Platforms: An Application to Internet Search Engines Geza Sapi, Irina Suleymanova June 2011 IMPRINT DICE DISCUSSION PAPER Published by Heinrich

More information

Risk Aversion. Expected value as a criterion for making decisions makes sense provided that C H A P T E R 2. 2.1 Risk Attitude

Risk Aversion. Expected value as a criterion for making decisions makes sense provided that C H A P T E R 2. 2.1 Risk Attitude C H A P T E R 2 Risk Aversion Expected value as a criterion for making decisions makes sense provided that the stakes at risk in the decision are small enough to \play the long run averages." The range

More information

Bayesian Nash Equilibrium

Bayesian Nash Equilibrium . Bayesian Nash Equilibrium . In the final two weeks: Goals Understand what a game of incomplete information (Bayesian game) is Understand how to model static Bayesian games Be able to apply Bayes Nash

More information

Herding, Contrarianism and Delay in Financial Market Trading

Herding, Contrarianism and Delay in Financial Market Trading Herding, Contrarianism and Delay in Financial Market Trading A Lab Experiment Andreas Park & Daniel Sgroi University of Toronto & University of Warwick Two Restaurants E cient Prices Classic Herding Example:

More information

R&D Collaboration Networks in Mixed Oligopoly

R&D Collaboration Networks in Mixed Oligopoly R&D Collaboration Networks in Mixed Oligopoly Vasileios Zikos Department of Economics, Loughborough University Loughborough LE11 3TU, U.K. V.Zikos@lboro.ac.uk Abstract We develop a model of endogenous

More information

Covert Networks and the Antitrust Policy

Covert Networks and the Antitrust Policy Covert Networks and the Antitrust Policy Flavia Roldán Universidad ORT Uruguay and Public-Private Sector Research Center, IESE Business School June, 2011 Abstract This article studies the e ectiveness

More information

CONTRACTUAL SIGNALLING, RELATIONSHIP-SPECIFIC INVESTMENT AND EXCLUSIVE AGREEMENTS

CONTRACTUAL SIGNALLING, RELATIONSHIP-SPECIFIC INVESTMENT AND EXCLUSIVE AGREEMENTS CONTRACTUAL SIGNALLING, RELATIONSHIP-SPECIFIC INVESTMENT AND EXCLUSIVE AGREEMENTS LUÍS VASCONCELOS y Abstract. I analyze a simple model of hold-up with asymmetric information at the contracting stage.

More information

Voluntary Voting: Costs and Bene ts

Voluntary Voting: Costs and Bene ts Voluntary Voting: Costs and Bene ts Vijay Krishna y and John Morgan z November 7, 2008 Abstract We study strategic voting in a Condorcet type model in which voters have identical preferences but di erential

More information

Insurance and Public Pensions : (b) Adverse Selection

Insurance and Public Pensions : (b) Adverse Selection Insurance and Public Pensions : (b) Adverse Selection Adverse selection is said to occur if potential buyers of insurance know their own probabilities of loss better than do insurance companies. So suppose

More information

National Responses to Transnational Terrorism: Intelligence and Counterterrorism Provision

National Responses to Transnational Terrorism: Intelligence and Counterterrorism Provision National Responses to Transnational Terrorism: Intelligence and Counterterrorism Provision Thomas Jensen October 10, 2013 Abstract Intelligence about transnational terrorism is generally gathered by national

More information

Dynamic Pricing of Enterprise Software with Value Uncertainty: Motivation for Selling Software as a Service

Dynamic Pricing of Enterprise Software with Value Uncertainty: Motivation for Selling Software as a Service Dynamic Pricing of Enterprise Software with Value Uncertainty: Motivation for Selling Software as a Service November 26, 2011 Abstract This paper studies a software vendor s decision to o er perpetual

More information

Single-bank proprietary platforms

Single-bank proprietary platforms Single-bank proprietary platforms Jonathan Cave y and Luca Gelsomini zx Abstract This paper models strategic trading in a market with a single informed dealer willing to trade a risky asset at public bid

More information

Sharp and Diffuse Incentives in Contracting

Sharp and Diffuse Incentives in Contracting Risk & Sustainable Management Group Risk and Uncertainty Working Paper: R07#6 Research supported by an Australian Research Council Federation Fellowship http://www.arc.gov.au/grant_programs/discovery_federation.htm

More information

Adverse selection and moral hazard in health insurance.

Adverse selection and moral hazard in health insurance. Adverse selection and moral hazard in health insurance. Franck Bien David Alary University Paris Dauphine November 10, 2006 Abstract In this paper, we want to characterize the optimal health insurance

More information

CPC/CPA Hybrid Bidding in a Second Price Auction

CPC/CPA Hybrid Bidding in a Second Price Auction CPC/CPA Hybrid Bidding in a Second Price Auction Benjamin Edelman Hoan Soo Lee Working Paper 09-074 Copyright 2008 by Benjamin Edelman and Hoan Soo Lee Working papers are in draft form. This working paper

More information

Customer Service Quality and Incomplete Information in Mobile Telecommunications: A Game Theoretical Approach to Consumer Protection.

Customer Service Quality and Incomplete Information in Mobile Telecommunications: A Game Theoretical Approach to Consumer Protection. Customer Service Quality and Incomplete Information in Mobile Telecommunications: A Game Theoretical Approach to Consumer Protection.* Rafael López Zorzano, Universidad Complutense, Spain. Teodosio Pérez-Amaral,

More information

The Role of Joint Liability Contracts and Guarantor Contracts in Micro nance. May 22nd, 2010

The Role of Joint Liability Contracts and Guarantor Contracts in Micro nance. May 22nd, 2010 The Role of Joint Liability ontracts and Guarantor ontracts in Micro nance Tomek Katzur Robert Lensink May 22nd, 2 Abstract. We extend the existing literature on group lending contracts by analyzing the

More information

Domestic and Cross-Border Mergers in Unionized Oligopoly

Domestic and Cross-Border Mergers in Unionized Oligopoly Domestic and Cross-Border Mergers in Unionized Oligopoly Beatrice Pagel y Christian Wey z June 202 Abstract We re-examine the model of Lommerud et al. (2006) which shows that cross-border mergers should

More information

Financial Market Microstructure Theory

Financial Market Microstructure Theory The Microstructure of Financial Markets, de Jong and Rindi (2009) Financial Market Microstructure Theory Based on de Jong and Rindi, Chapters 2 5 Frank de Jong Tilburg University 1 Determinants of the

More information

Cournot s model of oligopoly

Cournot s model of oligopoly Cournot s model of oligopoly Single good produced by n firms Cost to firm i of producing q i units: C i (q i ), where C i is nonnegative and increasing If firms total output is Q then market price is P(Q),

More information

A Simpli ed Axiomatic Approach to Ambiguity Aversion

A Simpli ed Axiomatic Approach to Ambiguity Aversion A Simpli ed Axiomatic Approach to Ambiguity Aversion William S. Neilson Department of Economics University of Tennessee Knoxville, TN 37996-0550 wneilson@utk.edu March 2009 Abstract This paper takes the

More information

Costly Information Acquisition with Credit Scores

Costly Information Acquisition with Credit Scores Costly Information Acquisition with Credit Scores Sergio Vicente y Universidad Carlos III de Madrid November 25, 215 Abstract This paper analyzes the e ect of competition between large and small lenders

More information

Imperfect information Up to now, consider only firms and consumers who are perfectly informed about market conditions: 1. prices, range of products

Imperfect information Up to now, consider only firms and consumers who are perfectly informed about market conditions: 1. prices, range of products Imperfect information Up to now, consider only firms and consumers who are perfectly informed about market conditions: 1. prices, range of products available 2. characteristics or relative qualities of

More information

A Simple Model of Price Dispersion *

A Simple Model of Price Dispersion * Federal Reserve Bank of Dallas Globalization and Monetary Policy Institute Working Paper No. 112 http://www.dallasfed.org/assets/documents/institute/wpapers/2012/0112.pdf A Simple Model of Price Dispersion

More information

Asymmetric Information (2)

Asymmetric Information (2) Asymmetric nformation (2) John Y. Campbell Ec2723 November 2013 John Y. Campbell (Ec2723) Asymmetric nformation (2) November 2013 1 / 24 Outline Market microstructure The study of trading costs Bid-ask

More information

Health Insurance, Treatment Plan, and. Delegation to Altruistic Physician

Health Insurance, Treatment Plan, and. Delegation to Altruistic Physician Health Insurance, Treatment Plan, and Delegation to Altruistic Physician Ting Liu Ching-to Albert Ma Department of Economics Department of Economics Michigan State Univeristy Boston University 0 Marshall-Adams

More information

Participating insurance contracts and the Rothschild-Stiglitz equilibrium puzzle

Participating insurance contracts and the Rothschild-Stiglitz equilibrium puzzle Participating insurance contracts and the Rothschild-Stiglitz equilibrium puzzle Pierre Picard 23 November 2009 Abstract We show that an equilibrium always exists in the Rothschild-Stiglitz insurance market

More information

On the incentives of an integrated ISP to favor its own content

On the incentives of an integrated ISP to favor its own content On the incentives of an integrated ISP to favor its own content Duarte Brito y UNL and CEFAGE-UE dmb@fct.unl.pt Pedro Pereira z AdC and CEFAGE-UE pedro.br.pereira@gmail.com. João Vareda x European Commission

More information

Pricing Health Bene ts: A Cost-Minimization Approach

Pricing Health Bene ts: A Cost-Minimization Approach Pricing Health Bene ts: A Cost-Minimization Approach Nolan H. Miller March 14, 2005 Abstract We study the role of health bene ts in an employer s compensation strategy, given the overall goal of minimizing

More information

Microeconomic Theory Jamison / Kohlberg / Avery Problem Set 4 Solutions Spring 2012. (a) LEFT CENTER RIGHT TOP 8, 5 0, 0 6, 3 BOTTOM 0, 0 7, 6 6, 3

Microeconomic Theory Jamison / Kohlberg / Avery Problem Set 4 Solutions Spring 2012. (a) LEFT CENTER RIGHT TOP 8, 5 0, 0 6, 3 BOTTOM 0, 0 7, 6 6, 3 Microeconomic Theory Jamison / Kohlberg / Avery Problem Set 4 Solutions Spring 2012 1. Subgame Perfect Equilibrium and Dominance (a) LEFT CENTER RIGHT TOP 8, 5 0, 0 6, 3 BOTTOM 0, 0 7, 6 6, 3 Highlighting

More information

14.773 Problem Set 2 Due Date: March 7, 2013

14.773 Problem Set 2 Due Date: March 7, 2013 14.773 Problem Set 2 Due Date: March 7, 2013 Question 1 Consider a group of countries that di er in their preferences for public goods. The utility function for the representative country i is! NX U i

More information

Competing for Consumers Online: The Advertising Strategies of. Vertically Di erentiated Firms

Competing for Consumers Online: The Advertising Strategies of. Vertically Di erentiated Firms Competing for Consumers Online: The Advertising Strategies of Vertically Di erentiated Firms Taylan Yalcin Harvard Business School, Harvard University tyalcin@hbs.edu Elie Ofek Harvard Business School,

More information

Our development of economic theory has two main parts, consumers and producers. We will start with the consumers.

Our development of economic theory has two main parts, consumers and producers. We will start with the consumers. Lecture 1: Budget Constraints c 2008 Je rey A. Miron Outline 1. Introduction 2. Two Goods are Often Enough 3. Properties of the Budget Set 4. How the Budget Line Changes 5. The Numeraire 6. Taxes, Subsidies,

More information

Exact Nonparametric Tests for Comparing Means - A Personal Summary

Exact Nonparametric Tests for Comparing Means - A Personal Summary Exact Nonparametric Tests for Comparing Means - A Personal Summary Karl H. Schlag European University Institute 1 December 14, 2006 1 Economics Department, European University Institute. Via della Piazzuola

More information

Can a Lump-Sum Transfer Make Everyone Enjoy the Gains. from Free Trade?

Can a Lump-Sum Transfer Make Everyone Enjoy the Gains. from Free Trade? Can a Lump-Sum Transfer Make Everyone Enjoy te Gains from Free Trade? Yasukazu Icino Department of Economics, Konan University June 30, 2010 Abstract I examine lump-sum transfer rules to redistribute te

More information

Problem 1 (Issuance and Repurchase in a Modigliani-Miller World)

Problem 1 (Issuance and Repurchase in a Modigliani-Miller World) Problem 1 (Issuance and Repurchase in a Modigliani-Miller World) A rm has outstanding debt with a market value of $100 million. The rm also has 15 million shares outstanding with a market value of $10

More information

Central Bank Lending and Money Market Discipline

Central Bank Lending and Money Market Discipline Central Bank Lending and Money Market Discipline Marie Hoerova European Central Bank Cyril Monnet FRB Philadelphia November 2010 PRELIMINARY Abstract This paper provides a theory for the joint existence

More information

Why variable inventory costs intensify retail competition, and a case for manufacturer returns

Why variable inventory costs intensify retail competition, and a case for manufacturer returns Why variable inventory costs intensify retail competition, and a case for manufacturer returns Abstract We study how the extent to which the inventory cost is sunk or remains variable a ects retail competition

More information

Moral Hazard. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Moral Hazard. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Moral Hazard Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania 1 Principal-Agent Problem Basic problem in corporate finance: separation of ownership and control: o The owners of the firm are typically

More information

Policy-Speci c Information and Informal Agenda Power

Policy-Speci c Information and Informal Agenda Power Policy-Speci c Information and Informal Agenda Power Alexander V. Hirsch 1 and Kenneth W. Shotts 2 September 27, 2008 1 PhD Candidate in Political Economy, Stanford GSB. 518 Memorial Way, Stanford, CA

More information

Lecture 11: The Design of Trading Platforms (Alos-Ferrer et al. 2010)

Lecture 11: The Design of Trading Platforms (Alos-Ferrer et al. 2010) Lecture 11: The Design of Trading Platforms (Alos-Ferrer et al. 2010) 1. Introduction Lecture 10: selection between exogenously given market institutions now: emergence of new institutions 2 possibilities

More information

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium When players move sequentially and have private information, some of the Bayesian Nash equilibria may involve strategies that are not sequentially rational. The problem is

More information

Heterogeneous Expectations, Adaptive Learning, and Evolutionary Dynamics

Heterogeneous Expectations, Adaptive Learning, and Evolutionary Dynamics Heterogeneous Expectations, Adaptive Learning, and Evolutionary Dynamics Eran A. Guse West Virginia University November 006 (Revised December 008) Abstract This paper presents a linear self-referential

More information

Getting Prices Right: Mobile Phone Di usion, Market E ciency and Inequality 1

Getting Prices Right: Mobile Phone Di usion, Market E ciency and Inequality 1 Getting Prices Right: Mobile Phone Di usion, Market E ciency and Inequality 1 Francis ANDRIANARISON 2 CSAE Conference 2010 Economic Development in Africa. 21st - 23rd March 2010, Oxford. Abstract: In this

More information

Dynamics and Stability of Political Systems

Dynamics and Stability of Political Systems Dynamics and Stability of Political Systems Daron Acemoglu MIT February 11, 2009 Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Marshall Lectures 2 February 11, 2009 1 / 52 Introduction Motivation Towards a general framework? One

More information