Consistency of the Continuum Hypothesis

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Consistency of the Continuum Hypothesis"

Transcription

1 Consistency of the Continuum Hypothesis Bruce W. Rogers April 22, Introduction One of the basic results in set theory is that the cardinality of the power set of the natural numbers is the same as the cardinality of the real numbers, which is strictly greater than the cardinality of the naturals. In fact Cantor proved a more general theorem: for any set X, the cardinality of X is strictly less than the cardinality of the power set of X. Since there is an infinite set, say the naturals, each application of the power set gives a greater infinite number. For each infinite set X we assign a cardinal number ℵ X. It is equivalent to the Axiom of Choice that every set of alephs is linearly ordered. In fact, every set of cardinals is well ordered, so we can index the alephs with ordinals, α, β, in such a way that α < β iff ℵ α < ℵ β. The problem is that we don t know which cardinals go where in the ordering. We know that countably infinite sets have the smallest infinite cardinal, ℵ 0, and we know ℵ 0 is less than 2 ℵ 0, but we don t know if there are any cardinals between. Cantor could not find any sets whose cardinalities were greater than ℵ 0 but less than 2 ℵ 0, so Cantor hypothesized that 2 ℵ 0 is actually the next cardinal after ℵ 0, i.e. 2 ℵ 0 = ℵ 1. This statement is known as the Continuum Hypothesis [CH] since one can prove that 2 ℵ 0 is the cardinality of the continuum of real numbers, R. Equivalently, CH says that every uncountable set of real numbers has cardinality 2 ℵ 0. Proving CH would mean that mathematicians have a very good handle on the ordering of the cardinals, so much effort was spent trying to prove CH from the axioms of set theory. As it turns out, however, CH cannot be proven true or false from the Zermelo-Fraenkel [ZF] axioms of set theory. In other words, ZF cannot imply CH, and ZF cannot imply the negation of CH (if ZF is consistent to start with). Thus we say CH is independent of ZF in 1

2 the former case, and CH is consistent with ZF in the latter. Another way to think about consistency is that assuming CH along with the other axioms of ZF will not introduce a contradiction. The notions of consistency and independence also appear outside of set theory. In fact, for any sufficiently strong (and consistent) axiomatic system there must be a proposition, say P, such that neither P nor the negation of P is provable in the system. This follows from Gödel s incompleteness theorem. The most famous example of such a proposition is Euclid s Parallel Postulate. The Greeks did not think the Parallel Postulate was self-evident, so they attempted to prove it using the other axioms of geometry. This is impossible since the Parallel Postulate is independent from those axioms. In fact, the negation of the Parallel Postulate produces interesting noncontradictory geometries, which shows that the Parallel Postulate is independent. Consistency of the Parallel Postulate follows from the lack of contradictions in Euclidean plane geometry. In this paper we will show the consistency of CH with ZF. This proof was first given by Gödel, and our proof follows his loosely. Before we start, the term consistent needs to be defined a little more precisely. We do this by introducing the notion of model. 2 Models and the Axiom of Constructibility Definition. Let M be a set and ϕ(v 1,..., v n ) be a formula. Let x 1,..., x n M. Then we write M = ϕ(x 1,..., x n ) (read M models ϕ or M satisfies ϕ) according to the following inductive definition: (1) if ϕ is of the form v i v j, then M = ϕ if it is actually the case that x i x j ; (2) M = ϕ if it is not true that M = ϕ; (3) M = ϕ ψ if both M = ϕ and M = ψ; (4) M = v i (ϕ) if there exists ˆx M such that M = ϕ(x 1,..., ˆx,..., x n ). Basically, M = ϕ means we would think ϕ were true if M were the universe of all sets. We say M is a model for ZF if M satisfies every axiom of ZF. Now if there is a model for ZF in which CH is true, then CH is consistent with ZF. The rest of this section deals with defining such a model. Definition. The cumulative hierarchy of sets (V α ) is defined for all ordinals α by V 0 =, V α+1 = (V α ), and V β = α<βv α for limit ordinals β. 2

3 Since the V α s are built up by taking power sets, it is fairly clear that in every V α, x y V α implies x V α, i.e. V α is transitive. Also, if α < β, V α is a proper subset of V β. It is also true that every set lives inside of some V α. This result is not intuitively obvious, so we will take the time to prove it. Propostion. Every set is a member of V α for some ordinal α. Proof: Suppose X is a set not in the cumulative hierarchy, and let Y be the transitive closure of X, i.e., Y = X n where X 0 = X and X n+1 = X n. Then Y is the smallest transitive set containing X. We claim there is a set Z that is not in the cumulative hierarchy, but all the elements of Z are. Since X Y, Y V α for any α by the transitivity of V α. Let S = {y Y y V α for all α}. If S =, then Y has the claimed property. If S, then it has an ɛ minimal element, Y 0, by the axiom of regularity. Since Y is transitive, we can let Z = Y 0. Now, for each x Z let α x be the smallest ordinal so that x V αx. Then let β = x Zα x. It follows that Z V β, hence Z V β+1, a contradiction. So we can (roughly) think of the union of all the V α s as the universe of sets. However, there are a couple of problems with this notion. First, we don t know how high the ordinals go, so we cannot take the union of every V α. Second, to make new sets we take the power sets of previous sets. This seems simple enough, but we don t have a specific mechanism to form all the subsets of a arbitrary set. One solution to the latter problem is to define the Gödel constructible hierarchy, in which we will give give definite methods for constructing sets. One way to think about the constructible hierarchy (roughly) is that is consists of those sets which we can build from logical and set theoretic notation with certain restrictions. To be a little more precise, there are ten Gödel operations on sets X and Y which we will use to define the constructible hierarchy. These are F 1 (X, Y ) = {X, Y } F 2 (X, Y ) = X Y F 3 (X, Y ) = ɛ(x, Y ) = {[x, y] X Y x y} F 4 (X, Y ) = X Y F 5 (X, Y ) = X Y F 6 (X, Y ) = X = {x y X where x y} F 7 (X, Y ) = π(x) = {x y([x, y] X} F 8 (X, Y ) = {[x, y] [y, x] X} F 9 (X, Y ) = {[x, y, z] [x, z, y] X} F 1 0(X, Y ) = {[x, y, z] [y, z, x] X} 3

4 Now for any set X the Gödel closure of X, denoted cl(x), is the smallest set which contains X and is closed under the Gödel operations. So to get cl(x) we take all the elements of X and apply all the Gödel operations, and then repeat. That is, if we define G(X) = {F i (x, y) x, y X and 1 i 10} X then cl(x) = G(X) G 2 (X) G 3 (X)... Next we use cl(x) to define another construction on a set X. Definition. For any set X, the set def(x) = cl(x {X}) (X) is called the set of logically definable subsets of X. Thus, def(x) consists of precisely those subsets of X which can be constructed from elements of X, along with X itself, in a finite number of steps using the Gödel operations. From the following lemma and theorem we see that def(x) is called the collection of logically definable sets for good reason. Note that a restricted formula is a logical formula whose quantifiers are all restricted, e.g. ( x y)(φ) is restricted but x(φ) is not. Also, we take φ(v 1,..., v n ) to mean v 1,..., v n are the variables of φ, none of which occur both free and bound. Lemma. Let ϕ be a restricted formula of n variables and let n 1. Then there is a function F of n variables such that F is a composition of Gödel operations and for any sets X 1,..., X n we have F (X 1,..., X n ) = {[x 1,..., x n ] X 1... X n ϕ(x 1,..., x n )}. Theorem. Let X be a transitive set. Then def(x) consists of precisely those subsets Y X such that for some formula ψ and some elements x 1,..., x n X we have Y = {x X ψ(x, x 1,..., x n )}. The proof of the lemma is an induction on the complexity of ϕ, where one formula is more complex than another if it has more quantifiers. For formulas with the same number of quantifiers, complexity is decided by length. Then, the theorem is a fairly immediate consequence. The main idea is that each element in def(x) is constructed in a finite number of steps using Gödel operations. We are finally ready to define the constructible hierarchy, L α. Definition. The constructible hierarchy, L α, is defined inductively for all ordinals α. Let L 0 =, L α+1 = def(l α ), and L β = α<βl α for limit ordinals β. There are a few interesting things we can say about L α. First, like V α, every L α is transitive and if α < β, then L α is a proper subset of L β. Also if X is a 4

5 finite transitive set, def(x) = (X) so that L α = V α for all α ω. However, L α is a proper subset of V α for every ordinal α > ω. In fact, we have that L α = α for every infinite ordinal α. Proposition. L α = α for every infinite ordinal α. At this point we may wonder if we get all the sets in the constructible hierarchy as we do in the cumulative hierarchy. The assumption that we do, that is if X is a set, then X L α for some α, is called the Axiom of Constructibility. Axiom of Constructibility. V = L V = L seems harmless enough since no one knows of a set that is not constuctible. However, since there is no proof that every set is in L, most set theorists are wary of V = L. Also, V = L implies both the Axiom of Choice and CH, so if L were a model for ZF, the Axiom of Choice and CH are consistent with ZF (and L also models ZFC). Fact. L = α OrdL α models ZF. The remainder of this paper will show how V = L implies CH. 3 Preliminary Results The basic idea now is to show that every constructible subset of ω belongs to L Ω, where Ω is the first uncountable ordinal. Assuming V = L we then have (ω) L Ω, and from above L Ω = Ω = ℵ 1 (Note: We define the cardinal number of a set as the least ordinal which can be mapped bijectively to the set. Thus Ω = ℵ 1, the first uncountable cardinal.) If X is a constructible subset of ω, we will show it is in L Ω by constructing a set M which models X L Ω while at the same time making sure what M models is really true. This will require some powerful tools: absoluteness, adequacy, and reflection. Absoluteness is what will ultimately insure the set M we construct will model true things, i.e. M = ϕ implies ϕ. Definition. Let M be a transitive set and ϕ(x 1,..., x n ) be a formula. We say ϕ is absolute for M if M = ϕ(x 1,..., x n ) if and only if ϕ(x 1,..., x n ) for all x 1,..., x n M. Lemma. Every restricted formula is absolute. 5

6 Proof: Let ϕ(v 1,..., v n ) be a restricted formula, M a transitive set, and x 1,..., x n M. If ϕ is atomic, a negation, or a conjunction, it is clear from the definition of = that ϕ is absolute. So suppose ϕ is of the form ( v i v j )(ψ). Then M = ϕ iff there exists x i M such that M = (x i x j ) and M = ψ(x 1,..., x n ). By transitivity, this is equivalent to saying there exists x i x j such that M = ψ(x 1,..., x n ). By induction, the last condition holds iff ψ(x 1,..., x n ) is actually true, so the whole thing is equivalent to the truth of ϕ. Hence, M = ϕ iff ϕ. The following expressions are absolute since they are defined by restricted formulas: x y, x =, x is transitive, x is an ordinal, x = ω, z = F i (x, y) for 1 i 10. Unfortunately, the expression x = L α is not absolute, so we define adequacy to get around that problem. Definition. Let φ be the expression (1) for all x and y and 1 i 10 there exists z such that z = F i (x, y); (2) for all x there exists a set y which equals cl(x); and (3) for every ordinal α there exists a family {L β β < α} such that L 0 =, L β+1 = def(l β ), and L β = γ<βl γ for limit ordinals β. We call a set M adequate if M = φ. Gödel devised adequacy to be a condition under which x = L α acts like it is absolute, so the following result is not surprising. Lemma. If M is transitive and adequate, then for every ordinal α M, M = (x = L α ) implies that x = L α. So now we have some conditions on a set M which guarantees the truth of any formula modeled by M. Next we address which sets can model various formulas. Specifically, we will have a version of the Löwenheim-Skolem theorem called the reflection principle. The reflection principle states that if ϕ if satisfied by a countable set, then there is a nice countable set which models ϕ. While the set is nice, it is not transitive. Definition. A set M is called extensional if for any distinct x, y M there is z M which belongs to one or the other of x and y, but not both. In other words, if x, y M and x y, then M = (x y). Lemma. (Reflection Principle) Let M 0 be a countable set and let ϕ(v 1,..., v 2 ) be any formula. Suppose ϕ(x 1,..., x n ) is true for some x 1,..., x n M 0. Then there is a countable set M such that M 0 M; M is extensional; and M = ϕ(x 1,..., x n ). 6

7 We are almost ready to construct the desired set M. The last speed bump is that the reflection principle provides extensional sets, but for absoluteness we need a transitive set. This problem is taken care of in the next theorem, known as Mostowski s collapsing theoem. Theorem. Let M be an extensional set. Then there is a transitive set N which is isomorphic to M. That is, there is a bijection f : M N such that x y iff f(x) f(y). For any formula ϕ(v 1,..., v n ) and any x 1,..., x n M, we have M = ϕ(x 1,..., x n ) iff N = ϕ(f(x 1 ),..., f(x n )). Proof: We will define f by transfinite induction and let N be the range of f (so f is onto). By the Axiom of Regularity, there is a ɛ-minimal element, x, of M; since M is extensional, x is unique. Define f(x) =. For any y M, we may inductively assume that f is defined on every element of y which belongs to M. Then define f(y) = {f(z) z y M}. Suppose f is not one-to-one. Then the set S = {z M z = f(x) = f(y) for some x y} is nonempty and hence contains a minimal element z = f(x) = f(y) such that x y. Since M is extensional, without loss of generality, we may assume that there is w M so that w x y. Thus, f(w) f(x) = z, and by minimality of z it is not the case that f(w) = f(v) for any other v M. Then f(w) f(y), therefore, f(x) f(y), a contradiction. So f is bijective. Clearly, x y implies f(x) f(y). So suppose f(x) f(y). Then by the definition of f(y), f(x) = f(z) for some z y. Since f is one-to-one, x = z y. So f is an isomorphism onto N = f[m]. The fact that f preserves the satisfaction of formulas is a routine induction on the length of the formula. We can now put all the pieces together and show that V = L implies CH. 4 Consistency of CH Theorem Assume V = L. Then 2 ℵ 0 = ℵ 1. Proof: Let X ω. We claim that X L Ω. Once we show the claim we are done, since we will have (ω) L Ω. Then ℵ 0 < (ω) = 2 ℵ 0 L Ω = Ω = ℵ 1. So now we prove the claim. Since V = L, for some α we have X L α. By the reflection principle we can find a countable set M such that 7

8 (1) M is extensional; (2) ω M, X M, and α M; (3) M is adequate; and (4) M = (α is an ordinal and X L α ). By Mostowski collapse there exists an isomorphism f : M N where N is transitive. Since ω M, an easy induction shows that f(n) = n for all n ω. It also follows from the definition of f in the previous thereom that f(x) = X. Also, by (4), N = (α is an ordinal), hence by absoluteness β = f(α) actually is an ordinal. By (3), N is adequate, and by (4) N = (X = f(x) L f(α) = L β ). Thus, X L β. Now, β N and N is transitive and countable, so β is countable. Hence, X L β L Ω. By transitivity, X L Ω. References [Co] Cohen, P. Set Theory and the Continuum. The Benjamin/Cummings Publishing Company, London, (1966). [Gö] Gödel, K. The Consistency of the Continuum Hypothesis. Princeton University Press, Princeton, (1940). [Je] Jech, T. Set Theory. Academic Press, New York, (1978). [We] Weaver, N. Lecture notes in Set Theory. (1996?). 8

This asserts two sets are equal iff they have the same elements, that is, a set is determined by its elements.

This asserts two sets are equal iff they have the same elements, that is, a set is determined by its elements. 3. Axioms of Set theory Before presenting the axioms of set theory, we first make a few basic comments about the relevant first order logic. We will give a somewhat more detailed discussion later, but

More information

INTRODUCTORY SET THEORY

INTRODUCTORY SET THEORY M.Sc. program in mathematics INTRODUCTORY SET THEORY Katalin Károlyi Department of Applied Analysis, Eötvös Loránd University H-1088 Budapest, Múzeum krt. 6-8. CONTENTS 1. SETS Set, equal sets, subset,

More information

MODELS OF SET THEORY

MODELS OF SET THEORY MODELS OF SET THEORY STEFAN GESCHKE Contents 1. First order logic and the axioms of set theory 2 1.1. Syntax 2 1.2. Semantics 2 1.3. Completeness, compactness and consistency 3 1.4. Foundations of mathematics

More information

AN INTRODUCTION TO SET THEORY. Professor William A. R. Weiss

AN INTRODUCTION TO SET THEORY. Professor William A. R. Weiss AN INTRODUCTION TO SET THEORY Professor William A. R. Weiss October 2, 2008 2 Contents 0 Introduction 7 1 LOST 11 2 FOUND 19 3 The Axioms of Set Theory 23 4 The Natural Numbers 31 5 The Ordinal Numbers

More information

Handout #1: Mathematical Reasoning

Handout #1: Mathematical Reasoning Math 101 Rumbos Spring 2010 1 Handout #1: Mathematical Reasoning 1 Propositional Logic A proposition is a mathematical statement that it is either true or false; that is, a statement whose certainty or

More information

This chapter is all about cardinality of sets. At first this looks like a

This chapter is all about cardinality of sets. At first this looks like a CHAPTER Cardinality of Sets This chapter is all about cardinality of sets At first this looks like a very simple concept To find the cardinality of a set, just count its elements If A = { a, b, c, d },

More information

Cardinality. The set of all finite strings over the alphabet of lowercase letters is countable. The set of real numbers R is an uncountable set.

Cardinality. The set of all finite strings over the alphabet of lowercase letters is countable. The set of real numbers R is an uncountable set. Section 2.5 Cardinality (another) Definition: The cardinality of a set A is equal to the cardinality of a set B, denoted A = B, if and only if there is a bijection from A to B. If there is an injection

More information

Set theory as a foundation for mathematics

Set theory as a foundation for mathematics V I I I : Set theory as a foundation for mathematics This material is basically supplementary, and it was not covered in the course. In the first section we discuss the basic axioms of set theory and the

More information

3. Mathematical Induction

3. Mathematical Induction 3. MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION 83 3. Mathematical Induction 3.1. First Principle of Mathematical Induction. Let P (n) be a predicate with domain of discourse (over) the natural numbers N = {0, 1,,...}. If (1)

More information

God created the integers and the rest is the work of man. (Leopold Kronecker, in an after-dinner speech at a conference, Berlin, 1886)

God created the integers and the rest is the work of man. (Leopold Kronecker, in an after-dinner speech at a conference, Berlin, 1886) Chapter 2 Numbers God created the integers and the rest is the work of man. (Leopold Kronecker, in an after-dinner speech at a conference, Berlin, 1886) God created the integers and the rest is the work

More information

Finite dimensional topological vector spaces

Finite dimensional topological vector spaces Chapter 3 Finite dimensional topological vector spaces 3.1 Finite dimensional Hausdorff t.v.s. Let X be a vector space over the field K of real or complex numbers. We know from linear algebra that the

More information

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 2

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 2 CS 70 Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 2 Proofs Intuitively, the concept of proof should already be familiar We all like to assert things, and few of us

More information

CHAPTER 3. Methods of Proofs. 1. Logical Arguments and Formal Proofs

CHAPTER 3. Methods of Proofs. 1. Logical Arguments and Formal Proofs CHAPTER 3 Methods of Proofs 1. Logical Arguments and Formal Proofs 1.1. Basic Terminology. An axiom is a statement that is given to be true. A rule of inference is a logical rule that is used to deduce

More information

Basic Concepts of Point Set Topology Notes for OU course Math 4853 Spring 2011

Basic Concepts of Point Set Topology Notes for OU course Math 4853 Spring 2011 Basic Concepts of Point Set Topology Notes for OU course Math 4853 Spring 2011 A. Miller 1. Introduction. The definitions of metric space and topological space were developed in the early 1900 s, largely

More information

Georg Cantor (1845-1918):

Georg Cantor (1845-1918): Georg Cantor (845-98): The man who tamed infinity lecture by Eric Schechter Associate Professor of Mathematics Vanderbilt University http://www.math.vanderbilt.edu/ schectex/ In papers of 873 and 874,

More information

MA651 Topology. Lecture 6. Separation Axioms.

MA651 Topology. Lecture 6. Separation Axioms. MA651 Topology. Lecture 6. Separation Axioms. This text is based on the following books: Fundamental concepts of topology by Peter O Neil Elements of Mathematics: General Topology by Nicolas Bourbaki Counterexamples

More information

CS 3719 (Theory of Computation and Algorithms) Lecture 4

CS 3719 (Theory of Computation and Algorithms) Lecture 4 CS 3719 (Theory of Computation and Algorithms) Lecture 4 Antonina Kolokolova January 18, 2012 1 Undecidable languages 1.1 Church-Turing thesis Let s recap how it all started. In 1990, Hilbert stated a

More information

The Prime Numbers. Definition. A prime number is a positive integer with exactly two positive divisors.

The Prime Numbers. Definition. A prime number is a positive integer with exactly two positive divisors. The Prime Numbers Before starting our study of primes, we record the following important lemma. Recall that integers a, b are said to be relatively prime if gcd(a, b) = 1. Lemma (Euclid s Lemma). If gcd(a,

More information

COFINAL MAXIMAL CHAINS IN THE TURING DEGREES

COFINAL MAXIMAL CHAINS IN THE TURING DEGREES COFINA MAXIMA CHAINS IN THE TURING DEGREES WEI WANG, IUZHEN WU, AND IANG YU Abstract. Assuming ZF C, we prove that CH holds if and only if there exists a cofinal maximal chain of order type ω 1 in the

More information

The Foundations of Mathematics

The Foundations of Mathematics The Foundations of Mathematics c 2005,2006,2007 Kenneth Kunen Kenneth Kunen October 29, 2007 Contents 0 Introduction 3 0.1 Prerequisites.................................. 3 0.2 Logical Notation...............................

More information

INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY

INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY MATH 410, CSUSM. SPRING 2008. PROFESSOR AITKEN This document covers the geometry that can be developed with just the axioms related to incidence and betweenness. The full

More information

WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT?

WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT? WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT? introduction Many students seem to have trouble with the notion of a mathematical proof. People that come to a course like Math 216, who certainly

More information

Cartesian Products and Relations

Cartesian Products and Relations Cartesian Products and Relations Definition (Cartesian product) If A and B are sets, the Cartesian product of A and B is the set A B = {(a, b) :(a A) and (b B)}. The following points are worth special

More information

Metric Spaces Joseph Muscat 2003 (Last revised May 2009)

Metric Spaces Joseph Muscat 2003 (Last revised May 2009) 1 Distance J Muscat 1 Metric Spaces Joseph Muscat 2003 (Last revised May 2009) (A revised and expanded version of these notes are now published by Springer.) 1 Distance A metric space can be thought of

More information

No: 10 04. Bilkent University. Monotonic Extension. Farhad Husseinov. Discussion Papers. Department of Economics

No: 10 04. Bilkent University. Monotonic Extension. Farhad Husseinov. Discussion Papers. Department of Economics No: 10 04 Bilkent University Monotonic Extension Farhad Husseinov Discussion Papers Department of Economics The Discussion Papers of the Department of Economics are intended to make the initial results

More information

BANACH AND HILBERT SPACE REVIEW

BANACH AND HILBERT SPACE REVIEW BANACH AND HILBET SPACE EVIEW CHISTOPHE HEIL These notes will briefly review some basic concepts related to the theory of Banach and Hilbert spaces. We are not trying to give a complete development, but

More information

CHAPTER 7 GENERAL PROOF SYSTEMS

CHAPTER 7 GENERAL PROOF SYSTEMS CHAPTER 7 GENERAL PROOF SYSTEMS 1 Introduction Proof systems are built to prove statements. They can be thought as an inference machine with special statements, called provable statements, or sometimes

More information

5. Linear algebra I: dimension

5. Linear algebra I: dimension 5. Linear algebra I: dimension 5.1 Some simple results 5.2 Bases and dimension 5.3 Homomorphisms and dimension 1. Some simple results Several observations should be made. Once stated explicitly, the proofs

More information

1 if 1 x 0 1 if 0 x 1

1 if 1 x 0 1 if 0 x 1 Chapter 3 Continuity In this chapter we begin by defining the fundamental notion of continuity for real valued functions of a single real variable. When trying to decide whether a given function is or

More information

MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 6.436J/15.085J Fall 2008 Lecture 5 9/17/2008 RANDOM VARIABLES

MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 6.436J/15.085J Fall 2008 Lecture 5 9/17/2008 RANDOM VARIABLES MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 6.436J/15.085J Fall 2008 Lecture 5 9/17/2008 RANDOM VARIABLES Contents 1. Random variables and measurable functions 2. Cumulative distribution functions 3. Discrete

More information

I. GROUPS: BASIC DEFINITIONS AND EXAMPLES

I. GROUPS: BASIC DEFINITIONS AND EXAMPLES I GROUPS: BASIC DEFINITIONS AND EXAMPLES Definition 1: An operation on a set G is a function : G G G Definition 2: A group is a set G which is equipped with an operation and a special element e G, called

More information

(LMCS, p. 317) V.1. First Order Logic. This is the most powerful, most expressive logic that we will examine.

(LMCS, p. 317) V.1. First Order Logic. This is the most powerful, most expressive logic that we will examine. (LMCS, p. 317) V.1 First Order Logic This is the most powerful, most expressive logic that we will examine. Our version of first-order logic will use the following symbols: variables connectives (,,,,

More information

Georg Cantor and Set Theory

Georg Cantor and Set Theory Georg Cantor and Set Theory. Life Father, Georg Waldemar Cantor, born in Denmark, successful merchant, and stock broker in St Petersburg. Mother, Maria Anna Böhm, was Russian. In 856, because of father

More information

Mathematics for Computer Science/Software Engineering. Notes for the course MSM1F3 Dr. R. A. Wilson

Mathematics for Computer Science/Software Engineering. Notes for the course MSM1F3 Dr. R. A. Wilson Mathematics for Computer Science/Software Engineering Notes for the course MSM1F3 Dr. R. A. Wilson October 1996 Chapter 1 Logic Lecture no. 1. We introduce the concept of a proposition, which is a statement

More information

1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set.

1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set. 1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set. Basic Topology Written by Men-Gen Tsai email: b89902089@ntu.edu.tw Proof: For any element x of the empty set, x is also an element of every set since

More information

How many numbers there are?

How many numbers there are? How many numbers there are? RADEK HONZIK Radek Honzik: Charles University, Department of Logic, Celetná 20, Praha 1, 116 42, Czech Republic radek.honzik@ff.cuni.cz Contents 1 What are numbers 2 1.1 Natural

More information

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces Dan Collins The textbook defines a subspace of a vector space in Chapter 4, but it avoids ever discussing the notion of a quotient space. This is understandable

More information

Radboud Universiteit Nijmegen

Radboud Universiteit Nijmegen Radboud Universiteit Nijmegen Faculteit der Natuurwetenschappen, Wiskunde en Informatica Uniqueness of the Hyperreal Field Noud Aldenhoven (0620874) Supervisor: dr. W.H.M. Veldman Second reader: prof.

More information

Lemma 5.2. Let S be a set. (1) Let f and g be two permutations of S. Then the composition of f and g is a permutation of S.

Lemma 5.2. Let S be a set. (1) Let f and g be two permutations of S. Then the composition of f and g is a permutation of S. Definition 51 Let S be a set bijection f : S S 5 Permutation groups A permutation of S is simply a Lemma 52 Let S be a set (1) Let f and g be two permutations of S Then the composition of f and g is a

More information

Introduction to Topology

Introduction to Topology Introduction to Topology Tomoo Matsumura November 30, 2010 Contents 1 Topological spaces 3 1.1 Basis of a Topology......................................... 3 1.2 Comparing Topologies.......................................

More information

THE TURING DEGREES AND THEIR LACK OF LINEAR ORDER

THE TURING DEGREES AND THEIR LACK OF LINEAR ORDER THE TURING DEGREES AND THEIR LACK OF LINEAR ORDER JASPER DEANTONIO Abstract. This paper is a study of the Turing Degrees, which are levels of incomputability naturally arising from sets of natural numbers.

More information

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send email to: permissions@pupress.princeton.edu

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send email to: permissions@pupress.princeton.edu COPYRIGHT NOTICE: Ariel Rubinstein: Lecture Notes in Microeconomic Theory is published by Princeton University Press and copyrighted, c 2006, by Princeton University Press. All rights reserved. No part

More information

CS 103X: Discrete Structures Homework Assignment 3 Solutions

CS 103X: Discrete Structures Homework Assignment 3 Solutions CS 103X: Discrete Structures Homework Assignment 3 s Exercise 1 (20 points). On well-ordering and induction: (a) Prove the induction principle from the well-ordering principle. (b) Prove the well-ordering

More information

(a) Write each of p and q as a polynomial in x with coefficients in Z[y, z]. deg(p) = 7 deg(q) = 9

(a) Write each of p and q as a polynomial in x with coefficients in Z[y, z]. deg(p) = 7 deg(q) = 9 Homework #01, due 1/20/10 = 9.1.2, 9.1.4, 9.1.6, 9.1.8, 9.2.3 Additional problems for study: 9.1.1, 9.1.3, 9.1.5, 9.1.13, 9.2.1, 9.2.2, 9.2.4, 9.2.5, 9.2.6, 9.3.2, 9.3.3 9.1.1 (This problem was not assigned

More information

Linear Algebra. A vector space (over R) is an ordered quadruple. such that V is a set; 0 V ; and the following eight axioms hold:

Linear Algebra. A vector space (over R) is an ordered quadruple. such that V is a set; 0 V ; and the following eight axioms hold: Linear Algebra A vector space (over R) is an ordered quadruple (V, 0, α, µ) such that V is a set; 0 V ; and the following eight axioms hold: α : V V V and µ : R V V ; (i) α(α(u, v), w) = α(u, α(v, w)),

More information

Mathematical Induction

Mathematical Induction Mathematical Induction (Handout March 8, 01) The Principle of Mathematical Induction provides a means to prove infinitely many statements all at once The principle is logical rather than strictly mathematical,

More information

Practice with Proofs

Practice with Proofs Practice with Proofs October 6, 2014 Recall the following Definition 0.1. A function f is increasing if for every x, y in the domain of f, x < y = f(x) < f(y) 1. Prove that h(x) = x 3 is increasing, using

More information

DEFINABLE TYPES IN PRESBURGER ARITHMETIC

DEFINABLE TYPES IN PRESBURGER ARITHMETIC DEFINABLE TYPES IN PRESBURGER ARITHMETIC GABRIEL CONANT Abstract. We consider the first order theory of (Z, +,

More information

6.2 Permutations continued

6.2 Permutations continued 6.2 Permutations continued Theorem A permutation on a finite set A is either a cycle or can be expressed as a product (composition of disjoint cycles. Proof is by (strong induction on the number, r, of

More information

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 3. Spaces with special properties

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 3. Spaces with special properties SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR MATHEMATICS 205A Part 3 Fall 2008 III. Spaces with special properties III.1 : Compact spaces I Problems from Munkres, 26, pp. 170 172 3. Show that a finite union of compact subspaces

More information

THE BANACH CONTRACTION PRINCIPLE. Contents

THE BANACH CONTRACTION PRINCIPLE. Contents THE BANACH CONTRACTION PRINCIPLE ALEX PONIECKI Abstract. This paper will study contractions of metric spaces. To do this, we will mainly use tools from topology. We will give some examples of contractions,

More information

x < y iff x < y, or x and y are incomparable and x χ(x,y) < y χ(x,y).

x < y iff x < y, or x and y are incomparable and x χ(x,y) < y χ(x,y). 12. Large cardinals The study, or use, of large cardinals is one of the most active areas of research in set theory currently. There are many provably different kinds of large cardinals whose descriptions

More information

The Banach-Tarski Paradox

The Banach-Tarski Paradox University of Oslo MAT2 Project The Banach-Tarski Paradox Author: Fredrik Meyer Supervisor: Nadia S. Larsen Abstract In its weak form, the Banach-Tarski paradox states that for any ball in R, it is possible

More information

Notes on Complexity Theory Last updated: August, 2011. Lecture 1

Notes on Complexity Theory Last updated: August, 2011. Lecture 1 Notes on Complexity Theory Last updated: August, 2011 Jonathan Katz Lecture 1 1 Turing Machines I assume that most students have encountered Turing machines before. (Students who have not may want to look

More information

Mathematical Induction

Mathematical Induction Mathematical Induction In logic, we often want to prove that every member of an infinite set has some feature. E.g., we would like to show: N 1 : is a number 1 : has the feature Φ ( x)(n 1 x! 1 x) How

More information

CODING TRUE ARITHMETIC IN THE MEDVEDEV AND MUCHNIK DEGREES

CODING TRUE ARITHMETIC IN THE MEDVEDEV AND MUCHNIK DEGREES CODING TRUE ARITHMETIC IN THE MEDVEDEV AND MUCHNIK DEGREES PAUL SHAFER Abstract. We prove that the first-order theory of the Medvedev degrees, the first-order theory of the Muchnik degrees, and the third-order

More information

Fundamentele Informatica II

Fundamentele Informatica II Fundamentele Informatica II Answer to selected exercises 1 John C Martin: Introduction to Languages and the Theory of Computation M.M. Bonsangue (and J. Kleijn) Fall 2011 Let L be a language. It is clear

More information

ON SEQUENTIAL CONTINUITY OF COMPOSITION MAPPING. 0. Introduction

ON SEQUENTIAL CONTINUITY OF COMPOSITION MAPPING. 0. Introduction ON SEQUENTIAL CONTINUITY OF COMPOSITION MAPPING Abstract. In [1] there was proved a theorem concerning the continuity of the composition mapping, and there was announced a theorem on sequential continuity

More information

Undergraduate Notes in Mathematics. Arkansas Tech University Department of Mathematics

Undergraduate Notes in Mathematics. Arkansas Tech University Department of Mathematics Undergraduate Notes in Mathematics Arkansas Tech University Department of Mathematics An Introductory Single Variable Real Analysis: A Learning Approach through Problem Solving Marcel B. Finan c All Rights

More information

MATH10040 Chapter 2: Prime and relatively prime numbers

MATH10040 Chapter 2: Prime and relatively prime numbers MATH10040 Chapter 2: Prime and relatively prime numbers Recall the basic definition: 1. Prime numbers Definition 1.1. Recall that a positive integer is said to be prime if it has precisely two positive

More information

FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: QUOTIENT SPACES

FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: QUOTIENT SPACES FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: QUOTIENT SPACES CHRISTOPHER HEIL 1. Cosets and the Quotient Space Any vector space is an abelian group under the operation of vector addition. So, if you are have studied

More information

Mathematical Induction. Mary Barnes Sue Gordon

Mathematical Induction. Mary Barnes Sue Gordon Mathematics Learning Centre Mathematical Induction Mary Barnes Sue Gordon c 1987 University of Sydney Contents 1 Mathematical Induction 1 1.1 Why do we need proof by induction?.... 1 1. What is proof by

More information

GENTLY KILLING S SPACES TODD EISWORTH, PETER NYIKOS, AND SAHARON SHELAH

GENTLY KILLING S SPACES TODD EISWORTH, PETER NYIKOS, AND SAHARON SHELAH GENTLY KILLING S SPACES TODD EISWORTH, PETER NYIKOS, AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We produce a model of ZFC in which there are no locally compact first countable S spaces, and in which 2 ℵ 0 < 2 ℵ 1. A

More information

On strong fairness in UNITY

On strong fairness in UNITY On strong fairness in UNITY H.P.Gumm, D.Zhukov Fachbereich Mathematik und Informatik Philipps Universität Marburg {gumm,shukov}@mathematik.uni-marburg.de Abstract. In [6] Tsay and Bagrodia present a correct

More information

THE SEARCH FOR NATURAL DEFINABILITY IN THE TURING DEGREES

THE SEARCH FOR NATURAL DEFINABILITY IN THE TURING DEGREES THE SEARCH FOR NATURAL DEFINABILITY IN THE TURING DEGREES ANDREW E.M. LEWIS 1. Introduction This will be a course on the Turing degrees. We shall assume very little background knowledge: familiarity with

More information

A Beginner s Guide to Modern Set Theory

A Beginner s Guide to Modern Set Theory A Beginner s Guide to Modern Set Theory Martin Dowd Product of Hyperon Software PO Box 4161 Costa Mesa, CA 92628 www.hyperonsoft.com Copyright c 2010 by Martin Dowd 1. Introduction..... 1 2. Formal logic......

More information

A Propositional Dynamic Logic for CCS Programs

A Propositional Dynamic Logic for CCS Programs A Propositional Dynamic Logic for CCS Programs Mario R. F. Benevides and L. Menasché Schechter {mario,luis}@cos.ufrj.br Abstract This work presents a Propositional Dynamic Logic in which the programs are

More information

E3: PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS lecture notes

E3: PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS lecture notes E3: PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS lecture notes 2 Contents 1 PROBABILITY THEORY 7 1.1 Experiments and random events............................ 7 1.2 Certain event. Impossible event............................

More information

ON FUNCTIONAL SYMBOL-FREE LOGIC PROGRAMS

ON FUNCTIONAL SYMBOL-FREE LOGIC PROGRAMS PROCEEDINGS OF THE YEREVAN STATE UNIVERSITY Physical and Mathematical Sciences 2012 1 p. 43 48 ON FUNCTIONAL SYMBOL-FREE LOGIC PROGRAMS I nf or m at i cs L. A. HAYKAZYAN * Chair of Programming and Information

More information

Turing Degrees and Definability of the Jump. Theodore A. Slaman. University of California, Berkeley. CJuly, 2005

Turing Degrees and Definability of the Jump. Theodore A. Slaman. University of California, Berkeley. CJuly, 2005 Turing Degrees and Definability of the Jump Theodore A. Slaman University of California, Berkeley CJuly, 2005 Outline Lecture 1 Forcing in arithmetic Coding and decoding theorems Automorphisms of countable

More information

Dedekind s forgotten axiom and why we should teach it (and why we shouldn t teach mathematical induction in our calculus classes)

Dedekind s forgotten axiom and why we should teach it (and why we shouldn t teach mathematical induction in our calculus classes) Dedekind s forgotten axiom and why we should teach it (and why we shouldn t teach mathematical induction in our calculus classes) by Jim Propp (UMass Lowell) March 14, 2010 1 / 29 Completeness Three common

More information

Mathematical Methods of Engineering Analysis

Mathematical Methods of Engineering Analysis Mathematical Methods of Engineering Analysis Erhan Çinlar Robert J. Vanderbei February 2, 2000 Contents Sets and Functions 1 1 Sets................................... 1 Subsets.............................

More information

The Philosophical Implications (if any) of the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem by Peter Hollo

The Philosophical Implications (if any) of the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem by Peter Hollo The Philosophical Implications (if any) of the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem by A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF Advanced Science/Arts UNSW 1996 i UNSW Abstract

More information

Lecture 2: Universality

Lecture 2: Universality CS 710: Complexity Theory 1/21/2010 Lecture 2: Universality Instructor: Dieter van Melkebeek Scribe: Tyson Williams In this lecture, we introduce the notion of a universal machine, develop efficient universal

More information

Math 223 Abstract Algebra Lecture Notes

Math 223 Abstract Algebra Lecture Notes Math 223 Abstract Algebra Lecture Notes Steven Tschantz Spring 2001 (Apr. 23 version) Preamble These notes are intended to supplement the lectures and make up for the lack of a textbook for the course

More information

CHAPTER 5. Number Theory. 1. Integers and Division. Discussion

CHAPTER 5. Number Theory. 1. Integers and Division. Discussion CHAPTER 5 Number Theory 1. Integers and Division 1.1. Divisibility. Definition 1.1.1. Given two integers a and b we say a divides b if there is an integer c such that b = ac. If a divides b, we write a

More information

Linear Algebra I. Ronald van Luijk, 2012

Linear Algebra I. Ronald van Luijk, 2012 Linear Algebra I Ronald van Luijk, 2012 With many parts from Linear Algebra I by Michael Stoll, 2007 Contents 1. Vector spaces 3 1.1. Examples 3 1.2. Fields 4 1.3. The field of complex numbers. 6 1.4.

More information

So let us begin our quest to find the holy grail of real analysis.

So let us begin our quest to find the holy grail of real analysis. 1 Section 5.2 The Complete Ordered Field: Purpose of Section We present an axiomatic description of the real numbers as a complete ordered field. The axioms which describe the arithmetic of the real numbers

More information

3. Prime and maximal ideals. 3.1. Definitions and Examples.

3. Prime and maximal ideals. 3.1. Definitions and Examples. COMMUTATIVE ALGEBRA 5 3.1. Definitions and Examples. 3. Prime and maximal ideals Definition. An ideal P in a ring A is called prime if P A and if for every pair x, y of elements in A\P we have xy P. Equivalently,

More information

1 Homework 1. [p 0 q i+j +... + p i 1 q j+1 ] + [p i q j ] + [p i+1 q j 1 +... + p i+j q 0 ]

1 Homework 1. [p 0 q i+j +... + p i 1 q j+1 ] + [p i q j ] + [p i+1 q j 1 +... + p i+j q 0 ] 1 Homework 1 (1) Prove the ideal (3,x) is a maximal ideal in Z[x]. SOLUTION: Suppose we expand this ideal by including another generator polynomial, P / (3, x). Write P = n + x Q with n an integer not

More information

Metric Spaces. Chapter 1

Metric Spaces. Chapter 1 Chapter 1 Metric Spaces Many of the arguments you have seen in several variable calculus are almost identical to the corresponding arguments in one variable calculus, especially arguments concerning convergence

More information

Mechanics 1: Vectors

Mechanics 1: Vectors Mechanics 1: Vectors roadly speaking, mechanical systems will be described by a combination of scalar and vector quantities. scalar is just a (real) number. For example, mass or weight is characterized

More information

An Innocent Investigation

An Innocent Investigation An Innocent Investigation D. Joyce, Clark University January 2006 The beginning. Have you ever wondered why every number is either even or odd? I don t mean to ask if you ever wondered whether every number

More information

THE DIMENSION OF A VECTOR SPACE

THE DIMENSION OF A VECTOR SPACE THE DIMENSION OF A VECTOR SPACE KEITH CONRAD This handout is a supplementary discussion leading up to the definition of dimension and some of its basic properties. Let V be a vector space over a field

More information

o-minimality and Uniformity in n 1 Graphs

o-minimality and Uniformity in n 1 Graphs o-minimality and Uniformity in n 1 Graphs Reid Dale July 10, 2013 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Languages and Structures 2 3 Definability and Tame Geometry 4 4 Applications to n 1 Graphs 6 5 Further Directions

More information

WRITING PROOFS. Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology

WRITING PROOFS. Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology WRITING PROOFS Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology A theorem is just a statement of fact A proof of the theorem is a logical explanation of why the theorem is true Many theorems have this

More information

Notes on metric spaces

Notes on metric spaces Notes on metric spaces 1 Introduction The purpose of these notes is to quickly review some of the basic concepts from Real Analysis, Metric Spaces and some related results that will be used in this course.

More information

8 Primes and Modular Arithmetic

8 Primes and Modular Arithmetic 8 Primes and Modular Arithmetic 8.1 Primes and Factors Over two millennia ago already, people all over the world were considering the properties of numbers. One of the simplest concepts is prime numbers.

More information

Geometric Transformations

Geometric Transformations Geometric Transformations Definitions Def: f is a mapping (function) of a set A into a set B if for every element a of A there exists a unique element b of B that is paired with a; this pairing is denoted

More information

Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part IV: Vector Spaces

Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part IV: Vector Spaces Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part IV: Vector Spaces D. R. Wilkins Academic Year 1996-7 9 Vector Spaces A vector space over some field K is an algebraic structure consisting of a set V on which are

More information

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products Chapter 3 Cartesian Products and Relations The material in this chapter is the first real encounter with abstraction. Relations are very general thing they are a special type of subset. After introducing

More information

Quotient Rings and Field Extensions

Quotient Rings and Field Extensions Chapter 5 Quotient Rings and Field Extensions In this chapter we describe a method for producing field extension of a given field. If F is a field, then a field extension is a field K that contains F.

More information

Metric Spaces. Chapter 7. 7.1. Metrics

Metric Spaces. Chapter 7. 7.1. Metrics Chapter 7 Metric Spaces A metric space is a set X that has a notion of the distance d(x, y) between every pair of points x, y X. The purpose of this chapter is to introduce metric spaces and give some

More information

it is easy to see that α = a

it is easy to see that α = a 21. Polynomial rings Let us now turn out attention to determining the prime elements of a polynomial ring, where the coefficient ring is a field. We already know that such a polynomial ring is a UF. Therefore

More information

Continued Fractions and the Euclidean Algorithm

Continued Fractions and the Euclidean Algorithm Continued Fractions and the Euclidean Algorithm Lecture notes prepared for MATH 326, Spring 997 Department of Mathematics and Statistics University at Albany William F Hammond Table of Contents Introduction

More information

Set Theory Basic Concepts and Definitions

Set Theory Basic Concepts and Definitions Set Theory Basic Concepts and Definitions The Importance of Set Theory One striking feature of humans is their inherent need and ability to group objects according to specific criteria. Our prehistoric

More information

Chapter 4, Arithmetic in F [x] Polynomial arithmetic and the division algorithm.

Chapter 4, Arithmetic in F [x] Polynomial arithmetic and the division algorithm. Chapter 4, Arithmetic in F [x] Polynomial arithmetic and the division algorithm. We begin by defining the ring of polynomials with coefficients in a ring R. After some preliminary results, we specialize

More information

Kevin James. MTHSC 412 Section 2.4 Prime Factors and Greatest Comm

Kevin James. MTHSC 412 Section 2.4 Prime Factors and Greatest Comm MTHSC 412 Section 2.4 Prime Factors and Greatest Common Divisor Greatest Common Divisor Definition Suppose that a, b Z. Then we say that d Z is a greatest common divisor (gcd) of a and b if the following

More information

GROUPS ACTING ON A SET

GROUPS ACTING ON A SET GROUPS ACTING ON A SET MATH 435 SPRING 2012 NOTES FROM FEBRUARY 27TH, 2012 1. Left group actions Definition 1.1. Suppose that G is a group and S is a set. A left (group) action of G on S is a rule for

More information

Vector and Matrix Norms

Vector and Matrix Norms Chapter 1 Vector and Matrix Norms 11 Vector Spaces Let F be a field (such as the real numbers, R, or complex numbers, C) with elements called scalars A Vector Space, V, over the field F is a non-empty

More information