Comparative Causation: A Re-examination

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Comparative Causation: A Re-examination"

Transcription

1 CDE August 2005 Comparative Causation: A Re-examination Ram Singh ram@econdse.org Delhi School of Economics University of Delhi Working Paper No. 139 Centre for Development Economics Department of Economics, Delhi School of Economics

2 Working Paper No. 139 Comparative Causation: A Re-examination Ram Singh Abstract Negligence-based liability has been justified on the grounds of its efficiency properties. However, this approach towards liability assignment has been criticized in several recent writings. In a series of articles, causation-based apportionment of liability has been recommended, as an alternative basis for liability assignment. In an interesting paper, Parisi and Fon (2004) have studied various properties of the causation-based liability. In this paper, I review some of their propositions. The main aim of the paper, however, is to investigate the implications of the alternative specification of liability. The paper shows that a combination of negligence-based and causation-based liability makes the diligence strategies dominant choice for the agents. Keywords: liability rules, negligence-based liability, causation-based liability, comparative causation, economic efficiency JEL Classification: K 13 Acknowledgements I am thankful to Abhijit Banerji, TCA Anant, Sugato Dasgupta, Dhammika Dharmapala, Keith Hylton, Satish Jain, Francisco Parisi and Jaivir Singh for helpful comments and valuable suggestions. Remaining errors, if any, are mine.

3 1. Introduction The literature on liability rules is replete with economic analyses of fault or negligencebased regimes. 1 Negligence-based liability has been rationalized and justified on the grounds of its efficiency properties. However, in a series of articles, this approach towards liability has been severely criticized. Several noted scholars have recommended causationbased apportionment of liability, as an alternative basis for liability assignment. 2 In an interesting contribution, Parisi and Fon (2004) have studied various properties of the causation-based liability assignment. In this paper, I review some of their propositions. The main aim of the paper, however, is to investigate the implications of causation based apportionment of liability. Under liability rules that use negligence-based approach towards liability assignment, a party usually faces either full liability or no liability at all. For example, under the rule of negligence, an injurer has no liability if he is not negligent. But, his liability jumps from none to full, the moment his care level falls just below the due level of care, even when the victim takes no care at all. Similarly, under the rule of strict liability with the defense of contributory negligence, the victim s liability jumps from none to full, depending on whether his care level is just above the due level or falls just short of that level, irrespective of the care level of the injurer. While criticizing negligence-based liability, it has been argued that this approach towards liability assignment neglects the causal contributions of the parties involved. Therefore, it does not form a convincing basis for liability assignment, particularly between a non-negligent injurer and a vigilant victim. In addition, the argument goes, it is either inapplicable or unsatisfactory in the cases where multiple causation is involved or where fault is not easy to establish (Strassfeld, 1992; Calabresi and Cooper, 1996; Parisi and 1 For example, see Polinsky (1989), Landes and Posner (1987), Shavell (1987), Arlen, J (1990), Miceli (1997), Cooter and Ulen (1998), Jain and Singh (2002), etc. For a comprehensive account of the positive theory of torts doctrines see Hylton (2000), and Geistfeld (2001). 2 See, Calabresi and Cooper (1996). 1

4 Fon, 2004). 3 In contrast, under causal apportionment of liability, parties bear accident loss in shares that are proportional to their contribution to the loss. Therefore, causal apportionment of liability is said to be consistent with the principle of equity, which requires loss spreading between parties (Honoré, 1997). 4 Moreover, as various studies have revealed, this approach is being used by some courts in many countries, including France, Germany, Japan and the United States (see, e.g., Yoshihsa (1999), Grimley (2000), Yu (2000), and Parisi and Fon (2004)). It is in the context of the above-mentioned debates that Parisi and Fon (2004) have studied the desirability or otherwise of the causation-based liability. For several reasons, the paper by Parisi and Fon is an important contribution in tort literature. First, it systematically investigates the effects of causation-based apportionment of liability on care as well as activity levels of the parties involved. Second, it highlights the inappropriateness of negligence-based regimes. Fault-based or negligence-based legal systems do not provide a reasonable criterion for loss sharing, particularly when neither the injurer nor the victim was negligent at the time of accident. Finally, in the context of a formal analysis, it seeks to provide an explanation for the scope of causation-based division of liability. The last exercise is undertaken both for historical as well as contemporary legal regimes. In order to investigate the efficiency implications of the causation-based liability, Parisi and Fon have introduced and analysed two liability rules. The first liability rule has been defined as the rule of Pure Comparative Causation. Under this rule, parties bear accident loss in shares that are proportional to their causal contribution to the loss, regardless of whether at the time accident parties were at fault or not. In their analysis, the authors have shown that since each party bears only a fraction of the loss, there is an incentive to choose less than socially optimal care and more than socially optimal activity levels. That 3 For criticisms of economic modelling of liability rules on various grounds see Grady (1989), Kahan (1989), Mark (1994), Burrow (1999), and Wright (2002) 4 Honoré, Tony (1997) has argued that the morality of tort law requires that liability of a party should be proportional to the parties causal contribution. Also see, Calabresi (1965, and 1970). 2

5 is, the rule of Pure Comparative Causation induces neither efficient care levels nor efficient activity levels. Next, they discuss the efficiency of what they call the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence. This rule mixes essential features of traditional negligencecriterion based rules, and of the rule of Pure Comparative Causation. Under this rule, when a party is found solely negligent, the entire loss is borne by that party. Accident loss is shared between the parties in cases wherein both the parties are found negligent, or where both are found non-negligent. In such cases, the loss-sharing takes place as under the rule of Pure Comparative Causation. 5 Motivation behind introducing the essential feature of negligence-based liability under the rule of comparative causation comes from the mainstream understanding of the need for fault-based liability. Dominant understanding is that a point of discontinuity in the liability curves faced by the parties must be created to entice both parties to choose optimal care and activity levels. 6 Assuming that the due care levels for the parties are set at the levels that are socially optimal, if this rule could induce both the parties to take the due care and efficient activity levels, it will have the unique virtue of being efficient as well as equitable. However, Parisi and Fon (2004) have stated the following propositions about incentive effects under the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence: (i) In equilibrium, parties are never induced to take more than the due care. (ii) Multiple equilibria in which one or both the parties take less than the due care are possible, i.e., in equilibrium, one or both the parties can be negligent. (iii) In some contexts, choice of due care by both the parties is also a possibility. (iv) Though there is an incentive to mitigate activity levels, each party s activity level will be greater than the corresponding socially optimal level. 5 Proportional loss sharing also takes place under the rule of comparative negligence, but only when both parties are negligent. For an analysis of this rule see Schwartz, G. (1978), Landes and Posner (1980), Cooter and Ulen (1986), Haddock and Curran (1985), Rubinfeld (1987), Rea (1987), Chung (1993), and Edlin (1994). For a critical review of some of these works see Liao and White (2002), and Bar-Gill and Ben-Shahar (2003). 6 See, Parisi and Fon (2004, p. 359). 3

6 (See Parisi and Fon, 2004, pp , 364, Table 1). That is, the authors have claimed that the diligent (non-negligent) strategies are not dominant strategies. In contrast, we will show that under the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence, in an equilibrium, parties cannot both be negligent. That is, in an equilibrium, parties both cannot take less than the due care. Indeed, appealing to an existing claim in the literature, we are able to show that, in any equilibrium, neither the injurer nor the victim can be negligent (that is, each party will take at least the due level of care). In other words, we show that diligent strategies are dominant strategies for both the parties. Therefore, multiple equilibria, if exist, will involve at least the due care by both the parties. The framework of analysis in this paper is less restrictive than the standard framework. Regarding variables and functions, our framework has the virtue of relying on a fewer assumptions about continuity, differentiability, functional forms, etc. In particular, our analysis is equally applicable for both continuous as well as discrete variables. 7 Regarding the causation function, the mainstream focus has been on two forms of causal relationship; namely, the cases of causal complements and causal substitutes. In this paper, we allow a very general form of the causation function. Section 2 introduces the framework of analysis that outlines the notations and assumptions made in the paper. In Section 3, we investigate the efficiency implications of causal apportionment of liability, when both activity levels and care levels are variable. We conclude in Section 4 with remarks on the analysis in the paper. 2. Framework of Analysis We consider accidents resulting from the interaction of two parties who are strangers to each other. Both parties are assumed to be rational and risk-neutral. Each party s behaviour potentially contributes to causing an accident. However, when an accident takes place, the entire loss falls on one party to be called the victim; the other party will 7 Feldman and Frost (1998) have argued that the discrete and sometimes dichotomous care is the reality of many accident settings. 4

7 be called the injurer. Following Parisi and Fon (2004), parties choice of activity levels as well as care levels affect the causation of an accident. An accident is less likely to occur if a party decreases its activity level or increases its precaution, and vice-versa. In other words, a party s contribution to the causation of an accident increases, if it increases its activity level or decreases its care level. We refer to the parties individual contributions to causation of an accident as causal inputs. Therefore, a party s causal input will increase with the increase in its activity level, and decrease with the increase in its care level. Causation of an accident depends on the causal inputs of the parties involved. The elements contributing to the overall social cost of accident, are the cost of harm occasioned by an accident, the cost of care, and the cost of reducing the parties activity levels. Following the notation in Parisi and Fon (2004), we denote by: 8 x care level for the injurer, y care level for the victim, z activity level for the injurer, u activity level for the victim, X = {x x is some feasible level of care for the injurer }, Y = {y y is some feasible level of care for the victim}, Z = {z z is some feasible level of activity for the injurer }, U = {u u is some feasible level of activity for the victim}, w the benefit function for the injurer, b the benefit function for the victim, D loss per unit of activity, D 0, c I c V the causal input of the injurer, the causal input of the victim, C the total causation function, s the injurer s share in accident loss, t the victim s share in accident loss, such that t = 1 s. 8 These are conventional notation (see, e.g. Miceli (1997)). 5

8 We assume: (A1): w is a function of z and x; w = w(z, x). Benefits to the injurer increase with his activity level up to a point, i.e., w initially increases with z but ultimately decreases. w reaches a maximum at z p (x), for given x X. Increasing care is costly to the injurer, hence w is a decreasing function of x, for all z Z. Likewise, (A2): b is a function of u and y; b=b(u, y). b initially increases with the victim s activity level, u, but ultimately decreases. b reaches a maximum at u p (y), for given y Y. b is a decreasing function of y, for all u U. (A3): D is a function of x and y; D = D(x, y). Clearly, D 0. D is a non-increasing function of care level of each party. That is, a larger care by either party, given the care level of the other party, results in lesser or equal accident loss. As D is loss per unit of activity, for given z and u total loss will be zud(x, y). (A4): c I is a function of z and x; c I = c I (z, x). c I increases with z and decreases with x. (A5): c V is a function of u and y; c V = c V (u, y). c V increases with u and decreases with y. (A4) and (A5) imply that by increasing its activity level or reducing its care level, a party increases its contribution to the causation of an accident, i.e., make the accident more likely, and vice-versa. (A6): C, the total causation function, is an increasing function of both c I and c V ; C = C(c I, c V ). Therefore, C is an increasing function of both z and u, and a decreasing function of x and y. (A7): Social benefits from activity of a party are fully internalized by that party. (A8): Social goal is to maximize the net social benefits from the activities of the parties; the net social benefits are equal to the total social benefits minus the total social costs of accident. (A9): Benefit, cost, and causation functions are such that there is a unique tuple of z, u, x, and y, denoted by ((z, x ), (u, y )) that is socially optimal. In other words, net social benefits are maximized, if the injurer chooses z as his activity level and x as his care level, and the victim opts for u as his activity level and y as his care level. Therefore, z and x, respectively, denote the activity level and the care level for the injurer 6

9 that are optimal from social point of view; and u and y, respectively, are the activity level and the care level of the victim that are optimal from social point of view. (A10): The legal due care standard (i.e., the negligence standard) for the injurer, wherever applicable (say under the rule of negligence), is set at x. Similarly, the legal negligence standard of care for the victim, wherever applicable (say under the rule of strict liability with defense) is set at y. (A11): c I (.), c V (.), C(.) D(.) are all positive. It should be noted that assumptions (A1)-(A11) are standard assumptions. 9 However, on several counts, our framework is less restrictive than the standard framework. For one, regarding the variables and functional forms, in mainstream analyses it is generally taken that the care levels as well as the activity levels are continuous variables, and various functions (e.g., the benefit function, the expected loss functions, and so on) are differentiable. Our modelling, in contrast, does not impose any such condition, and is more general in that it is equally applicable for continuous as well as discrete variables. For another, regarding the causation function, Parisi and Fon (2004) have considered only two forms of C(c I (z, x), c V (u, y)), namely when C(c I (z, x), c V (u, y)) = c I (z, x). c V (u, y), and when C(c I (z, x), c V (u, y)) = c I (z, x) + c V (u, y). The first one is called the case of causal complements and the second one is called the case of causal substitutes. However, in the literature it has been argued that causal inputs of the parties can affect the causation of an accident in several different ways. In some cases causal inputs affect causation of an accident additively, while in other cases they can do so multiplicatively, or some times even a mix thereof (Parisi and Fon 2004; Landes and Posner, 1983). 10 In this paper, we allow a very general form of the causation function. In fact, the only restriction imposed is the assumption (A6). The social objective is to maximize the net social benefits from the activities. There- 9 e.g., see Miceli (1997), and Parisi and Fon (2004). 10 Also see Rizzo and Arnold (1980 and 1986), Kaye and Aickin (1984), Wright (1985), and Kruskal (1986). 7

10 fore, the social optimization problem is given by: 11 max z,x,u,y w(z, x) + b(u, y) C(c I (z, x), c V (u, y))zud(x, y). A liability rule can be considered as a rule or a mechanism that determines the proportions in which the victim and the injurer will bear the accident loss, as a function of their care and activity levels. Depending on the care and activity levels of the victim and the injurer, a liability rule uniquely determines the proportions in which they are to bear the accident loss. That is, given the choice of z and x by the injurer, and u and y by the victim, a liability rule determines the injurer s share, s(z, x, u, y), and the victim s share, t(z, x, u, y), of accident loss. 12 For a party, payoff from engaging in an activity depends on its activity level, its care level, and the proportion of accident loss it will be required to bear under the liability rule in force. Therefore, choice of care and activity level by a party will depend on the liability rule in force, as well as the care and activity levels of the other party. For any given pair (u, y) opted by the victim and depending on the rule, the injurer being rational and risk-neutral will choose a pair (z, x) that maximizes his expected payoff. In other words, given (u, y) U Y opted by the victim, problem facing the injurer is max z,x w(z, x) s(z, x, u, y)c(c I (z, x), c V (u, y))zud(x, y). Likewise, given (z, x) Z X opted by the injurer, problem facing the victim is max u,y b(u, y) t(z, x, u, y)c(c I (z, x), c V (u, y))zud(x, y), where s(z, x, u, y) and t(z, x, u, y) are determined by the relevant liability rule, but are such that s + t = This formulation of social optimization problem is as in Parisi and Fon (2004). 12 It should be noted that in the standard literature, these share depend on only the care levels of the parties involved. Since I want to re-examine the results in Parisi and Fon (2004), share are assumed to depend on care as well as activity levels of the parties. Later, however, we show that results in this paper hold, even when these share are determined only on the basis of the care levels of the parties. 8

11 A liability rule is said to be efficient iff it motivates both the parties to take socially efficient care and activity levels. Formally, a liability rule is efficient iff ((z, x ), (u, y )) is a unique Nash equilibrium (N.E.) under the rule Comparative Causation In this section, we consider the two rules introduced and analyzed in Parisi and Fon (2004); the rule of Pure Comparative Causation, and the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence. Pure Comparative Causation Under the rule of Pure Comparative Causation, as defined by Parisi and Fon, for given (z, x) and (u, y) opted by the injurer and the victim, respectively, the injurer s share in accident loss is equal to by c I (z,x) c I (z,x)+c V (u,y). Therefore, the victim s share is given c V (u,y). Formally, the rule of Pure Comparative Causation, can be defined as c I (z,x)+c V (u,y) follows: For (z, x) Z X and (u, y) U Y, s(z, x, u, y) = c I (z, x) c I (z, x) + c V (u, y) and t(z, x, u, y) = c V (u, y) c I (z, x) + c V (u, y). In their analysis, Parisi and Fon have argued that under this rule, the injurer [the victim] will choose some x < x [y < y ] as care level and some z > z [u > u ] as activity level (see Parisi and Fon, 2004, pp. 355, 357, 364). They have argued that since each party bears only a fraction of the loss, there is an incentive to choose less than socially optimal care and more than socially optimal activity level. In other words, the rule of Pure Comparative Causation induces neither efficient care levels nor efficient activity levels. Next, we consider the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence, as proposed by Parisi and Fon. 13 We consider only pure strategy Nash equilibria. A tuple (( z, x), (ū, ȳ)) is said to be a N.E. iff given (ū, ȳ) opted by the victim, ( z, x) is a best response from the view point of the injurer, and vice-versa. The use of the notion of N.E. as prediction for equilibrium outcome is very common in the literature on liability rules. 9

12 Comparative Causation Under Negligence Under this rule, when a party is found solely negligent, the entire loss is borne by this party. In other words, whenever the injurer is negligent and the victim is not, the victim receives full compensation for the loss. If the victim is negligent and the injurer is not, the victim bears the entire loss. Accident loss is shared between the parties only in cases where parties are either both negligent or when both are non-negligent. In such cases, the loss-sharing is done as under the rule of Pure Comparative Causation. This rule, therefore, captures an essential feature of traditional negligence-criterion based rules; a solely negligent party bears the entire accident loss, and the other (non-negligent) party bears none of it. Yet, the rule allows sharing of accident loss that is consistent with the rule of Pure Comparative Causation, when neither of the parties is unilaterally negligent. Summing up, under this rule, given (u, y) U Y opted by the victim, the problem faced by the injurer is given by the following: max z, x w(z, x) if x x and y < y ; w(z, x) c I (z,x) c I (z,x)+c V (u,y) C(cI (z, x), c V (u, y))zud(x, y) if x x and y y, or x < x and y < y ; w(z, x) C(c I (z, x), c V (u, y))zud(x, y) if x < x and y y. Similarly, under the rule, the problem facing the victim is: max u, y b(u, y) if x < x and y y ; b(u, y) c V (u,y) c I (z,x)+c V (u,y) C(cI (z, x), c V (u, y))zud(x, y) if x x and y y, or x < x and y < y ; b(u, y) C(c I (z, x), c V (u, y))zud(x, y) if x x and y < y. Note that under the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence if both the parties take efficient care, then they share accident loss according to the requirement of pure comparative causation. Therefore, if this rule could induce both the parties to take efficient care and activity levels, it will have the unique virtue of being efficient as well as 10

13 equitable. However, regarding the behaviour of the parties under the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence, Parisi and Fon (2004) have stated the following propositions: (1) In equilibrium, parties are never induced to take more than the due care; (2) Multiple equilibria in which one or both the parties take less than the due care are possible; (3) In some contexts, the choice of the due care by both the parties is also a possibility; (4) Though there is an incentive to mitigate activity levels, each party s activity level will be greater than the corresponding socially optimal level. (See Parisi and Fon, 2004, pp , 364, Table 1). That is, the authors have concluded that for the parties the diligent (non-negligent) strategies are not dominant strategies. Therefore, in an equilibrium, the level of care taken the injurer, x, and the level of care taken the victim, y, will be such that x x and y y. 14 In particular, in an equilibrium, any of the following can hold: (i) x < x and y < y, (ii) x < x and y = y, (iii) x = x and y < y, and (iv) x = x and y = y. In contrast, we will show that under the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence, the claims (i)-(iii) cannot be true. We show that in any equilibrium, x < x and y < y, i.e., the claim (i) above, can never hold. Appealing to an already existing claim in the literature, we show that claims (ii) and (iii) cannot hold. Indeed, care levels x and y can be part of an equilibrium, only if x x and y y. In other words, we show that diligent strategies are dominant strategies for both the parties. First of all, note that an essential feature of negligence-criterion based rules is captured by the following property: Property (P1): A non-negligent party has no liability, if the other party is negligent. In the following, we investigate the behavior of parties under rules that satisfy property 14 See Parisi and Fon, 2004, pp. 362, 364, Table 1. 11

14 (P1). To start with, we show that under a liability rule that satisfies property (P1), the parties cannot both be negligent in a N.E., no matter how the liability is assigned when both parties are negligent. 15 In other words, in any Nash equilibrium, x < x and y < y can never hold. To see why, take any ((z, x), (u, y)) such that x < x and y < y. Suppose, the injurer opts for (z, x) and the victim for (u, y). At ((z, x), (u, y)), let s(z, x, u, y) be the injurer s share of loss, where 0 s(z, x, u, y) 1. So, t(z, x, u, y) = 1 s(z, x, u, y). As a result, suppressing the arguments of s and t, at ((z, x), (u, y)), the payoff of the victim is b(u, y) t C(c I (z, x), c V (u, y))zud(x, y). On the other hand, given that (z, x) is opted by the injurer, if the victim instead opts for (u, y ), then the injurer will be solely negligent. In that case, in view of (P1), the injurer s liability is full and that of the victim is none. Therefore, given that (z, x) is opted by the injurer, if the victim opts for (u, y ), his payoff will be b(u, y ). Similarly, at ((z, x), (u, y)) the payoff of the injurer are w(z, x) s C(c I (z, x), c V (u, y))zud(x, y). But, given that (u, y) is opted by the victim, should the injurer opt instead for (z, x ), his payoff will be w(z, x ). At ((z, x), (u, y)) if w(z, x ) > w(z, x) sc(c I (z, x), c V (u, y))zud(x, y), a unilateral deviation by the injurer to (z, x ) will be strictly profitable. In that case, ((z, x), (u, y)) cannot be a N.E. Thus, if ((z, x), (u, y)) is a N.E., then a unilateral deviation by the injurer to (z, x ) cannot be strictly profitable. Therefore, assume that w(z, x) sc(c I (z, x), c V (u, y))zud(x, y) w(z, x ) (1) Since ((z, x), (u, y)) ((z, x ), (u, y )), by assumption, we know that w(z, x ) + b(u, y ) C(c I (z, x ), c V (u, y ))z u D(x, y ) > w(z, x) + b(u, y) C(c I (z, x), c V (u, y))zud(x, y). (2) Subtracting w(z, x ) from the LHS and w(z, x) s(c I (z, x), c V (u, y))zud(x, y) from the RHS of (2), in view of (1), we get 15 It should be noted that an equilibrium in Parisi and Fon (2004) will be a N.E. 12

15 b(u, y ) C(c I (z, x ), c V (u, y ))z u D(x, y ) > b(u, y) tc(c I (z, x), c V (u, y))zud(x, y). (3) Now, since C(c I (z, x ), c V (u, y ))z u D(x, y ) 0, from (3) we have b(u, y ) > b(u, y) tc(c I (z, x), c V (u, y))zud(x, y). That is, given (z, x < x ) opted by the injurer, payoff of the victim is strictly greater if he chooses (u, y ) rather than (u, y), i.e., the victim will be better off opting (u, y ) rather than (u, y). Again, ((z, x), (u, y)) cannot be a N.E. In other words, under a liability rule satisfying (P1), from any ((z, x), (u, y)) such that x < x & y < y, either the injurer will find unilaterally deviation to (z, x ) profitable, or the victim will find unilaterally deviation to (u, y ) profitable. Hence, we have the following result. Proposition 1 If a liability rule satisfies property (P1), then ( ((z, x), (u, y))) [x < x & y < y ((z, x), (u, y)) cannot be a N.E.]. Note that how a liability rule assign liability when parties are both negligent has no implications for the validity of Proposition 1. Moreover most of the negligence criterion based rules discussed in the literature (e.g., the rule of negligence, the rule of negligence with the defense of contributory negligence, the rule of strict liability with the defense of contributory negligence) satisfy property (P1). Therefore, under all these rules both the parties cannot be negligent in an equilibrium. In particular, the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence, as defined in Parisi and Fon (2004), satisfies property (P1). Hence, we can make the following claim about the rule. Proposition 2 Under the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence, ( ((z, x), (u, y))) [x < x & y < y ((z, x), (u, y)) cannot be a N.E. ]. Remark 1: Suppose a liability rule satisfies property (P1). When x x and y < y, the victim is solely negligent. In such an event, due to property (P1), the injurer has no liability. So, for given z his payoff is w(z, x). Note that w(z, x) increases with z and deceases with x. Therefore, regardless of the z opted by him whenever x > x, the injurer can increase his payoff simply by reducing x until he reaches at x. This means that the injurer will be better off opting x rather than any x > x. As a result, any 13

16 tuple ((z, x), (u, y)), such that x > x & y < y, cannot be a N.E. In fact, when the rule satisfies property (P1), in the region of x x and y < y, w(z, x) is uniquely maximized at (x, zp), where zp = z p (x ). Therefore, under the rule, when x x and y < y, a tuple ((z, x), (u, y)) can be a N.E. only if (z, x) = (zp, x ). Similarly, under a rule satisfying property (P1), when x < x and y y, a tuple ((z, x), (u, y)) can be a N.E. only if (u, y) = (u p, y ), where u p = u p (y ). It will be interesting to compare the incentive effects of the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence with those of the standard rules discussed in the literature. Regarding the standard negligence-criterion based rules the following claim exists in the literature (e.g., see Miceli, 1997 p. 29, Dari Mattiacci (2002), Parisi and Fon, 2004 Table 1, p. 364). 16 Claim (C1): Both the rule of negligence as well as the rule of strict liability with the defense of contributory negligence induce efficient care levels from both the parties. That is, the claim is that under these rules, there exist an equilibrium in which the injurer and the victim opt for x and y, respectively. Remark 2: It should be noted that the Claim (C1) is only regarding the care levels; activity levels are not claimed to be efficient. Moreover, equilibrium under the rule of negligence will be different from that under the rule of the strict liability with the defense of contributory negligence. The claim, however, implies that under both the rules, when (x, y) (x, y ), a tuple ((z, x), (u, y)) cannot be a N.E. Equipped with the claim (C1), Proposition 3 shows that under the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence, in equilibrium, neither of the parties can be negligent. In an equilibrium, both parties will take at least the due level of care. Formally, care levels x and y can be part of a N.E., only if x x and y y. 16 Also see Landes and Posner (1987) and Shavell (1987) as cited in Parisi and Fon (2004). 14

17 Proposition 3 Given that (C1) holds, under the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence, ((z, x), (u, y)) is a N.E. x x & y y. Proof: In view of Proposition 1, a tuple ((z, x), (u, y)) such that x < x and y < y, cannot be a N.E. Thus, to prove the claim, it will be sufficient if we can show that under the rule, a tuple ((z, x), (u, y)) such that x x and y < y, or x < x and y y cannot be a N.E. Consider a tuple ((z, x), (u, y)) such that x x and y < y. Since the rule in question satisfies (P1), in view of Remark 1, when x x and y < y, a tuple ((z, x), (u, y)) can be a N.E. only if (z, x) = (z p, x ), where z p = z p (x ). Therefore, to show that a tuple ((z, x), (u, y)) such that x x and y < y cannot be a N.E., we just have show that tuple ((z p, x ), (u, y)), where y < y, cannot be a N.E. Similarly, to show that a tuple ((z, x), (u, y)), such that x < x and y y, cannot be a N.E., we just have show that tuple ((z, x), (u p, y )), where x < x and u p = u p (y ), cannot be a N.E. First, we consider whether a tuple ((z p, x ), (u, y)), such that y < y, is a N.E. or not. Suppose, (z p, x ) is opted by the injurer. Notice that under the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence, when (z p, x ) is opted by the injurer, if the victim chooses some (u, y ) then both the parties are non-negligent. So, the victim s payoff will be b(u, y ) c V (u,y ) c I (z p,x )+c V (u,y ) C(cI (z p, x ), c V (u, y ))z pud(x, y ). And, if he instead chooses some (u, y), such that y < y, he will be solely negligent. In that case, under the rule he will be required to bear the entire accident loss. Therefore, when (z p, x ) is opted by the injurer, if the victim chooses some (u, y) such that y < y, his payoff will be b(u, y) C(c I (z p, x ), c V (u, y))z pud(x, y). In the following, we show that given (z p, x ) opted by the injurer, the victim will be better off opting y along with a suitable u U, rather than any y < y. We are given that Claim (C1) holds, i.e., under the rule of negligence, in equilibrium, the injurer opts for x and the victim opts for y. When x = x, the injurer is nonnegligent. Therefore, under the rule of negligence he has no liability, i.e., for given z his payoff is w(z, x ), which is uniquely maximized at z = z p, where z p = z p (x ). In other words, the claim implies that under the rule of negligence, the injurer will opt for (z p, x ). 15

18 On the other hand, when x = x, the victim bears the entire loss. Therefore, if he opts for some (u, y) his payoff is b(u, y) C(c I (zp, x ), c V (u, y))zpud(x, y). In view of Claim (C1), along with y, the victim will choose a u U, say ū, that maximizes his payoff. 17 In other words, given that the injurer has opted for (zp, x ), under the rule of negligence (ū, y ) is a best choice for the victim. Formally put, the claim implies that there exists ū U such that between (ū, y ), on the one hand, and any (u, y) U Y, on the other, the following relationship exists: b(u, y) C(c I (zp, x ), c V (u, y))zpud(x, y) b(ū, y ) C(c I (zp, x ), c V (ū, y ))zpūd(x, y ). (4) But, since c V (ū,y ) c I (z p,x )+c V (ū,y ) < 1 and C(cI (z p, x ), c V (ū, y ))z pūd(x, y ) > 0, we get b(ū, y ) C(c I (z p, x ), c V (ū, y ))z pūd(x, y ) < b(ū, y ) c V (ū,y ) c I (z p,x )+c V (ū,y ) C(cI (z p, x ), c V (ū, y ))z pūd(x, y ). (5) Now, (4)&(5) for all (u, y) U Y, we get b(u, y) C(c I (z p, x ), c V (u, y))z pud(x, y) c V (ū,y ) < b(ū, y ) c I (zp,x )+c V (ū,y ) C(cI (zp, x ), c V (ū, y ))zpūd(x, y ). In particular, for all (u, y) U Y, such that y < y, we have b(u, y) C(c I (z p, x ), c V (u, y))z pud(x, y) < b(ū, y ) c V (ū,y ) c I (z p,x )+c V (ū,y ) C(cI (z p, x ), c V (ū, y ))z pūd(x, y ). (6) In other words, for all (u, y < y ) U Y, there exists (ū, y ) U Y such that (6) holds. Note that under the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence if we assume that the injurer has opted for (z p, x ), then the left hand side of (6) denotes the payoff of the victim when he opts for some (u, y) U Y, such that y < y. The right hand side of (6) denotes the payoff of the victim, when he instead opts for (ū, y ). But, (6) implies that given that (z p, x ) is opted by the injurer, the victim is better off opting (ū, y ) rather than any (u, y) such that y < y. Thus, under the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence, any ((z p, x ), (u, y)), such that y < y, cannot be a N.E. 17 We assume that such u exists. In that case, it should be noted that Claim 1 implies that under the rule of negligence, ((z p, x ), (ū, y )) is a N.E. 16

19 Similarly, appealing to the claim that under the rule of strict liability with the defense of contributory negligence, the injurer opts for x and the victim opts for y, and arguing as above, we can show the following: Under the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence, given that (u p, y ) is opted by the victim, the injurer will not choose any (z, x) such that x < x. That is, a tuple ((z, x), (u p, y )), such that x < x, cannot be a N.E. Thus, under the rule, any ((z, x), (u, y)) such that x < x & y y, or x x & y < y cannot be a N.E. Remark 3: It should be noted that for Propositions 1 and 2 to hold, the sufficient condition is the Property (P1). The condition concerns liability assignment when one party is negligent and the other is not, regardless of the activity levels of the parties. Therefore, for these claims to hold, liability assignment need not be based on the activity levels of the parties. For Proposition 3, the sufficient condition is provided by the Property (P1) along with Claim (C1). Again, it can be checked that liability need not depend on the activity levels of the parties Concluding Remarks Parisi and Fon (2004) is an important contribution to the tort literature in that it is first systematic study of the liability assignment based on comparative causation. However, we have shown that some of the propositions in the study need re-examination. We have shown that under the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence, in an equilibrium, choice of less than the due care by both parties is not possible. In fact, in any equilibrium, neither of the parties can be negligent. It immediately follows from out results that multiple equilibria, if they exist, will involve at least the due care by both the parties. Therefore, the search for the existence of an equilibrium should focus on the cases which involve the due or more than the due care by both the parties; not on the cases wherein one or both the parties are negligent, as Parisi and Fon suggest. 18 Of course, to the extant that liability does not depend on the activity levels of the parties, liability assignment will be different from what is required under the rules of comparative causation. 17

20 Note that under the rule of Comparative Causation Under Negligence, when both parties take at least the due care, a party bears only a fraction of the total accident loss. Now, when both parties are non-negligent, suppose a party increases its activity level beyond the socially optimal level for this party. In such a scenario, this party will bear only a fraction of the resulting increase in the social costs. On the other hand, all the benefits from increased activity level will accrue to the party. As a result, excess activity levels seem to be a possibility. Regarding the care levels, however, the opposite in true; a party bears full cost of the care taken by it, while sharing the benefits of care with the other party. This means that there are incentives for parties to take less care. But, at the same time, under the rule the following is also true. When a party increases its care level beyond the due level, the loss that will be shared as well as the party s share in the loss come down. This means there are some incentives for the parties to take excess care. Moreover, it can be shown that productivity of care increases with the increase in the activity levels of the parties. Therefore, in the non-negligence region parties face various prospects with conflicting implications. In such a scenario, whether there will be a unique equilibrium, no equilibrium, or multi-equilibria, is an important question that requires further research. Finally, it should be noted that while proving Propositions 1-3, we have not restricted the functional form of the causation function. Therefore, our results hold in a more general context of the causal relationship. The Propositions are, of course, valid for the cases of causal substitutes and causal complements, which are two special forms of the causation function. 18

21 References Arlen, J (1990), Re-examining liability rules when injurers as well as victims suffer losses, 10, International Review of Law and Economics, Bar-Gill, Oren, and Ben-Shahar, Omri (2003), The Uneasy Case for Comparative Negligence, American Law and Economic Review, 5: Burrows, P (1999), A deferential role for efficiency theory in analysing causation-based Tort law, 8, European Journal of Law and Economics, Calabresi, Guido (1965), The decision for accidents: An approach to non-fault allocation of costs. 78 Harvard Law Review Calabresi, Guido (1970), The Costs of Accidents: A Legal and Economic Analysis, New Haven: Yale University Press. Calabresi, Guido and Cooper, Jeffrey (1996), New directions in tort law. 30 Valparaiso University Law Review, Chung, Tai-Yeong (1993), Efficiency of Comparative Negligence: A Game Theoretic Analysis, 22 Journal of Legal Studies, Cooter, R. D. and Ulen, T. S. (1998), Law and Economics, IInd ed., New York, Addison- Wesley. Cooter, Robert D. and Ulen, Thomas S. (1986), An Economic Case for Comparative Negligence, 81 New York University Law Review, Dari Mattiacci, G (2002), Tort Law and Economics, in Hatzis A. ed., Economics Analysis of Law: A European Perspective, Edward Elgar. Edlin, Aaron S. (1994), Efficient Standards of Due Care: Should Courts Find More Parties Negligent under Comparative Negligence?, 14 International Review of Law and Economics, Feldman, Allan M. and Frost, John M. (1998), A Simple Model of Efficient Tort Liability Rules, 18 International Review of Law and Economics, Geistfeld, Mark (2001), Economics, Moral Philosophy, and the Positive Analysis of Tort Law, in Gerald J. Postema ed., Philosophy and the Law of Torts, , Cambridge University Press. 19

22 Grady, Mark F. (1989), Untaken Precautions, 18, Journal of Legal Studies, Grimley, William (2000), Comparative Fault Solidary Delictual Obligations: On Further Consideration, 60 Louisiana Law Review 513. Haddock, D., and Curran, C. (1985): An Economic Theory of Comparative Negligence. Journal of Legal Studies 14: Honoré, Tony (1997), The morality of Tort Law, in Owen, David G. (ed.) (1997), Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law, Oxford, Clarendon Press. Hylton Keith N (2000), The Theory of Tort Doctrine and The Restatement of Torts Boston University School Of Law Working Paper Series, Law Economics, No Jain, Satish K and Singh, Ram, (2002), Efficient Liability Rules: Complete Characterization, Journal of Economics, Vol. 75, No 2, Kahan, Marcel (1989), Causation and Incentives to Take Care under the Negligence Rule, 18 Journal of Legal Studies, Kaye, David and Aickin, Mikel (1984), A Comment on Causal Apportionment, 13 Journal of Legal Studies, Kruskal, William (1986), Terms of Reference: Singular Confusion about Multiple Causation, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, Landes, William M. and Posner, R. A. (1987), The Economic Structure of Tort Law, Cambridge (MA), Harvard University Press. Landes, William M. and Posner, Richard A. (1983), Causation in Tort Law: An Economic Approach, 12 Journal of Legal Studies, Liao, Yu-Ping and White, Michelle J. (2002), No-Fault for Motor Vehicles: An Economic Analysis, American Law and Economics Review Marks, Stephen V. (1994), Discontinuities, Causation, and Grady s Uncertainty Theorem, 23 Journal of Legal Studies, Miceli, Thomas J. (1997), Economics of the Law: Torts, Contracts, Property, Litigation, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Parisi, Francesco (2001), Genesis of Liability in Ancient Law, 3 American Law and Economics Review, Parisi, Francesco and Fon, Vincy (2004), Comparative Causation, 6, American Law and 20

23 Economics Review, Polinsky, A. M(1989), An Introduction to Law and Economics, 2nd ed,boston,little,brown and Co. Rea, S.A., Jr. (1987): The Economics of Comparative Negligence. International Review of Law and Economics 7: Rizzo, Mario J. and Arnold, Frank S. (1980), Causal Apportionment in the Law of Torts: an Economic Theory, Columbia Law Review, Rizzo, Mario J. and Arnold, Frank S. (1986), Causal Apportionment: Reply to the Critics, 15 Journal of Legal Studies, Rubinfeld, Daniel L. (1987), The Efficiency of Comparative Negligence, 16 Journal of Legal Studies, Schwartz, Gary T. (1978), Contributory and Comparative Negligence: A Reappraisal, 87 Yale Law Journal, Shavell, S. (1987), Economic Analysis of Accident Law, Cambridge (MA), Harvard Univ. Press. Strassfeld, Robert (1992), Causal Comparisons, 60 Fordham Law Review, Wright, Richard W. (1985), Actual Causation vs. Probabilistic Linkage: The Bane of Economic Analysis, Journal of Legal Studies, Wright, Richard W. (1987), The Efficiency Theory of Causation and Responsibility: Unscientific Formalism and False Semantics, 63 Chicago-Kent Law Review, Yoshihsa, Nomi (1999), Environmental Liability in Japan, in, Ewould Hondius ed. 1999, Modern Trends in Tort Law, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Yu, Li (2000), Book Review: Modern Trends in Tort Law: Dutch and Japanese Law Compared, 6 Columbia Journal of European Law *Complete list of Working Papers is available at the CDE Website: 21

Full Compensation Criteria in the Law of Torts An Enquiry into the Doctrine of Causation Ram Singh

Full Compensation Criteria in the Law of Torts An Enquiry into the Doctrine of Causation Ram Singh Full Compensation Criteria in the Law of Torts An Enquiry into the Doctrine of Causation Ram Singh WORKING PAPER SERIES Centre for the Study of Law and Governance Jawaharlal Nehru University, New Delhi

More information

HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS

HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS chissn 1045-6333 ECONOMICS AND LIABILITY FOR ACCIDENTS Steven Shavell Discussion Paper No. 535 12/2005 Harvard Law School Cambridge, MA 02138

More information

Empirical Comparisons of the Contributory versus Comparative Negligence Rules. Michelle J. White

Empirical Comparisons of the Contributory versus Comparative Negligence Rules. Michelle J. White Empirical Comparisons of the Contributory versus Comparative Negligence Rules Michelle J. White The liability rule traditionally used in accident law when both the injurer s and the victim s behaviour

More information

The Reasonable Person Negligence Standard and Liability Insurance. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University

The Reasonable Person Negligence Standard and Liability Insurance. Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University \ins\liab\dlirpr.v3a 06-06-07 The Reasonable Person Negligence Standard and Liability Insurance Vickie Bajtelsmit * Colorado State University Paul Thistle University of Nevada Las Vegas Thistle s research

More information

LIABILITY FOR ACCIDENTS

LIABILITY FOR ACCIDENTS Chapter 2 LIABILITY FOR ACCIDENTS STEVEN SHAVELL * School of Law, Harvard University, and National Bureau of Economic Research Contents 1. Introduction 142 Part A: Central theory of liability 142 2. Incentives

More information

ON THE INTRINSIC SUPERIORITY OF REGULATION AND INSURANCE OVER TORT LAW

ON THE INTRINSIC SUPERIORITY OF REGULATION AND INSURANCE OVER TORT LAW ON THE INTRINSIC SUPERIORITY OF REGULATION AND INSURANCE OVER TORT LAW Gerrit De Geest * Utrecht University and Ghent University Giuseppe Dari Mattiacci ** Ghent University and Utrecht University ABSTRACT

More information

)LQDQFLDO$VVXUDQFH,VVXHV RI(QYLURQPHQWDO/LDELOLW\

)LQDQFLDO$VVXUDQFH,VVXHV RI(QYLURQPHQWDO/LDELOLW\ )LQDQFLDO$VVXUDQFH,VVXHV RI(QYLURQPHQWDO/LDELOLW\ ([HFXWLYH6XPPDU\ %\ 3URI'U0LFKDHO*)DXUH//0 DQG 0U'DYLG*ULPHDXG Maastricht University and European Centre for Tort and Insurance Law (ECTIL) Final version

More information

3500 TORT DAMAGES. Abstract

3500 TORT DAMAGES. Abstract 3500 TORT DAMAGES Jennifer Arlen Ivadelle and Theodore Johnson Professor of Law and Business University of Southern California Law School Copyright 1999 Jennifer Arlen Abstract This chapter surveys the

More information

STRICT LIABILITY VERSUS NEGLIGENCE

STRICT LIABILITY VERSUS NEGLIGENCE STRICT LIABILITY VERSUS NEGLIGENCE Hans-Bernd Schäfer and Frank Müller-Langer Universität Hamburg - Fachbereich Rechtswissenschaft Copyright 2008 Hans-Bernd Schäfer and Frank Müller-Langer Abstract The

More information

HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS

HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS ISSN 1045-6333 ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF ACCIDENT LAW Steven Shavell Discussion Paper No. 396 12/2002 Harvard Law School Cambridge, MA 02138 This

More information

3300 CAUSATION AND FORSEEABILITY

3300 CAUSATION AND FORSEEABILITY 3300 CAUSATION AND FORSEEABILITY Omri Ben-Shahar Tel Aviv University Copyright 1999 Omri Ben-Shahar Abstract This chapter begins with a survey of the implicit role of causation in the writings of the early,

More information

George Mason University

George Mason University George Mason Universit SCHOOL of LAW COMPARATE CAUSATON Francesco Parisi inc Fon 01-30 Forthcoming in the American Law and Economics Review. LAW AND ECONOMCS WORKNG PAPER SERES This paper can be downloaded

More information

Chapter 7. Sealed-bid Auctions

Chapter 7. Sealed-bid Auctions Chapter 7 Sealed-bid Auctions An auction is a procedure used for selling and buying items by offering them up for bid. Auctions are often used to sell objects that have a variable price (for example oil)

More information

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF ACCIDENT LAW. Steven Shavell. Working Paper 9694 http://www.nber.org/papers/w9694

NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF ACCIDENT LAW. Steven Shavell. Working Paper 9694 http://www.nber.org/papers/w9694 NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF ACCIDENT LAW Steven Shavell Working Paper 9694 http://www.nber.org/papers/w9694 NATIONAL BUREAU OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH 1050 Massachusetts Avenue Cambridge,

More information

DOES UNCERTAINTY CALL FOR COMPARATIVE NEGLIGENCE? Oren Bar-Gill. Discussion Paper No. 346 12/2001. Harvard Law School Cambridge, MA 02138

DOES UNCERTAINTY CALL FOR COMPARATIVE NEGLIGENCE? Oren Bar-Gill. Discussion Paper No. 346 12/2001. Harvard Law School Cambridge, MA 02138 ISSN 1045-6333 DOES UNCERTAINTY CALL FOR COMPARATIVE NEGLIGENCE? Oren Bar-Gill Discussion Paper No. 346 12/2001 Harvard Law School Cambridge, MA 02138 The Center for Law, Economics, and Business is supported

More information

George Mason University SCHOOL of LAW

George Mason University SCHOOL of LAW George Mason University SCHOOL of LAW CAUSATION AND RESPONSIBILITY: THE COMPENSATION PRINCIPLE FROM GROTIUS TO CALABRESI Francesco Parisi Vincy Fon 04-13 LAW AND ECONOMICS WORKING PAPER SERIES This paper

More information

Why Plaintiffs Attorneys Use Contingent and Defense Attorneys Fixed Fee Contracts

Why Plaintiffs Attorneys Use Contingent and Defense Attorneys Fixed Fee Contracts Why Plaintiffs Attorneys Use Contingent and Defense Attorneys Fixed Fee Contracts Winand Emons 1 Claude Fluet 2 1 Department of Economics University of Bern, CEPR, CIRPEE 2 Université du Québec à Montréal,

More information

ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW

ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW Chapter 25 ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW LOUIS KAPLOW and STEVEN SHAVELL Harvard Law School and National Bureau of Economic Research Contents Abstract 1665 Keywords 1665 1. Introduction 1666 2. Liability for

More information

A Simple Model of Efficient Tort Liability Rules

A Simple Model of Efficient Tort Liability Rules A Simple Model of Efficient Tort Liability Rules ALLAN M. FELDMAN and JOHN M. FROST Department of Economics, Brown University, Providence, Rhode Island, USA E-mail: allan feldman@brown.edu We present a

More information

System Reliability and Free Riding

System Reliability and Free Riding System Reliability and Free Riding Hal R. Varian University of California, Berkeley February 2001 This version: November 30, 2004. System reliability often depends on the effort of many individuals, making

More information

Boalt Hall UC Berkeley

Boalt Hall UC Berkeley Boalt Hall UC Berkeley Title: A Note on Settlements under the Contingent Fee Method of Compensating Lawyers Author: Polinsky, A. Mitchell, Stanford Law School Rubinfeld, Daniel L., University of California,

More information

Moral Hazard. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania

Moral Hazard. Itay Goldstein. Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania Moral Hazard Itay Goldstein Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania 1 Principal-Agent Problem Basic problem in corporate finance: separation of ownership and control: o The owners of the firm are typically

More information

LOUISIANA PERSONAL INJURY ACCIDENT BASICS

LOUISIANA PERSONAL INJURY ACCIDENT BASICS LOUISIANA PERSONAL INJURY ACCIDENT BASICS The Concept of Negligence If you have been injured, only an experienced Louisiana personal injury accident attorney can evaluate the unique facts and circumstances

More information

Liability Insurance as Protection Against Legal Error. Vickie Bajtelsmit Colorado State University. and

Liability Insurance as Protection Against Legal Error. Vickie Bajtelsmit Colorado State University. and lipale.v2a 07-17-08 Liability Insurance as Protection Against Legal Error Vickie Bajtelsmit Colorado State University and Paul D. Thistle * University of Nevada Las Vegas Thistle s research was supported

More information

Accident Law and Ambiguity

Accident Law and Ambiguity Accident Law and Ambiguity Surajeet Chakravarty and David Kelsey Department of Economics University of Exeter January 2012 (University of Exeter) Tort and Ambiguity January 2012 1 / 26 Introduction This

More information

The Many Faces of Negligence

The Many Faces of Negligence The Many Faces of Negligence Ariel Porat * Negligence law is built around the paradigmatic case of a person who unreasonably preferred his own interests to those of others and, as a result, caused damage

More information

1 SHORT ANSWER QUESTIONS

1 SHORT ANSWER QUESTIONS Tort Law Suggested Answers 1 SHORT ANSWER QUESTIONS Comment on the Following: 1. [2002, Midterm #2a] Suppose that all doctors were held strictly liable for injuries they cause to their patients. What are

More information

Any Non-welfarist Method of Policy Assessment Violates the Pareto Principle. Louis Kaplow and Steven Shavell

Any Non-welfarist Method of Policy Assessment Violates the Pareto Principle. Louis Kaplow and Steven Shavell Any Non-welfarist Method of Policy Assessment Violates the Pareto Principle Louis Kaplow and Steven Shavell Harvard Law School and National Bureau of Economic Research The public at large, many policymakers,

More information

Journal Of Financial And Strategic Decisions Volume 8 Number 1 Spring 1995 INTEREST RATE SWAPS: A MANAGERIAL COMPENSATION APPROACH

Journal Of Financial And Strategic Decisions Volume 8 Number 1 Spring 1995 INTEREST RATE SWAPS: A MANAGERIAL COMPENSATION APPROACH Journal Of Financial And Strategic Decisions Volume 8 Number 1 Spring 1995 INTEREST RATE SWAPS: A MANAGERIAL COMPENSATION APPROACH John L. Scott * and Maneesh Sharma * Abstract The market for interest

More information

CHAPTER 2 THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN NO-FAULT INSURANCE AND DRIVER BEHAVIOR

CHAPTER 2 THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN NO-FAULT INSURANCE AND DRIVER BEHAVIOR -5- CHAPTER 2 THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN NO-FAULT INSURANCE AND DRIVER BEHAVIOR Under a traditional tort system, at-fault drivers are liable for the economic and noneconomic damages they inflict on third

More information

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets

Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Unraveling versus Unraveling: A Memo on Competitive Equilibriums and Trade in Insurance Markets Nathaniel Hendren January, 2014 Abstract Both Akerlof (1970) and Rothschild and Stiglitz (1976) show that

More information

Summary of Doctoral Dissertation: Voluntary Participation Games in Public Good Mechanisms: Coalitional Deviations and Efficiency

Summary of Doctoral Dissertation: Voluntary Participation Games in Public Good Mechanisms: Coalitional Deviations and Efficiency Summary of Doctoral Dissertation: Voluntary Participation Games in Public Good Mechanisms: Coalitional Deviations and Efficiency Ryusuke Shinohara 1. Motivation The purpose of this dissertation is to examine

More information

AN ECONOMIC MODEL OF TORT LAW

AN ECONOMIC MODEL OF TORT LAW CHAPTER 2 AN ECONOMIC MODEL OF TORT LAW This chapter and the next develop the economic model of accident, or tort, law. The model is based on the proposition that the rules of tort law are designed to

More information

HARVARD. Lucian Arye Bebchuk. Discussion Paper No. 226 12/1997. As published in 3 The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law 551-554 (1998)

HARVARD. Lucian Arye Bebchuk. Discussion Paper No. 226 12/1997. As published in 3 The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law 551-554 (1998) ISSN 1045-6333 HARVARD JOHN M. OLIN CENTER FOR LAW, ECONOMICS, AND BUSINESS SUITS WITH NEGATIVE EXPECTED VALUE Lucian Arye Bebchuk Discussion Paper No. 226 12/1997 As published in 3 The New Palgrave Dictionary

More information

Regret and Rejoicing Effects on Mixed Insurance *

Regret and Rejoicing Effects on Mixed Insurance * Regret and Rejoicing Effects on Mixed Insurance * Yoichiro Fujii, Osaka Sangyo University Mahito Okura, Doshisha Women s College of Liberal Arts Yusuke Osaki, Osaka Sangyo University + Abstract This papers

More information

Working Paper Series

Working Paper Series RGEA Universidade de Vigo http://webs.uvigo.es/rgea Working Paper Series A Market Game Approach to Differential Information Economies Guadalupe Fugarolas, Carlos Hervés-Beloso, Emma Moreno- García and

More information

Economics of Insurance

Economics of Insurance Economics of Insurance In this last lecture, we cover most topics of Economics of Information within a single application. Through this, you will see how the differential informational assumptions allow

More information

arxiv:1112.0829v1 [math.pr] 5 Dec 2011

arxiv:1112.0829v1 [math.pr] 5 Dec 2011 How Not to Win a Million Dollars: A Counterexample to a Conjecture of L. Breiman Thomas P. Hayes arxiv:1112.0829v1 [math.pr] 5 Dec 2011 Abstract Consider a gambling game in which we are allowed to repeatedly

More information

The Efficiency of Medical Malpractice Law. Theory and Empirical Evidence. Reed Neil Olsen

The Efficiency of Medical Malpractice Law. Theory and Empirical Evidence. Reed Neil Olsen The Efficiency of Medical Malpractice Law Theory and Empirical Evidence Reed Neil Olsen Department of Economics Southwest Missouri State University Phone: 417-836-5379 Fax: 417-836-4236 E-Mail: rno174f@smsu.edu

More information

(1) A person to whom damage to another is legally attributed is liable to compensate that damage.

(1) A person to whom damage to another is legally attributed is liable to compensate that damage. Principles of European Tort Law TITLE I. Basic Norm Chapter 1. Basic Norm Art. 1:101. Basic norm (1) A person to whom damage to another is legally attributed is liable to compensate that damage. (2) Damage

More information

Game Theory: Supermodular Games 1

Game Theory: Supermodular Games 1 Game Theory: Supermodular Games 1 Christoph Schottmüller 1 License: CC Attribution ShareAlike 4.0 1 / 22 Outline 1 Introduction 2 Model 3 Revision questions and exercises 2 / 22 Motivation I several solution

More information

Employers' Liability and Workers' Compensation

Employers' Liability and Workers' Compensation Brochure More information from http://www.researchandmarkets.com/reports/2623488/ Employers' Liability and Workers' Compensation Description: This large-scale comparative study analyses the two principal

More information

A Simple Model of Price Dispersion *

A Simple Model of Price Dispersion * Federal Reserve Bank of Dallas Globalization and Monetary Policy Institute Working Paper No. 112 http://www.dallasfed.org/assets/documents/institute/wpapers/2012/0112.pdf A Simple Model of Price Dispersion

More information

Lecture 8 The Subjective Theory of Betting on Theories

Lecture 8 The Subjective Theory of Betting on Theories Lecture 8 The Subjective Theory of Betting on Theories Patrick Maher Philosophy 517 Spring 2007 Introduction The subjective theory of probability holds that the laws of probability are laws that rational

More information

NEGLIGENCE, CAUSATION, AND INCENTIVES FOR CARE

NEGLIGENCE, CAUSATION, AND INCENTIVES FOR CARE NEGLIGENCE, CAUSATION, AND INCENTIVES FOR CARE Boston University School of Law Working Paper No. 11-15 (March 24, 2011) Revised February 15, 2013 Keith N. Hylton Boston University School of Law Haizhen

More information

THE EFFECT OF NO-FAULT ON FATAL ACCIDENT RATES

THE EFFECT OF NO-FAULT ON FATAL ACCIDENT RATES -xiii- SUMMARY Thirteen states currently either mandate no-fault auto insurance or allow drivers to choose between no-fault and tort insurance. No-fault auto insurance requires individuals to carry personal

More information

Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zurich. Working Paper Series ISSN 1424-0459. Working Paper No. 229

Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zurich. Working Paper Series ISSN 1424-0459. Working Paper No. 229 Institute for Empirical Research in Economics University of Zurich Working Paper Series ISSN 1424-0459 Working Paper No. 229 On the Notion of the First Best in Standard Hidden Action Problems Christian

More information

Employers Liability and Workers Compensation Questionnaire

Employers Liability and Workers Compensation Questionnaire Employers Liability and Workers Compensation Questionnaire [Reports should be structured according to the numbered headings below. Items designated by bullet points need not be addressed in separate subheadings,

More information

The Economics of Insurance Fraud Investigation: Evidence of a Nash Equilibrium

The Economics of Insurance Fraud Investigation: Evidence of a Nash Equilibrium The Economics of Insurance Fraud Investigation: Evidence of a Nash Equilibrium by Stephen. D Arcy University of Illinois Department of Finance 06 South Sixth Street Champaign I 680 USA Telephone: 00-7-333-077

More information

PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE OR CIRCULATE VERY PRELIMINARY VERSION The Economics of Reverse Contingent Fees

PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE OR CIRCULATE VERY PRELIMINARY VERSION The Economics of Reverse Contingent Fees PLEASE DO NOT QUOTE OR CIRCULATE VERY PRELIMINARY VERSION The Economics of Reverse Contingent Fees Albert CHOI University of Virginia Nuno GAROUPA Universidade Nova de Lisboa CEPR, London June 2005 Abstract

More information

Submissions on Civil Liability Reform

Submissions on Civil Liability Reform Submissions on Civil Liability Reform The Coalition of British Columbia Businesses October 2002 Introduction: The following submissions are made on behalf of the Coalition of British Columbia Businesses.

More information

EMPLOYMENT EDUCATION. HARVARD LAW SCHOOL Cambridge, Massachusetts Visiting Professor of Law, Fall, 2003

EMPLOYMENT EDUCATION. HARVARD LAW SCHOOL Cambridge, Massachusetts Visiting Professor of Law, Fall, 2003 GREGORY C. KEATING USC Gould School of Law Los Angeles, CA 90089-0071 Tel: 213.740.2565 Fax: 213.740.5502 e-mail: gkeating@law.usc.edu http://www.usc.edu/dept/law/faculty/gkeating.htm EMPLOYMENT UNIVERSITY

More information

Credible Discovery, Settlement, and Negative Expected Value Suits

Credible Discovery, Settlement, and Negative Expected Value Suits Credible iscovery, Settlement, and Negative Expected Value Suits Warren F. Schwartz Abraham L. Wickelgren Abstract: This paper introduces the option to conduct discovery into a model of settlement bargaining

More information

Minimum asset requirements and compulsory liability insurance as solutions to the judgment-proof problem

Minimum asset requirements and compulsory liability insurance as solutions to the judgment-proof problem RAND Journal of Economics Vol. 36, No. 1, Spring 2005 pp. 63 77 Minimum asset requirements and compulsory liability insurance as solutions to the judgment-proof problem Steven Shavell Minimum asset and

More information

Volume 3, Spring Issue, 1990 ENVIRONMENTAL ACCIDENTS: PERSONAL INJURY AND PUBLIC RESPONSIBILITY

Volume 3, Spring Issue, 1990 ENVIRONMENTAL ACCIDENTS: PERSONAL INJURY AND PUBLIC RESPONSIBILITY Volume 3, Spring Issue, 1990 ENVIRONMENTAL ACCIDENTS: PERSONAL INJURY AND PUBLIC RESPONSIBILITY By Richard Gaskins.l Philadelphia: Temple University Press. 1989. Pp. ix, 350. $34.95. As it stands now,

More information

Factors About Advertising and Product Risk

Factors About Advertising and Product Risk MANDATORY VERSUS VOLUNTARY DISCLOSURE OF PRODUCT RISKS A. Mitchell Polinsky Steven Shavell WORKING PAPER 12776 NBER WORKING PAPER SERIES MANDATORY VERSUS VOLUNTARY DISCLOSURE OF PRODUCT RISKS A. Mitchell

More information

TOPIC IS IN THE ECONOMICS OF TORT LIABILITY (from COOTER, ULEN Introduction to Law and Economics 2000 (3rd ed))

TOPIC IS IN THE ECONOMICS OF TORT LIABILITY (from COOTER, ULEN Introduction to Law and Economics 2000 (3rd ed)) TOPIC IS IN THE ECONOMICS OF TORT LIABILITY (from COOTER, ULEN Introduction to Law and Economics 2000 (3rd ed)) Let us advance the understanding of the economic analysis of the tort-liability in two ways.

More information

The Plaintiff s Attorney in the Liability Insurance Claims Settlement Process: A Game Theoretic Approach

The Plaintiff s Attorney in the Liability Insurance Claims Settlement Process: A Game Theoretic Approach The Plaintiff s Attorney in the Liability Insurance Claims Settlement Process: A Game Theoretic Approach Lisa L. Posey * Abstract: The decision of a claimant to obtain legal counsel, the timing of this

More information

Competition and Fraud in Online Advertising Markets

Competition and Fraud in Online Advertising Markets Competition and Fraud in Online Advertising Markets Bob Mungamuru 1 and Stephen Weis 2 1 Stanford University, Stanford, CA, USA 94305 2 Google Inc., Mountain View, CA, USA 94043 Abstract. An economic model

More information

No-Betting Pareto Dominance

No-Betting Pareto Dominance No-Betting Pareto Dominance Itzhak Gilboa, Larry Samuelson and David Schmeidler HEC Paris/Tel Aviv Yale Interdisciplinary Center Herzlyia/Tel Aviv/Ohio State May, 2014 I. Introduction I.1 Trade Suppose

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 2: Strategic Form Games

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 2: Strategic Form Games 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 2: Strategic Form Games Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 4, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Decisions, utility maximization Strategic form games Best responses

More information

Sharing Online Advertising Revenue with Consumers

Sharing Online Advertising Revenue with Consumers Sharing Online Advertising Revenue with Consumers Yiling Chen 2,, Arpita Ghosh 1, Preston McAfee 1, and David Pennock 1 1 Yahoo! Research. Email: arpita, mcafee, pennockd@yahoo-inc.com 2 Harvard University.

More information

Economic Analysis of Medical Malpractice Liability and its Reform

Economic Analysis of Medical Malpractice Liability and its Reform NELLCO NELLCO Legal Scholarship Repository New York University Law and Economics Working Papers New York University School of Law 10-1-2013 Economic Analysis of Medical Malpractice Liability and its Reform

More information

CPC/CPA Hybrid Bidding in a Second Price Auction

CPC/CPA Hybrid Bidding in a Second Price Auction CPC/CPA Hybrid Bidding in a Second Price Auction Benjamin Edelman Hoan Soo Lee Working Paper 09-074 Copyright 2008 by Benjamin Edelman and Hoan Soo Lee Working papers are in draft form. This working paper

More information

Chapter 4 Crimes (Review)

Chapter 4 Crimes (Review) Chapter 4 Crimes (Review) On a separate sheet of paper, write down the answer to the following Q s; if you do not know the answer, write down the Q. 1. What is a crime? 2. There are elements of a crime.

More information

On the Efficiency of Competitive Stock Markets Where Traders Have Diverse Information

On the Efficiency of Competitive Stock Markets Where Traders Have Diverse Information Finance 400 A. Penati - G. Pennacchi Notes on On the Efficiency of Competitive Stock Markets Where Traders Have Diverse Information by Sanford Grossman This model shows how the heterogeneous information

More information

FACT PATTERN ONE. The following facts are based on the case of Bedard v. Martyn [2009] A.J. No. 308

FACT PATTERN ONE. The following facts are based on the case of Bedard v. Martyn [2009] A.J. No. 308 FACT PATTERN ONE The following facts are based on the case of Bedard v. Martyn [2009] A.J. No. 308 The infant plaintiff developed a large blood clot in his brain at some time either before or during the

More information

FIRE ON THE ICE: RECENT DEVELOPMENTS IN THE LAW OF NEGLIGENCE REGARDING CAUSATION

FIRE ON THE ICE: RECENT DEVELOPMENTS IN THE LAW OF NEGLIGENCE REGARDING CAUSATION Aaron L. Sherriff FIRE ON THE ICE: RECENT DEVELOPMENTS IN THE LAW OF NEGLIGENCE REGARDING CAUSATION 2 Aaron L. Sherriff TABLE OF CONTENTS I. THE CGL POLICY... 3 II. NEGLIGENCE... 3 III. MR. HANKE... 4

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 15: Repeated Games and Cooperation

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 15: Repeated Games and Cooperation 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 15: Repeated Games and Cooperation Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT November 2, 2009 1 Introduction Outline The problem of cooperation Finitely-repeated prisoner s dilemma

More information

Fault versus No Fault for Personal Injury

Fault versus No Fault for Personal Injury Fault versus No Fault for Personal Injury Reviewing the International Evidence Kirsten Armstrong & Daniel Tess PricewaterhouseCoopers Who Cares? Accident Comp insurance is General Insurance Very much a

More information

Hacking-proofness and Stability in a Model of Information Security Networks

Hacking-proofness and Stability in a Model of Information Security Networks Hacking-proofness and Stability in a Model of Information Security Networks Sunghoon Hong Preliminary draft, not for citation. March 1, 2008 Abstract We introduce a model of information security networks.

More information

Labor Economics, 14.661. Lecture 3: Education, Selection, and Signaling

Labor Economics, 14.661. Lecture 3: Education, Selection, and Signaling Labor Economics, 14.661. Lecture 3: Education, Selection, and Signaling Daron Acemoglu MIT November 3, 2011. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Education, Selection, and Signaling November 3, 2011. 1 / 31 Introduction

More information

Research Note: Assessing Household Service Losses with Joint Survival Probabilities

Research Note: Assessing Household Service Losses with Joint Survival Probabilities Research Note: Assessing Household Service Losses with Joint Survival Probabilities Victor A. Matheson and Robert A. Baade December 2006 COLLEGE OF THE HOLY CROSS, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS FACULTY RESEARCH

More information

What Is a Barrier to Entry?

What Is a Barrier to Entry? WHEN ARE SUNK COSTS BARRIERS TO ENTRY? ENTRY BARRIERS IN ECONOMIC AND ANTITRUST ANALYSIS What Is a Barrier to Entry? By R. PRESTON MCAFEE, HUGO M. MIALON, AND MICHAEL A. WILLIAMS* Discussants: Steve Berry,

More information

Rotterdam Institute of Law and Economics (RILE) Working Paper Series

Rotterdam Institute of Law and Economics (RILE) Working Paper Series ROTTERDAM INSTITUTE OF LAW AND ECONOMICS Rotterdam Institute of Law and Economics (RILE) Working Paper Series www.rile.nl No. 2008/03 Justifications and Excuses in the Economic Analysis of Tort Law Louis

More information

On Compulsory Per-Claim Deductibles in Automobile Insurance

On Compulsory Per-Claim Deductibles in Automobile Insurance The Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, 28: 25 32, 2003 c 2003 The Geneva Association On Compulsory Per-Claim Deductibles in Automobile Insurance CHU-SHIU LI Department of Economics, Feng Chia

More information

Legal Liability in Recreation Site Management. Legal Climate. Classification of Legal Liability RRT 484. Professor Ed Krumpe

Legal Liability in Recreation Site Management. Legal Climate. Classification of Legal Liability RRT 484. Professor Ed Krumpe Legal Liability in Recreation Site Management RRT 484 Professor Ed Krumpe 1 Legal Climate Sovereign immunity is basically dead. Lawsuits are part of normal operations & we cannot prevent them. Injuries

More information

Work incentives and household insurance: Sequential contracting with altruistic individuals and moral hazard

Work incentives and household insurance: Sequential contracting with altruistic individuals and moral hazard Work incentives and household insurance: Sequential contracting with altruistic individuals and moral hazard Cécile Aubert Abstract Two agents sequentially contracts with different principals under moral

More information

Defenses in a Product Liability Claim

Defenses in a Product Liability Claim Defenses in a Product Liability Claim written by: Mark Schultz, Esq. COZEN O CONNOR Suite 400, 200 Four Falls Corporate Center West Conshohocken, PA 19428 (800) 379-0695 (610) 941-5400 mschultz@cozen.com

More information

Strict liability and compensation

Strict liability and compensation Strict liability and compensation THEDANISH MODEL Denmark in figures (2011) Population: App. 5.5 million Number of MTPL insurers: 72 Potential drivers age 18 70: App. 37 3.7 million Number of motor vehicles:

More information

Published in Journal of Legal Economics, Volume 5, Number 2, Fall 1995 pp.57-65.

Published in Journal of Legal Economics, Volume 5, Number 2, Fall 1995 pp.57-65. Published in Journal of Legal Economics, Volume 5, Number 2, Fall 1995 pp.57-65. The Defense Economist s Role in Litigation Settlement Negotiations Lawrence M. Spizman Professor of Economics State University

More information

0.0.2 Pareto Efficiency (Sec. 4, Ch. 1 of text)

0.0.2 Pareto Efficiency (Sec. 4, Ch. 1 of text) September 2 Exercises: Problem 2 (p. 21) Efficiency: p. 28-29: 1, 4, 5, 6 0.0.2 Pareto Efficiency (Sec. 4, Ch. 1 of text) We discuss here a notion of efficiency that is rooted in the individual preferences

More information

Economic Analysis of Medical Malpractice Liability and its Reform

Economic Analysis of Medical Malpractice Liability and its Reform NELLCO NELLCO Legal Scholarship Repository New York University Public Law and Legal Theory Working Papers New York University School of Law 10-1-2013 Economic Analysis of Medical Malpractice Liability

More information

THE SWEDISH TRAFFIC DAMAGE ACT. A short introduction Warsaw 21 March 2011

THE SWEDISH TRAFFIC DAMAGE ACT. A short introduction Warsaw 21 March 2011 THE SWEDISH TRAFFIC DAMAGE ACT A short introduction Warsaw 21 March 2011 Some background facts Sweden's first motorist's liability act was introduced in 1906. In 1916 the law was made more stringent. It

More information

Vicarious liability of a charity or its trustees

Vicarious liability of a charity or its trustees 1 of 7 Guidance Vicarious liability of a charity or its trustees Contents In general, for what are trustees liable? Liability for the actions or omissions of others What does the law cover in this area?

More information

AUTOMOBILE INSURANCE: THE MINNESOTA NO-FAULT AUTOMOBILE INSURANCE LAW

AUTOMOBILE INSURANCE: THE MINNESOTA NO-FAULT AUTOMOBILE INSURANCE LAW This document is made available electronically by the Minnesota Legislative Reference Library as part of an ongoing digital archiving project. http://www.leg.state.mn.us/lrl/lrl.asp.~l' ''''d:.,j i.;'~\;

More information

The Minister of Transport hereby publishes the above draft Bill and the

The Minister of Transport hereby publishes the above draft Bill and the 2 No. 38173 GOVERNMENT GAZETTE, 3 NOVEMBER 2014 No. CONTENTS INHOUD Page No. Gazette No. GENERAL NOTICE Transport, Department of General Notice 950 Road Accident Fund Amendment Bill, 2014: Publication

More information

NEW DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NEGLIGENCE AND STRICT LIABILITY AND THEIR IMPLICATIONS ON MEDICAL MALPRACTICE REFORM

NEW DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NEGLIGENCE AND STRICT LIABILITY AND THEIR IMPLICATIONS ON MEDICAL MALPRACTICE REFORM NEW DIFFERENCES BETWEEN NEGLIGENCE AND STRICT LIABILITY AND THEIR IMPLICATIONS ON MEDICAL MALPRACTICE REFORM NOAM SHER* ABSTRACT This Article seeks to explore previously unexamined differences between

More information

WORKERS COMPENSATION SUBROGATION AND THIRD PARTY SETTLEMENTS. B. Industrial Revolution and Workers Compensation Statutes

WORKERS COMPENSATION SUBROGATION AND THIRD PARTY SETTLEMENTS. B. Industrial Revolution and Workers Compensation Statutes I. HISTORICAL BACKGROUND A. Common Law WORKERS COMPENSATION SUBROGATION AND THIRD PARTY SETTLEMENTS Before the advent of workers compensation statutes, the only protection afforded to victims of work place

More information

Accidental Death and the Rule of Joint and Several Liability

Accidental Death and the Rule of Joint and Several Liability Accidental Death and the Rule of Joint and Several Liability Daniel Carvell CNA Analysis and Solutions carvelld@cna.org Janet Currie Princeton University and NBER jcurrie@princeton.edu W. Bentley MacLeod

More information

Sharing Online Advertising Revenue with Consumers

Sharing Online Advertising Revenue with Consumers Sharing Online Advertising Revenue with Consumers Yiling Chen 2,, Arpita Ghosh 1, Preston McAfee 1, and David Pennock 1 1 Yahoo! Research. Email: arpita, mcafee, pennockd@yahoo-inc.com 2 Harvard University.

More information

When is Reputation Bad? 1

When is Reputation Bad? 1 When is Reputation Bad? 1 Jeffrey Ely Drew Fudenberg David K Levine 2 First Version: April 22, 2002 This Version: November 20, 2005 Abstract: In traditional reputation theory, the ability to build a reputation

More information

Persuasion by Cheap Talk - Online Appendix

Persuasion by Cheap Talk - Online Appendix Persuasion by Cheap Talk - Online Appendix By ARCHISHMAN CHAKRABORTY AND RICK HARBAUGH Online appendix to Persuasion by Cheap Talk, American Economic Review Our results in the main text concern the case

More information

Online Appendix Feedback Effects, Asymmetric Trading, and the Limits to Arbitrage

Online Appendix Feedback Effects, Asymmetric Trading, and the Limits to Arbitrage Online Appendix Feedback Effects, Asymmetric Trading, and the Limits to Arbitrage Alex Edmans LBS, NBER, CEPR, and ECGI Itay Goldstein Wharton Wei Jiang Columbia May 8, 05 A Proofs of Propositions and

More information

Mandatory Versus Voluntary Disclosure of Product Risks

Mandatory Versus Voluntary Disclosure of Product Risks 360 JLEO, V28 N2 Mandatory Versus Voluntary Disclosure of Product Risks A. Mitchell Polinsky* Stanford University Steven Shavell** Harvard University We analyze a model in which firms are able to acquire

More information

HOLD HARMLESS, INDEMNITY, SUBROGATION AND ADDITIONAL INSURED INSURANCE IN TRANSPORTATION CONTRACTS

HOLD HARMLESS, INDEMNITY, SUBROGATION AND ADDITIONAL INSURED INSURANCE IN TRANSPORTATION CONTRACTS HOLD HARMLESS, INDEMNITY, SUBROGATION AND ADDITIONAL INSURED INSURANCE IN TRANSPORTATION CONTRACTS By James W. Bryan Nexsen Pruet P.L.L.C. Greensboro, North Carolina 336-373-1600 jbryan@nexsenpruet.com

More information

But For Causation in Defective Drug and Toxic Exposure Cases: California s Form Jury Instruction CACI 430

But For Causation in Defective Drug and Toxic Exposure Cases: California s Form Jury Instruction CACI 430 But For Causation in Defective Drug and Toxic Exposure Cases: California s Form Jury Instruction CACI 430 By Matt Powers and Charles Lifland Since the California Supreme Court s 1991 decision in Mitchell

More information

Modeling Insurance Markets

Modeling Insurance Markets Modeling Insurance Markets Nathaniel Hendren Harvard April, 2015 Nathaniel Hendren (Harvard) Insurance April, 2015 1 / 29 Modeling Competition Insurance Markets is Tough There is no well-agreed upon model

More information

Chapter 11 Auto Insurance in the United States (continued)

Chapter 11 Auto Insurance in the United States (continued) Chapter 11 Auto Insurance in the United States (continued) Overview Compensating innocent motorists who have been injured in auto accidents is an important issue for society. Private insurers are not anxious

More information