9. Boolean algebras and forcing orders

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "9. Boolean algebras and forcing orders"

Transcription

1 9. Boolean algebras and forcing orders To introduce the apparatus of generic extensions and forcing in a clear fashion, it is necessary to go into a special set theoretic topic: Boolean algebras and their relation to certain orders. A Boolean algebra (BA) is a structure A, +,,, 0, 1 with two binary operations + and, a unary operation, and two distinguished elements 0 and 1 such that the following axioms hold for all x, y, z A: (A) x + (y + z) = (x + y) + z; (A ) x (y z) = (x y) z; (C) x + y = y + x; (C ) x y = y x; (L) x + (x y) = x; (L ) x (x + y) = x; (D) x (y + z) = (x y) + (x z); (D ) x + (y z) = (x + y) (x + z); (K) x + ( x) = 1; (K ) x ( x) = 0. The main example of a Boolean algebra is a field of sets: a set A of subsets of some set X, closed under union, intersection, and complementation with respect to X. The associated Boolean algebra is A,,, \, 0, X. Here \ is treated as a one-place operation, producing X\a for any a A. This example is really all-encompassing every BA is isomorphic to one of these. We will not prove this, or use it. As is usual in algebra, we usually denote a whole algebra A, +,,, 0, 1 just by mentioning its universe A, everything else being implicit. Some notations used in some treatments of Boolean algebras are: or for +; or for ; for. These notations might be confusing if discussing logic, or elementary set theory. Our notation might be confusing if discussing ordinary algebra. Now we give the elementary arithmetic of Boolean algebras. We recommend that the reader go through them, but then approach any arithmetic statement in the future from the point of view of seeing if it works in fields of sets; if so, it should be easy to derive from the axioms. First we have the duality principle, which we shall not formulate carefully; our particular uses of it will be clear. Namely, notice that the axioms come in pairs, obtained from each other by interchanging + and and 0 and 1. This means that also if we prove some arithmetic statement, the dual statement, obtained by this interchanging process, is also valid. Proposition 9.1. x + x = x and x x = x. Proof. the second statement follows by duality. x + x = x + x (x + x) by (L ) = x by (L); Proposition 9.2. x + y = y iff x y = x. Proof. Assume that x + y = y. Then, by (L ), x y = x (x + y) = x. 66

2 The converse follows by duality. In any BA we define x y iff x + y = y. Note that the dual of x y is y x, by 9.2 and commutativity. (The dual of a defined notion is obtained by dualizing the original notions.) Proposition 9.3. On any BA, is reflexive, transitive, and antisymmetric; that is, the following conditions hold: (i) x x; (ii) If x y and y z, then x z; (iii) If x y and y x, then x = y. Proof. x x means x + x = x, which was proved in 9.1. Assume the hypothesis of (ii). Then x + z = x + (y + z) = (x + y) + z = y + z = z, as desired. Finally, under the hypotheses of (iii), x = x + y = y + x = y. Note that Proposition 9.3 says that is a partial order on the BA A. There are some notions concerning partial orders which we need. An element z is an upper bound for a set Y of elements of X if y z for all y Y ; similarly for lower bounds. And z is a least upper bound for Y if it is an upper bound for Y and is any other upper bound for Y ; simlarly for greatest lower bounds. By antisymmetry, in any partial order least upper bounds and greatest lower bounds are unique if they exist. Proposition 9.4. x + y is the least upper bound of {x, y}, and x y is the greatest lower bound of {x, y}. Proof. We have x + (x + y) = (x + x) + y = x + y, and similarly y + (x + y) = y + (y + x) = (y + y) + x = y + x = x + y; so x + y is an upper bound for {x, y}. If z is any upper bound for {x, y}, then (x + y) + z = (x + (y + z) = x + z = z, as desired. The other part follows by duality(!). Proposition 9.5. (i) x + 0 = x and x 1 = x; (ii) x 0 = x and x + 1 = 1; (iii) 0 x 1. 67

3 Proof. By (K) and Proposition 9.4, 1 is the least upper bound of x and x; in particular it is an upper bound, so x 1. Everything else follows by duality, Proposition 9.2, and the definitions. Proposition 9.6. For any x and y, y = x iff x y = 0 and x + y = 1. Proof. holds by (K) and (K ). Now suppose that x y = 0 and x + y = 1. Then y = y 1 = y (x + x) = y x + y x = 0 + y x = y x; x = x 1 = x (x + y) = x x + x y = 0 + x y = x y = y. Proposition 9.7. (i) x = x; (ii) if x = y then x = y; (iii) 0 = 1 and 1 = 0; (iv) (DeMorgan s laws) (x + y) = x y and (x y) = x + y. Proof. If we apply Proposition 9.6 with x and y replaced respectively by x and x, we get x = x. Next, if x = y, then x = x = y = y. For (iii), by 9.5(iii), 0 1 = 0 and = 1, so by 9.6, 0 = 1. Then 1 = 0 by duality. For the first part of (iv), (x + y) x y = x x y + y x y = = 0, and (x + y) + x y = x (y + y) + y + x y = x y + x y + y + x y = y + x y + x y = y + y = 1, so that (x + y) = x y by Proposition 9.6. Finally, the second part of (iv) follows by duality. Proposition 9.8. x y iff y x. Proof. Assume that x y. Then x + y = y, so x y = y, i.e., y x. For the converse, use the implication just proved, plus 9.7(i). Proposition 9.9. If x x and y y, then x + y x + y and x y x y. Proof. Assume the hypothesis. Then (x + y) + (x + y ) = (x + x ) + (y + y ) = x + y, and so x + y x + y ; the second conclusion follows by duality. Proposition x y iff x y = 0. 68

4 Proof. If x y, then x = x y and so x y = 0. Conversely, if x y = 0, then so that x y. x = x (y + y) = x y + x y = x y, Elements x, y A are disjoint if x y = 0. For any x, y we define this is the symmetric difference of x and y. Proposition (i) x = y iff x y = 0; (ii) x (y z) = (x y) (x z); (iii) x (y z) = (x y) z. x y = x y + y x; Proof. For (i), is trivial. Now assume that x y = 0. Then x y = 0 = y x, so x y and y x, so x = y. For (ii), we have as desired. Finally, for (iii), x (y z) = x y z + x z y = (x y) (x z) + (x z) (x y) = (x y) (x z), x (y z) = x (y z + y z) + (y z + y z) x = x ( y + z) (y + z) + x y z + x y z = x y z + x y z + x y z + x y z; if we apply the same argument to z (y x) we get z (y x) = z y x + z y x + z y x + z y x, which is the same thing. So the obvious symmetry of gives the desired result. One further useful result is that axiom (D ) is redundant: Proposition (D ) is redundant. Proof. (x + y) (x + z) = ((x + y) x) + ((x + y) z) = (x (x + y)) + (z (x + y)) = x + ((z x) + (z y)) = x + ((x z) + (y z)) = (x + (x z)) + (y z) = x + (y z). 69

5 Complete Boolean algebras If M is a subset of a BA A, we denote by M its least upper bound (if it exists), and by M its greatest lower bound, if it exists. A is complete iff these always exist. Note that frequently people use M and M instead of M and M. Proposition Assume that A is a complete BA. (i) i I a i = i I a i. (ii) i I a i = i I a i. Proof. For (i), let a = i I a i; we show that a is the greatest lower bound of { a i : i I}. If i I, then a i a, and hence a a i ; thus a is a lower bound for the indicated set. Now suppose that x is any lower bound for this set. Then for any i I we have x a i, and so a i x. So x is an upper bound for {a i : i I}, and so a x. Hence x a, as desired. (ii) is proved similarly. The following (possibly infinite) distributive law is frequently useful. One should be aware of the fact that more general infinite distributive laws do not hold, in general. Since this will not enter into our treatment, we do not go into a counterexample or further discussion of really general distributive laws. Proposition If i I a i exists, then i I (b a i) exists and b a i = a i ). i I(b i I Proof. Let s = i I a i; we shall show that b s is the least upper bound of {b a i : i I}. If i I, then a i s and so b a i b s; so b s is an upper bound for the indicated set. Now suppose that x is any upper bound for this set. Then for any i I we have b a i x, hence b a i x = 0 and so a i (b x) = b + x; so b + x is an upper bound for {a i : i I}. It follows that s b + x, and hence s b x, as desired. Forcing orders A forcing order is a triple P = (P,, 1) such that is a reflexive and transitive relation on the nonempty set P, and p P(p 1). Note that we do not assume that is antisymmetric. Partial orders are special cases of forcing orders in which this is assumed (but we do not assume the existence of 1 in partial orders). Note that we assume that every forcing order has a largest element. Many set-theorists use partial order instead of forcing order. Frequently we use just P for a forcing order; and 1 are assumed. We say that elements p, q P are compatible iff there is an r p, q. We write p q to indicate that p and q are incompatible. A set A of elements of P is an antichain iff any two distinct members of A are incompatible. WARNING: sometimes antichain is used to mean pairwise incomparable, a much different notion. A subset Q of P is dense iff for every p P there is a q Q such that q p. 70

6 Now we are going to describe how to embed a forcing order into a complete BA. We take the regular open algebra of a certain topological space. We assume a very little bit of topology. To avoid assuming any knowledge of topology we now give a minimalist introduction to topology. A topology on a set X is a collection O of subsets of X satisfying the following conditions: (1) X, O. (2) O is closed under arbitrary unions. (3) O is closed under finite intersections. The members of O are said to be open. The interior of a subset Y X is the union of all open sets contained in Y ; we denote it by int(y ). Proposition (i) int( ) =. (ii) int(x) = X. (iii) int(y ) Y. (iv) int(y Z) = int(y ) int(z). (v) int(int(y )) = int(y ). (vi) int(y ) = {x X : x U Y for some open set U}. Proof. (i) (iii), (v), and (vi) are obvious. For (iv), if U is an open set contained in Y Z, then it is contained in Y ; so int(y Z) int(y ). Similarly for Z, so holds. For, note that the right side is an open set contained in Y Z. (v) holds since int(y ) is open. A subset C of X is closed iff X\C is open. Proposition (i) and X are closed. (ii) The collection of all closed sets is closed under finite unions and intersections of any nonempty subcollection. For any Y X, the closure of Y, denoted by cl(y ), is the intersection of all closed sets containing Y. Proposition (i) cl(y ) = X\int(X\Y ). (ii) int(y ) = X\cl(X\Y ). (iii) cl( ) =. (iv) cl(x) = X. (v) Y cl(y ). (vi) cl(y Z) = cl(y ) cl(z). (vii) cl(cl(y )) = cl(y ). (viii) cl(y ) = {x X :for every open set U, if x U then U Y }. Proof. (i): int(x\y ) is an open set contained in X\Y, so Y is a subset of the closed set X\int(X\Y ). Hence cl(y ) X\int(X\Y ). Also. cl(y ) is a closed set containing 71

7 Y, so X\cl(Y ) is an open set contained in X\Y. Hence X\cl(Y ) int(x\y ). Hence X\int(X\Y cl(y ). This proves (i). (ii): Using (i), (iii) (v): clear. (vi): (vii): X\cl(X\Y ) = X\(X\int(X\(X\Y ))) = int(y ). cl(y Z) = X\int(X\(Y Z)) by (i) = X\int((X\Y ) (X\Z)) = X\(int(X\Y ) int(x\z)) by 9.15(iv) = [X\int(X\Y )] [X\int(X\Z)] = cl(y ) cl(z). cl(cl(y )) = cl(x\int(x\y )) = X\int(X\(X\int(X\Y ))) = X\int(int(X\Y )) = X\int(X\Y ) = cl(y ). (vii): First suppose that x cl(y ), and x U, U open. By (i) and Proposition 9.15(vi) we have U X\Y, i.e., U Y, as desired. Second, suppose that x / cl(y ). Then by (i) and 9.15(vi) there is an open U such that x U X\Y ; so U Y =, as desired. Now we go beyond this minimum amount of topology and work with the notion of a regular open set, which is not a standard part of topology courses. We say that Y is regular open iff Y = int(cl(y )). Proposition (i) If Y is open, then Y int(cl(y )). (ii) If U and V are regular open, then so is U V. (iii) int(cl(y )) is regular open. (iv) If U is open, then int(cl(u)) is the smallest regular open set containing U. (v) If U is open then U cl(y ) cl(u Y ). (vi) If U is open, then U int(cl(y )) int(cl(u Y )). (vii) If U and V are open and U V =, then int(cl(u)) V =. (viii) If U and V are open and U V =, then int(cl(u)) int(cl(v )) =. (ix) For any set M of regular open sets, int(cl( M) is the least regular open set containing each member of M. Proof. (i): Y cl(y ), and hence Y = int(y ) int(cl(y )). 72

8 (ii): U V is open, and so U V int(cl(u V )). For the other inclusion, int(cl(u V )) int(cl(u)) = U, and similarly for V, so the other inclusion holds. (iii): int(cl(x)) cl(x), so cl(int(cl(x))) cl(cl(x)) = cl(x); hence int(cl(int(cl(x)))) int(cl(x)); the other inclusion is clear. (iv): By (iii), int(cl(u)) is a regular open set containing U. If V is any regular open set containing U, then int(cl(u)) int(cl(v )) = V. (v): and (v) follows. (vi): U (X\(U Y )) X\Y, hence U int(x\(u Y )) = int(u) int(x\(u Y )) = int(u (X\(U Y ))) int(x\y ), hence X\int(X\Y ) X\(U int(x\(u Y ))) = (X\U) (X\int(X\(U Y ))), hence U (X\int(X\Y )) (X\int(X\(U Y ))), U int(cl(y )) = int(u) int(cl(y )) = int(u cl(y )) int(cl(u Y )) by (v). (vii): U X\V, hence cl(u) cl(x\v ) = X\V, hence cl(u) V =, and the conclusion of (vii) follows. (viii): Apply (vii) twice. (ix): If U M, then U M int(cl( M). Suppose that V is regular open and U V for all U M. Then M V, and so int(cl( M)) int(cl(v ) = V. We let RO(X) be the collection of all regular open sets in X. We define operations on RO(X) which will make it a Boolean algebra. For any Y, Z RO(X), let Y + Z = int(cl(y Z)); Y Z = Y Z; Y = int(x\y ). Theorem The structure RO(X), +,,,, X 73

9 is a complete BA. Moreover, the ordering coincides with. Proof. RO(X) is closed under + by Proposition 9.18(ix), and is closed under by Proposition 9.18(ii). Clearly it is closed under, and, X RO(X). Now we check the axioms. The following are completely obvious: (A ), (C ), (C). Now let unexplained variables range over RO(X). For (A), note by 9.18(i) that U U + V (U + V ) + W; and similarly V (U +V ) +W and W U +V (U +V ) +W. If U, V, W Z, then by 9.18(iv), U + V Z and hence (U + V ) + W Z. Thus (U + V ) + W is the least upper bound in RO(X) of U, V, W. This is true for all U, V, W. So U + (V + W) = (V + W) + U is also the least upper bound of them; so (A) holds. For (L): U + U V = int(cl(u (U V ))) = int(cl(u)) = U. (L ) holds by 9.18(i). For (D), first note that Y (Z + W) = Y int(cl(z W)) int(cl(y (Z W))) by 9.18(vi) = int(cl((y Z) (Y W))) = Y Z + Y W. On the other hand, (Y Z) (Y W) = Y (Z W) Y, Z W, and hence easily Y Z + Y W = int(cl((y Z) (Y W))) int(cl(y ) = Y and Y Z + Y W = int(cl((y Z) (Y W))) int(cl(z W) = Z + W; so the other inclusion follows, and (D) holds. (K): For any regular open Y, from Proposition 9.17(ii) we get Y = int(x\y ) = X\cl(X\(X\Y )) = X\cl(Y ). Hence X = cl(y ) (X\cl(Y )) cl(y ) cl((x\cl(y )) = cl(y (X\cl(Y ))), and hence X = Y + Y. (K ): Clearly = Y int(x\y ) = Y Y. Thus we have now proved that RO(X), +,,,, X is a BA. Since is the same as, is the same as. Hence by Proposition 9.18(ix), RO(X), +,,,, X is a complete BA. Now we return to our task of embedding a forcing order into a complete Boolean algebra. Let P be a given forcing order. For each p P let P p = {q : q p}. Now we define O P = {X P : (P p) X for every p X}. 74

10 We check that this gives a topology on P. Clearly P, O. To show that O is closed under arbitrary unions, suppose that X O. Take any p X. Choose X X such that p X. Then (P p) X X, as desired. If X, Y O P, suppose that p X Y. Then p X, so (P p) X. Similarly (P p) Y, so (P p) X Y. Thus X Y O P, finishing the proof that O P is a topology on P. We denote the complete BA of regular open sets in this topology by RO(P). Now for any p P we define e(p) = int(cl(p p)). Thus e maps P into RO(P). This is our desired embedding. Actually it is not really an embedding in general, but it has several useful properties, and for many forcing orders it really is an embedding. The useful properties mentioned are as follows. We say that a subset X of P is dense below p iff for every r p there is a q r such that q X. Theorem Let P be a forcing order. Suppose that p, q P, F is a finite subset of P, a, b RO(P), and N is a subset of RO(P) (i) e[p] is dense in RO(P), i.e., for any nonzero Y RO(P) there is a p P such that e(p) Y. (ii) If p q then e(p) e(q). (iii) p q iff e(p) e(q) =. (iv) If e(p) e(q), then p and q are compatible. (v) The following conditions are equivalent: (a) e(p) e(q). (b) {r : r p, q} is dense below p. (vi) The following conditions are equivalent, for F nonempty: (a) e(p) q F e(q). (b) {r : r q for all q F } is dense below p. (vii) The following conditions are equivalent: (a) e(p) ( q F e(q)) N. (b) {r : r q for all q F and e(r) s for some s N} is dense below p. (viii) e(p) a iff there is no q p such that e(q) a. (ix) e(p) a + b iff for all q p, if e(q) a then e(q) b. Proof. (i): Assume the hypothesis. By the definition of the topology and since Y is nonempty and open, there is a p P such that P p Y. Hence e(p) = int(cl(p p)) int(cl(y )) = Y. (ii): If p q, then P p P q, and so e(p) = int(cl(p p)) int(cl(p q) = e(q)). (iii): Assume that p q. Then (P p) (P q) =, and hence by Proposition 9.18(viii), e(p) e(q) =. Conversely, suppose that e(p) e(q) =. Then (P p) (P q) e(p) e(q) =, and so p q. (iv): If e(p) e(q), then e(p) e(q) = e(p), so p and q are compatible by (iii). (v): For (a) (b), suppose that e(p) e(q) and s p. Then e(s) e(p) e(q), so s and q are compatible by (iv); say r s, q. Then r s p, hence r p, q, as desired. 75

11 For (b) (a), suppose that e(p) e(q). Thus e(p) e(q) 0. Hence there is an s such that e(s) e(p) e(q). Hence e(s) e(q) =, so s q by (iii). Now e(s) e(p), so s and p are compatible by (iv); say t s, p. For any r t we have r s, and hence r q. So (b) fails. (vi): We proceed by induction on F. The case F = 1 is given by (v). Now assume the result for F, and suppose that t P \F. First suppose that e(p) q F e(q) e(t). Suppose that s p. Now e(p) q F e(q), so by the inductive hypothesis there is a u s such that u q for all q F. Thus e(u) e(s) e(p) e(t), so by (iv), u and t are compatible. Take any v u, t. then v q for any q F {t}, as desired. Second, suppose that (b) holds for F {t}. In particular, {r : r q for all q F } is dense below p, and so e(p) q F e(q) by the inductive hypothesis. But also clearly {r : r t} is dense below p, so e(p) e(t) too, as desired. (vii): First assume that e(p) ( q F e(q)) N, and suppose that u p. By (vi), there is a v u such that v q for each q F. Now e(v) e(u) e(p) N, so 0 e(v) = e(v) N = s N (e(v) e(s)). Hence there is an s N such that e(v) e(s) 0. Hence by (iii), v and s are compatible; say r v, s. Clearly r is in the set described in (b). Second, suppose that (b) holds. Clearly then {r : r q for all q F } is dense below p, and so e(p) q F e(q) by (vi). Now suppose that e(p) N. Then e(p) N 0, so there is a q such that e(q) e(p) N. By (iv), q and p are compatible; say s p, q. Then by (b) choose r s and t N such that e(r) t. Thus e(r) e(s) t e(p) t ( N) N = 0, contradiction. (viii) : Assume that e(p) a. Suppose that q p and e(q) a. Then e(q) a a = 0, contradiction. (viii) : Assume that e(p) a. Then e(p) a 0, so there is a q such that e(q) e(p) a. By (vii) there is an r p, q with e(r) a, as desired. (ix) : Assume that e(p) a+b, q p, and e(q) a. Then e(q) a ( a+b) b, as desired. (ix) : Assume the indicated condition, but suppose that e(p) a + b. Then e(p) a b 0, so there is a q such that e(q) e(p) a b. By (vii) with F = {p} and N = {a b} we get q such that q p and e(q) a b. So q p and e(q) a, so by our condition, e(q) b. But also e(q) b, contradiction. We now expand on the remarks above concerning when e really is an embedding. Note that if P is a simple ordering, then the closure of P p is P itself, and hence P has only two regular open subsets, namely the empty set and P itself. If the ordering on P is trivial, meaning that no two elements are comparable, then every subset of P is regular open. An important condition satisfied by many forcing orders is defined as follows. We say that P is separative iff it is a partial order (thus is an antisymmetric forcing order), and for any p, q P, if p q then there is an r p such that r q. Proposition Let P be a forcing order. (i) cl(p p) = {q : p and q are compatible}. (ii) e(p) = {q : for all r q, r and p are compatible}. (iii) The following conditions are equivalent: (a) P is separative. 76

12 (b) e is one-one, and for all p, q P, p q iff e(p) e(q). Proof. (i) and (ii) are clear. For (iii), (a) (b), assume that P is separative. Take any p, q P. If p q, then e(p) e(q) by 9.20(ii). Suppose that p q. Choose r p such that r q. Then r e(p), while r / e(q) by (ii). Thus e(p) e(q). Now suppose that e(p) = e(q). Then p q p by what was just shown, so p = q since P is a partial order. For (iii), (b) (a), suppose that p q p. Then e(p) e(q) e(p), so e(p) = e(q), and hence p = q. So P is a partial order. Suppose that p q. Then e(p) e(q). Choose s e(p)\e(q). Since s / e(q), by (ii) we can choose t s such that t q. Since s e(p), it follows that t and p are compatible; choose r t, p. Clearly r q. Now we prove a theorem which says that the regular open algebra of a forcing order is unique up to isomorphism. Theorem Let P be a forcing order, A a complete BA, and j a function mapping P into A\{0} with the following properties: (i) j[p] is dense in A, i.e., for any nonzero a A there is a p P such that j(p) a. (ii) For all p, q P, if p q then j(p) j(q). (iii) For any p, q P, p q iff j(p) j(q) = 0. Then there is a unique isomorphism f from RO(P) onto A such that f e = j. That is, f is a bijection from RO(P) onto A, and for any x, y RO(P), x y iff f(x) f(y). Note that since the Boolean operations are easily expressible in terms of (as least upper bounds, etc.), the condition here implies that f preserves all of the Boolean operations too; this includes the infinite sums and products. Proof. Before beginning the proof, we introduce some notation in order to make the situation more symmetric. Let B 0 = RO(P), B 1 = A, k 0 = e, and k 1 = j. Then for each m < 2 the following conditions hold: (1) k m [P] is dense in B m. (2) For all p, q P, if p q then k m (p) k m (q). (3) For all p, q P, p q iff k m (p) k m (q) = 0. (4) For all p, q P, if k m (p) k m (q), then p and q are compatible. In fact, (1) (3) follow from 9.20 and the assumptions of the theorem. Condition (4) for m = 0, so that k m = e, follows from 9.20(iv). For m = 1, so that k m = j, it follows easily from (iii). Now we begin the proof. For each m < 2 we define, for any x B m, g m (x) = {k 1 m (p) : p P, k m (p) x}. The proof of the theorem now consists in checking the following, for each m 2: (5) If x, y B m and x y, then g m (x) g m (y). 77

13 (6) g 1 m g m is the identity on B m. In fact, suppose that (5) and (6) have been proved. If x, y RO(P), then x y implies that g 0 (x) g 0 (y) by (5); g 0 (x) g 0 (y) implies that x = g 1 (g 0 (x)) g 1 (g 0 (y)) = y by (5) and (6). Also, (6) holding for both m = 0 and m = 1 implies that g 0 is a bijection from RO(P) onto A. So g 0 is the desired function f of the theorem. Now (5) is obvious from the definition. To prove (6), assume that m 2. We first prove (7) For any p P and any b B m, k m (p) b iff k 1 m (p) g m (b). To prove (7), first suppose that k m (p) b. Then obviously k 1 m (p) g m (b). Second, suppose that k 1 m (p) g m (b) but k m (p) b. Thus k m (p) b 0, so by the denseness of k m [P] in B m, choose q P such that k m (q) k m (p) b. Then p and q are compatible by (4), so let r P be such that r p, q. Hence k 1 m (r) k 1 m (p) g m (b) = {k 1 m (s) : s P, k m (s) b}. Hence k 1 m (r) = {k 1 m (s) k 1 m (r) : s P, k m (s) b}, so there is an s P such that k m (s) b and k 1 m (s) k 1 m (r) 0. Hence s and r are compatible; say t s, r. Hence k m (t) k m (r) k m (q) b, but also k m (t) k m (s) b, contradiction. This proves (7). Now take any b B m. Then g 1 m (g m (b)) = {k m (p) : p P, k 1 m (p) g m (b)} = {k m (p) : p P, k m (p) b} = b. Thus (6) holds. This proves the existence of f. Now suppose that g is also an isomorphism from RO(P) onto A such that g e = j, but suppose that f g. Then there is an X RO(P) such that f(x) g(x). By symmetry, say that f(x) g(x) 0. By (ii), choose p P such that j(p) f(x) g(x). So f(e(p)) = j(p) f(x), so e(p) X, and hence j(p) = g(e(p)) g(x). This contradicts j(p) g(x). EXERCISES E9.1. Let (A, +,,, 0, 1) be a Boolean algebra. Show that (A,,, 0, 1) is a ring with identity in which every element is idempotent. This means that x x = x for all x. E9.2. Let (A, +,, 0, 1) be a ring with identity in which every element is idempotent. Show that A is a commutative ring, and (A,,,, 0, 1) is a Boolean algebra, where for any x, y A, x y = x + y + xy and for any x A, x = 1 + x. Hint: expand (x + y) 2. 78

14 E9.3. Show that the processes described in exercises E9.1 and E9.2 are inverses of one another. E9.4. A filter in a BA A is a subset F of A with the following properties: (1) 1 F. (2) If a F and a b, then b F. (3) If a, b F, then a b F. An ultrafilter in A is a filter F such that 0 / F, and for any a A, a F or a F. Prove that a filter F is an ultrafilter iff F is maximal among the set of all filters G such that 0 / G. E9.5. (Continuing exercise E9.4) Prove that for any nonzero a A there is an ultrafilter F such that a F. E9.6. (Continuing exercise E9.4) Prove that any BA is isomorphic to a field of sets. (Stone s representation theorem) Hint: given a BA A, let X be the set of all ultrafilters on A and define f(a) = {F X : a F }. E9.7 (Continuing exercise E9.4) Suppose that F is an ultrafilter on a BA A. Let 2 be the two-element BA. (This is, up to isomorphism, the BA of all subsets of 1.) For any a A let { 1 if a F, f(a) = 0 if a / F. Show that f is a homomorphism of A into 2. This means that for any a, b A, the following conditions hold: f(a + b) = f(a) + f(b); f(a b) = f(a) f(b); f( a) = f(a); f(0) = 0; f(1) = 1. E9.8. (Lindenbaum-Tarski algebras; A knowledge of logic is assumed.) Suppose that L is a first-order language and T is a set of sentences of L. Define ϕ T ψ iff ϕ and ψ are sentences of L and T = ϕ ψ. Show that this is an equivalence relation on the set S of all sentences of L. Let A be the collection of all equivalence classes under this equivalence relation. Show that there are operations +,, on A such that for any sentences ϕ, ψ, [ϕ] + [ψ] = [ϕ ψ]; [ϕ] [ψ] = [ϕ ψ]; [ϕ] = [ ϕ]. Finally, show that (A, +,,, [ v 0 ( (v 0 = v 0 ))], [ v 0 (v 0 = v 0 )]) is a Boolean algebra. 79

15 E9.9. (A knowledge of logic is assumed.) Show that every Boolean algebra is isomorphic to one obtained as in exercise E9.8. Hint: Let A be a Boolean algebra. Let L be the first-order language which has a unary relation symbol R a for each a A. Let T be the following set of sentences of L : x y(x = y); x[r a (x) R a (x)] for each a A; x[r a b (x) R a (x) R b (x)] for all a, b A; xr 1 (x). E9.10. Let A be the collection of all subsets X of Y def = {r Q : 0 r} such that there exist an m ω and a, b m (Y { }) such that a 0 < b 0 < a 1 < b 1 < < a m 1 < b m 1 and X = [a 0, b 0 ) [a 1, b 1 )... [a m 1, b m 1 ). Note that A by taking m = 0, and Y A since Y = [0, ). (i) Show that if X is as above, c, d Y { } with c < d, c a 0, then X [c, d) A, and c is the first element of X [c, d). (ii) Show that if X is as above and c, d Y { } with c < d, then X [c, d) A. (iii) Show that (A,,, \,, Y ) is a Boolean algebra. E9.11. (Continuing exercise E9.10.) For each n ω let x n = [n, n + 1), an interval in Q. Show that n ω x 2n does not exist in A. E9.12. Let A be the Boolean algebra of all subsets of some nonempty set X, under the natural set-theoretic operations. Show that if a i : i I is a system of elements of A, then i + a i ) = 1 = i I(a a ε(i) i, ε I 2 i I where for any y, y 1 = y and y 0 = y. E9.13. Let M be the set of all finite functions f ω 2. For each f M let U f = {g ω 2 : f g}. Let A consist of all finite unions of sets U f. (i) Show that A is a Boolean algebra under the set-theoretic operations. (ii) For each i ω, let x i = U {(i,1)}. Show that ω 2 = (x i + x i ) i ω while ε ω 2 i ω x ε(i) i =, 80

16 where for any y, y 1 = y and y 0 = y. This is an example of an infinite distributive law that holds in some BAs (by exercise E9.12), but does not hold in all BAs. E9.14. Suppose that (P,, 1) is a forcing order. Define p q iff p, q P, p q, and q p. Show that is an equivalence relation, and if Q is the collection of all -classes, then there is a relation on Q such that for all p, q P, [p] [q] iff p q. Finally, show that (Q, ) is a partial order, i.e., is reflexive on Q, transitive, and antisymmetric (q 1 q 2 q 1 implies that q 1 = q 2 ); moreover, q [1] for all q Q. E9.15. We say that (P, <) is a partial order in the second sense iff < is transitive and irreflexive. (Irreflexive means that for all p P, p p.) Show that if (P, <) is a partial order in the second sense and if we define by p q iff (p, q P and p < q or p = q), then A (P, <) def = (P, ) is a partial order. Furthermore, show that if (P, ) is a partial order, and we define p q by p q iff (p, q P, p q, and p q), then B(P, ) def = (P, ) is a partial order in the second sense. Also prove that A and B are inverses of one another. E9.16. Show that if (P,, 1) is a forcing order and we define by p q iff (p, q P, p q and q p), then (P, ) is a partial order in the second sense. Give an example where this partial order is not isomorphic to the one derived from (P,, 1) by the procedure of exercise E9.14. E9.17. Prove that if (P,, 1) is a forcing order such that the mapping e from P into RO(P) is one-one, then (P, ) is a partial order. Give an example of a forcing order such that e is not one-one. Give an example of an infinite forcing order Q such that e is not one-one, while for any p, q Q, p q iff e(p) e(q). E9.18. (Continuing E9.14.) Let P = (P,, 1) be a forcing order, and let Q = (Q,, [1]) be as in exercise E9.14. Show that there is an isomorphism f of RO(P) onto RO(Q) such that f e P = e Q π, where π : P Q is defined by π(p) = [p] for all p P. References Koppelberg, S. General theory of Boolean algebras. Volume 1 of Handbook of Boolean Algebras, edited by J. D. Monk and R. Bonnet, North-Holland 1989, 312pp. Kunen, K. Set Theory. 81

INTRODUCTORY SET THEORY

INTRODUCTORY SET THEORY M.Sc. program in mathematics INTRODUCTORY SET THEORY Katalin Károlyi Department of Applied Analysis, Eötvös Loránd University H-1088 Budapest, Múzeum krt. 6-8. CONTENTS 1. SETS Set, equal sets, subset,

More information

I. GROUPS: BASIC DEFINITIONS AND EXAMPLES

I. GROUPS: BASIC DEFINITIONS AND EXAMPLES I GROUPS: BASIC DEFINITIONS AND EXAMPLES Definition 1: An operation on a set G is a function : G G G Definition 2: A group is a set G which is equipped with an operation and a special element e G, called

More information

MA651 Topology. Lecture 6. Separation Axioms.

MA651 Topology. Lecture 6. Separation Axioms. MA651 Topology. Lecture 6. Separation Axioms. This text is based on the following books: Fundamental concepts of topology by Peter O Neil Elements of Mathematics: General Topology by Nicolas Bourbaki Counterexamples

More information

So let us begin our quest to find the holy grail of real analysis.

So let us begin our quest to find the holy grail of real analysis. 1 Section 5.2 The Complete Ordered Field: Purpose of Section We present an axiomatic description of the real numbers as a complete ordered field. The axioms which describe the arithmetic of the real numbers

More information

SOLUTIONS TO ASSIGNMENT 1 MATH 576

SOLUTIONS TO ASSIGNMENT 1 MATH 576 SOLUTIONS TO ASSIGNMENT 1 MATH 576 SOLUTIONS BY OLIVIER MARTIN 13 #5. Let T be the topology generated by A on X. We want to show T = J B J where B is the set of all topologies J on X with A J. This amounts

More information

Mathematics for Computer Science/Software Engineering. Notes for the course MSM1F3 Dr. R. A. Wilson

Mathematics for Computer Science/Software Engineering. Notes for the course MSM1F3 Dr. R. A. Wilson Mathematics for Computer Science/Software Engineering Notes for the course MSM1F3 Dr. R. A. Wilson October 1996 Chapter 1 Logic Lecture no. 1. We introduce the concept of a proposition, which is a statement

More information

This asserts two sets are equal iff they have the same elements, that is, a set is determined by its elements.

This asserts two sets are equal iff they have the same elements, that is, a set is determined by its elements. 3. Axioms of Set theory Before presenting the axioms of set theory, we first make a few basic comments about the relevant first order logic. We will give a somewhat more detailed discussion later, but

More information

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products Chapter 3 Cartesian Products and Relations The material in this chapter is the first real encounter with abstraction. Relations are very general thing they are a special type of subset. After introducing

More information

1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set.

1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set. 1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set. Basic Topology Written by Men-Gen Tsai email: b89902089@ntu.edu.tw Proof: For any element x of the empty set, x is also an element of every set since

More information

Degrees of Truth: the formal logic of classical and quantum probabilities as well as fuzzy sets.

Degrees of Truth: the formal logic of classical and quantum probabilities as well as fuzzy sets. Degrees of Truth: the formal logic of classical and quantum probabilities as well as fuzzy sets. Logic is the study of reasoning. A language of propositions is fundamental to this study as well as true

More information

1 if 1 x 0 1 if 0 x 1

1 if 1 x 0 1 if 0 x 1 Chapter 3 Continuity In this chapter we begin by defining the fundamental notion of continuity for real valued functions of a single real variable. When trying to decide whether a given function is or

More information

Basic Concepts of Point Set Topology Notes for OU course Math 4853 Spring 2011

Basic Concepts of Point Set Topology Notes for OU course Math 4853 Spring 2011 Basic Concepts of Point Set Topology Notes for OU course Math 4853 Spring 2011 A. Miller 1. Introduction. The definitions of metric space and topological space were developed in the early 1900 s, largely

More information

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 3. Spaces with special properties

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 3. Spaces with special properties SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR MATHEMATICS 205A Part 3 Fall 2008 III. Spaces with special properties III.1 : Compact spaces I Problems from Munkres, 26, pp. 170 172 3. Show that a finite union of compact subspaces

More information

Metric Spaces Joseph Muscat 2003 (Last revised May 2009)

Metric Spaces Joseph Muscat 2003 (Last revised May 2009) 1 Distance J Muscat 1 Metric Spaces Joseph Muscat 2003 (Last revised May 2009) (A revised and expanded version of these notes are now published by Springer.) 1 Distance A metric space can be thought of

More information

Introduction to Topology

Introduction to Topology Introduction to Topology Tomoo Matsumura November 30, 2010 Contents 1 Topological spaces 3 1.1 Basis of a Topology......................................... 3 1.2 Comparing Topologies.......................................

More information

No: 10 04. Bilkent University. Monotonic Extension. Farhad Husseinov. Discussion Papers. Department of Economics

No: 10 04. Bilkent University. Monotonic Extension. Farhad Husseinov. Discussion Papers. Department of Economics No: 10 04 Bilkent University Monotonic Extension Farhad Husseinov Discussion Papers Department of Economics The Discussion Papers of the Department of Economics are intended to make the initial results

More information

Linear Algebra. A vector space (over R) is an ordered quadruple. such that V is a set; 0 V ; and the following eight axioms hold:

Linear Algebra. A vector space (over R) is an ordered quadruple. such that V is a set; 0 V ; and the following eight axioms hold: Linear Algebra A vector space (over R) is an ordered quadruple (V, 0, α, µ) such that V is a set; 0 V ; and the following eight axioms hold: α : V V V and µ : R V V ; (i) α(α(u, v), w) = α(u, α(v, w)),

More information

INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY

INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY MATH 410, CSUSM. SPRING 2008. PROFESSOR AITKEN This document covers the geometry that can be developed with just the axioms related to incidence and betweenness. The full

More information

Turing Degrees and Definability of the Jump. Theodore A. Slaman. University of California, Berkeley. CJuly, 2005

Turing Degrees and Definability of the Jump. Theodore A. Slaman. University of California, Berkeley. CJuly, 2005 Turing Degrees and Definability of the Jump Theodore A. Slaman University of California, Berkeley CJuly, 2005 Outline Lecture 1 Forcing in arithmetic Coding and decoding theorems Automorphisms of countable

More information

God created the integers and the rest is the work of man. (Leopold Kronecker, in an after-dinner speech at a conference, Berlin, 1886)

God created the integers and the rest is the work of man. (Leopold Kronecker, in an after-dinner speech at a conference, Berlin, 1886) Chapter 2 Numbers God created the integers and the rest is the work of man. (Leopold Kronecker, in an after-dinner speech at a conference, Berlin, 1886) God created the integers and the rest is the work

More information

Cartesian Products and Relations

Cartesian Products and Relations Cartesian Products and Relations Definition (Cartesian product) If A and B are sets, the Cartesian product of A and B is the set A B = {(a, b) :(a A) and (b B)}. The following points are worth special

More information

INTRODUCTION TO TOPOLOGY

INTRODUCTION TO TOPOLOGY INTRODUCTION TO TOPOLOGY ALEX KÜRONYA In preparation January 24, 2010 Contents 1. Basic concepts 1 2. Constructing topologies 13 2.1. Subspace topology 13 2.2. Local properties 18 2.3. Product topology

More information

Page 331, 38.4 Suppose a is a positive integer and p is a prime. Prove that p a if and only if the prime factorization of a contains p.

Page 331, 38.4 Suppose a is a positive integer and p is a prime. Prove that p a if and only if the prime factorization of a contains p. Page 331, 38.2 Assignment #11 Solutions Factor the following positive integers into primes. a. 25 = 5 2. b. 4200 = 2 3 3 5 2 7. c. 10 10 = 2 10 5 10. d. 19 = 19. e. 1 = 1. Page 331, 38.4 Suppose a is a

More information

(a) Write each of p and q as a polynomial in x with coefficients in Z[y, z]. deg(p) = 7 deg(q) = 9

(a) Write each of p and q as a polynomial in x with coefficients in Z[y, z]. deg(p) = 7 deg(q) = 9 Homework #01, due 1/20/10 = 9.1.2, 9.1.4, 9.1.6, 9.1.8, 9.2.3 Additional problems for study: 9.1.1, 9.1.3, 9.1.5, 9.1.13, 9.2.1, 9.2.2, 9.2.4, 9.2.5, 9.2.6, 9.3.2, 9.3.3 9.1.1 (This problem was not assigned

More information

x < y iff x < y, or x and y are incomparable and x χ(x,y) < y χ(x,y).

x < y iff x < y, or x and y are incomparable and x χ(x,y) < y χ(x,y). 12. Large cardinals The study, or use, of large cardinals is one of the most active areas of research in set theory currently. There are many provably different kinds of large cardinals whose descriptions

More information

Linear Algebra I. Ronald van Luijk, 2012

Linear Algebra I. Ronald van Luijk, 2012 Linear Algebra I Ronald van Luijk, 2012 With many parts from Linear Algebra I by Michael Stoll, 2007 Contents 1. Vector spaces 3 1.1. Examples 3 1.2. Fields 4 1.3. The field of complex numbers. 6 1.4.

More information

3. Mathematical Induction

3. Mathematical Induction 3. MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION 83 3. Mathematical Induction 3.1. First Principle of Mathematical Induction. Let P (n) be a predicate with domain of discourse (over) the natural numbers N = {0, 1,,...}. If (1)

More information

Undergraduate Notes in Mathematics. Arkansas Tech University Department of Mathematics

Undergraduate Notes in Mathematics. Arkansas Tech University Department of Mathematics Undergraduate Notes in Mathematics Arkansas Tech University Department of Mathematics An Introductory Single Variable Real Analysis: A Learning Approach through Problem Solving Marcel B. Finan c All Rights

More information

1 = (a 0 + b 0 α) 2 + + (a m 1 + b m 1 α) 2. for certain elements a 0,..., a m 1, b 0,..., b m 1 of F. Multiplying out, we obtain

1 = (a 0 + b 0 α) 2 + + (a m 1 + b m 1 α) 2. for certain elements a 0,..., a m 1, b 0,..., b m 1 of F. Multiplying out, we obtain Notes on real-closed fields These notes develop the algebraic background needed to understand the model theory of real-closed fields. To understand these notes, a standard graduate course in algebra is

More information

Minimal R 1, minimal regular and minimal presober topologies

Minimal R 1, minimal regular and minimal presober topologies Revista Notas de Matemática Vol.5(1), No. 275, 2009, pp.73-84 http://www.saber.ula.ve/notasdematematica/ Comisión de Publicaciones Departamento de Matemáticas Facultad de Ciencias Universidad de Los Andes

More information

GROUPS ACTING ON A SET

GROUPS ACTING ON A SET GROUPS ACTING ON A SET MATH 435 SPRING 2012 NOTES FROM FEBRUARY 27TH, 2012 1. Left group actions Definition 1.1. Suppose that G is a group and S is a set. A left (group) action of G on S is a rule for

More information

3. Prime and maximal ideals. 3.1. Definitions and Examples.

3. Prime and maximal ideals. 3.1. Definitions and Examples. COMMUTATIVE ALGEBRA 5 3.1. Definitions and Examples. 3. Prime and maximal ideals Definition. An ideal P in a ring A is called prime if P A and if for every pair x, y of elements in A\P we have xy P. Equivalently,

More information

Fundamentele Informatica II

Fundamentele Informatica II Fundamentele Informatica II Answer to selected exercises 1 John C Martin: Introduction to Languages and the Theory of Computation M.M. Bonsangue (and J. Kleijn) Fall 2011 Let L be a language. It is clear

More information

A Little Set Theory (Never Hurt Anybody)

A Little Set Theory (Never Hurt Anybody) A Little Set Theory (Never Hurt Anybody) Matthew Saltzman Department of Mathematical Sciences Clemson University Draft: August 21, 2013 1 Introduction The fundamental ideas of set theory and the algebra

More information

Chapter 4, Arithmetic in F [x] Polynomial arithmetic and the division algorithm.

Chapter 4, Arithmetic in F [x] Polynomial arithmetic and the division algorithm. Chapter 4, Arithmetic in F [x] Polynomial arithmetic and the division algorithm. We begin by defining the ring of polynomials with coefficients in a ring R. After some preliminary results, we specialize

More information

4. CLASSES OF RINGS 4.1. Classes of Rings class operator A-closed Example 1: product Example 2:

4. CLASSES OF RINGS 4.1. Classes of Rings class operator A-closed Example 1: product Example 2: 4. CLASSES OF RINGS 4.1. Classes of Rings Normally we associate, with any property, a set of objects that satisfy that property. But problems can arise when we allow sets to be elements of larger sets

More information

Mathematics Review for MS Finance Students

Mathematics Review for MS Finance Students Mathematics Review for MS Finance Students Anthony M. Marino Department of Finance and Business Economics Marshall School of Business Lecture 1: Introductory Material Sets The Real Number System Functions,

More information

CODING TRUE ARITHMETIC IN THE MEDVEDEV AND MUCHNIK DEGREES

CODING TRUE ARITHMETIC IN THE MEDVEDEV AND MUCHNIK DEGREES CODING TRUE ARITHMETIC IN THE MEDVEDEV AND MUCHNIK DEGREES PAUL SHAFER Abstract. We prove that the first-order theory of the Medvedev degrees, the first-order theory of the Muchnik degrees, and the third-order

More information

FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 22

FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 22 FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 22 RAVI VAKIL CONTENTS 1. Discrete valuation rings: Dimension 1 Noetherian regular local rings 1 Last day, we discussed the Zariski tangent space, and saw that it

More information

Matrix Representations of Linear Transformations and Changes of Coordinates

Matrix Representations of Linear Transformations and Changes of Coordinates Matrix Representations of Linear Transformations and Changes of Coordinates 01 Subspaces and Bases 011 Definitions A subspace V of R n is a subset of R n that contains the zero element and is closed under

More information

8 Divisibility and prime numbers

8 Divisibility and prime numbers 8 Divisibility and prime numbers 8.1 Divisibility In this short section we extend the concept of a multiple from the natural numbers to the integers. We also summarize several other terms that express

More information

1 Homework 1. [p 0 q i+j +... + p i 1 q j+1 ] + [p i q j ] + [p i+1 q j 1 +... + p i+j q 0 ]

1 Homework 1. [p 0 q i+j +... + p i 1 q j+1 ] + [p i q j ] + [p i+1 q j 1 +... + p i+j q 0 ] 1 Homework 1 (1) Prove the ideal (3,x) is a maximal ideal in Z[x]. SOLUTION: Suppose we expand this ideal by including another generator polynomial, P / (3, x). Write P = n + x Q with n an integer not

More information

Math 223 Abstract Algebra Lecture Notes

Math 223 Abstract Algebra Lecture Notes Math 223 Abstract Algebra Lecture Notes Steven Tschantz Spring 2001 (Apr. 23 version) Preamble These notes are intended to supplement the lectures and make up for the lack of a textbook for the course

More information

Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part IV: Vector Spaces

Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part IV: Vector Spaces Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part IV: Vector Spaces D. R. Wilkins Academic Year 1996-7 9 Vector Spaces A vector space over some field K is an algebraic structure consisting of a set V on which are

More information

Chapter 13: Basic ring theory

Chapter 13: Basic ring theory Chapter 3: Basic ring theory Matthew Macauley Department of Mathematical Sciences Clemson University http://www.math.clemson.edu/~macaule/ Math 42, Spring 24 M. Macauley (Clemson) Chapter 3: Basic ring

More information

Geometric Transformations

Geometric Transformations Geometric Transformations Definitions Def: f is a mapping (function) of a set A into a set B if for every element a of A there exists a unique element b of B that is paired with a; this pairing is denoted

More information

FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: QUOTIENT SPACES

FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: QUOTIENT SPACES FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES: QUOTIENT SPACES CHRISTOPHER HEIL 1. Cosets and the Quotient Space Any vector space is an abelian group under the operation of vector addition. So, if you are have studied

More information

Separation Properties for Locally Convex Cones

Separation Properties for Locally Convex Cones Journal of Convex Analysis Volume 9 (2002), No. 1, 301 307 Separation Properties for Locally Convex Cones Walter Roth Department of Mathematics, Universiti Brunei Darussalam, Gadong BE1410, Brunei Darussalam

More information

Arkansas Tech University MATH 4033: Elementary Modern Algebra Dr. Marcel B. Finan

Arkansas Tech University MATH 4033: Elementary Modern Algebra Dr. Marcel B. Finan Arkansas Tech University MATH 4033: Elementary Modern Algebra Dr. Marcel B. Finan 3 Binary Operations We are used to addition and multiplication of real numbers. These operations combine two real numbers

More information

Quotient Rings and Field Extensions

Quotient Rings and Field Extensions Chapter 5 Quotient Rings and Field Extensions In this chapter we describe a method for producing field extension of a given field. If F is a field, then a field extension is a field K that contains F.

More information

Vector and Matrix Norms

Vector and Matrix Norms Chapter 1 Vector and Matrix Norms 11 Vector Spaces Let F be a field (such as the real numbers, R, or complex numbers, C) with elements called scalars A Vector Space, V, over the field F is a non-empty

More information

CS 103X: Discrete Structures Homework Assignment 3 Solutions

CS 103X: Discrete Structures Homework Assignment 3 Solutions CS 103X: Discrete Structures Homework Assignment 3 s Exercise 1 (20 points). On well-ordering and induction: (a) Prove the induction principle from the well-ordering principle. (b) Prove the well-ordering

More information

THE BANACH CONTRACTION PRINCIPLE. Contents

THE BANACH CONTRACTION PRINCIPLE. Contents THE BANACH CONTRACTION PRINCIPLE ALEX PONIECKI Abstract. This paper will study contractions of metric spaces. To do this, we will mainly use tools from topology. We will give some examples of contractions,

More information

Metric Spaces. Chapter 1

Metric Spaces. Chapter 1 Chapter 1 Metric Spaces Many of the arguments you have seen in several variable calculus are almost identical to the corresponding arguments in one variable calculus, especially arguments concerning convergence

More information

Notes on Richard Dedekind s Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?

Notes on Richard Dedekind s Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? Notes on Richard Dedekind s Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? David E. Joyce, Clark University December 2005 Contents Introduction 2 I. Sets and their elements. 2 II. Functions on a set. 5 III. One-to-one

More information

TOPOLOGY: THE JOURNEY INTO SEPARATION AXIOMS

TOPOLOGY: THE JOURNEY INTO SEPARATION AXIOMS TOPOLOGY: THE JOURNEY INTO SEPARATION AXIOMS VIPUL NAIK Abstract. In this journey, we are going to explore the so called separation axioms in greater detail. We shall try to understand how these axioms

More information

Group Theory. Contents

Group Theory. Contents Group Theory Contents Chapter 1: Review... 2 Chapter 2: Permutation Groups and Group Actions... 3 Orbits and Transitivity... 6 Specific Actions The Right regular and coset actions... 8 The Conjugation

More information

Solutions to In-Class Problems Week 4, Mon.

Solutions to In-Class Problems Week 4, Mon. Massachusetts Institute of Technology 6.042J/18.062J, Fall 05: Mathematics for Computer Science September 26 Prof. Albert R. Meyer and Prof. Ronitt Rubinfeld revised September 26, 2005, 1050 minutes Solutions

More information

Matrix Algebra. Some Basic Matrix Laws. Before reading the text or the following notes glance at the following list of basic matrix algebra laws.

Matrix Algebra. Some Basic Matrix Laws. Before reading the text or the following notes glance at the following list of basic matrix algebra laws. Matrix Algebra A. Doerr Before reading the text or the following notes glance at the following list of basic matrix algebra laws. Some Basic Matrix Laws Assume the orders of the matrices are such that

More information

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces Dan Collins The textbook defines a subspace of a vector space in Chapter 4, but it avoids ever discussing the notion of a quotient space. This is understandable

More information

Mathematical Induction

Mathematical Induction Mathematical Induction In logic, we often want to prove that every member of an infinite set has some feature. E.g., we would like to show: N 1 : is a number 1 : has the feature Φ ( x)(n 1 x! 1 x) How

More information

E3: PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS lecture notes

E3: PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS lecture notes E3: PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS lecture notes 2 Contents 1 PROBABILITY THEORY 7 1.1 Experiments and random events............................ 7 1.2 Certain event. Impossible event............................

More information

Duality of linear conic problems

Duality of linear conic problems Duality of linear conic problems Alexander Shapiro and Arkadi Nemirovski Abstract It is well known that the optimal values of a linear programming problem and its dual are equal to each other if at least

More information

THIN GROUPS OF FRACTIONS

THIN GROUPS OF FRACTIONS Contemporary Mathematics THIN GROUPS OF FRACTIONS Patrick DEHORNOY Abstract. A number of properties of spherical Artin Tits groups extend to Garside groups, defined as the groups of fractions of monoids

More information

26 Ideals and Quotient Rings

26 Ideals and Quotient Rings Arkansas Tech University MATH 4033: Elementary Modern Algebra Dr. Marcel B. Finan 26 Ideals and Quotient Rings In this section we develop some theory of rings that parallels the theory of groups discussed

More information

Some Special Artex Spaces Over Bi-monoids

Some Special Artex Spaces Over Bi-monoids Some Special Artex Spaces Over Bi-monoids K.Muthukumaran (corresponding auther) Assistant Professor PG and Research Department Of Mathematics, Saraswathi Narayanan College, Perungudi Madurai-625022,Tamil

More information

Mathematical Induction

Mathematical Induction Mathematical Induction (Handout March 8, 01) The Principle of Mathematical Induction provides a means to prove infinitely many statements all at once The principle is logical rather than strictly mathematical,

More information

Lemma 5.2. Let S be a set. (1) Let f and g be two permutations of S. Then the composition of f and g is a permutation of S.

Lemma 5.2. Let S be a set. (1) Let f and g be two permutations of S. Then the composition of f and g is a permutation of S. Definition 51 Let S be a set bijection f : S S 5 Permutation groups A permutation of S is simply a Lemma 52 Let S be a set (1) Let f and g be two permutations of S Then the composition of f and g is a

More information

EMBEDDING COUNTABLE PARTIAL ORDERINGS IN THE DEGREES

EMBEDDING COUNTABLE PARTIAL ORDERINGS IN THE DEGREES EMBEDDING COUNTABLE PARTIAL ORDERINGS IN THE ENUMERATION DEGREES AND THE ω-enumeration DEGREES MARIYA I. SOSKOVA AND IVAN N. SOSKOV 1. Introduction One of the most basic measures of the complexity of a

More information

The Banach-Tarski Paradox

The Banach-Tarski Paradox University of Oslo MAT2 Project The Banach-Tarski Paradox Author: Fredrik Meyer Supervisor: Nadia S. Larsen Abstract In its weak form, the Banach-Tarski paradox states that for any ball in R, it is possible

More information

ZORN S LEMMA AND SOME APPLICATIONS

ZORN S LEMMA AND SOME APPLICATIONS ZORN S LEMMA AND SOME APPLICATIONS KEITH CONRAD 1. Introduction Zorn s lemma is a result in set theory that appears in proofs of some non-constructive existence theorems throughout mathematics. We will

More information

DEFINABLE TYPES IN PRESBURGER ARITHMETIC

DEFINABLE TYPES IN PRESBURGER ARITHMETIC DEFINABLE TYPES IN PRESBURGER ARITHMETIC GABRIEL CONANT Abstract. We consider the first order theory of (Z, +,

More information

5. Linear algebra I: dimension

5. Linear algebra I: dimension 5. Linear algebra I: dimension 5.1 Some simple results 5.2 Bases and dimension 5.3 Homomorphisms and dimension 1. Some simple results Several observations should be made. Once stated explicitly, the proofs

More information

k, then n = p2α 1 1 pα k

k, then n = p2α 1 1 pα k Powers of Integers An integer n is a perfect square if n = m for some integer m. Taking into account the prime factorization, if m = p α 1 1 pα k k, then n = pα 1 1 p α k k. That is, n is a perfect square

More information

THE SEARCH FOR NATURAL DEFINABILITY IN THE TURING DEGREES

THE SEARCH FOR NATURAL DEFINABILITY IN THE TURING DEGREES THE SEARCH FOR NATURAL DEFINABILITY IN THE TURING DEGREES ANDREW E.M. LEWIS 1. Introduction This will be a course on the Turing degrees. We shall assume very little background knowledge: familiarity with

More information

it is easy to see that α = a

it is easy to see that α = a 21. Polynomial rings Let us now turn out attention to determining the prime elements of a polynomial ring, where the coefficient ring is a field. We already know that such a polynomial ring is a UF. Therefore

More information

1 Local Brouwer degree

1 Local Brouwer degree 1 Local Brouwer degree Let D R n be an open set and f : S R n be continuous, D S and c R n. Suppose that the set f 1 (c) D is compact. (1) Then the local Brouwer degree of f at c in the set D is defined.

More information

Commutative Algebra Notes Introduction to Commutative Algebra Atiyah & Macdonald

Commutative Algebra Notes Introduction to Commutative Algebra Atiyah & Macdonald Commutative Algebra Notes Introduction to Commutative Algebra Atiyah & Macdonald Adam Boocher 1 Rings and Ideals 1.1 Rings and Ring Homomorphisms A commutative ring A with identity is a set with two binary

More information

WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT?

WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT? WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT? introduction Many students seem to have trouble with the notion of a mathematical proof. People that come to a course like Math 216, who certainly

More information

Notes on Algebraic Structures. Peter J. Cameron

Notes on Algebraic Structures. Peter J. Cameron Notes on Algebraic Structures Peter J. Cameron ii Preface These are the notes of the second-year course Algebraic Structures I at Queen Mary, University of London, as I taught it in the second semester

More information

CONTENTS 1. Peter Kahn. Spring 2007

CONTENTS 1. Peter Kahn. Spring 2007 CONTENTS 1 MATH 304: CONSTRUCTING THE REAL NUMBERS Peter Kahn Spring 2007 Contents 2 The Integers 1 2.1 The basic construction.......................... 1 2.2 Adding integers..............................

More information

FIBER PRODUCTS AND ZARISKI SHEAVES

FIBER PRODUCTS AND ZARISKI SHEAVES FIBER PRODUCTS AND ZARISKI SHEAVES BRIAN OSSERMAN 1. Fiber products and Zariski sheaves We recall the definition of a fiber product: Definition 1.1. Let C be a category, and X, Y, Z objects of C. Fix also

More information

9. Quotient Groups Given a group G and a subgroup H, under what circumstances can we find a homomorphism φ: G G ', such that H is the kernel of φ?

9. Quotient Groups Given a group G and a subgroup H, under what circumstances can we find a homomorphism φ: G G ', such that H is the kernel of φ? 9. Quotient Groups Given a group G and a subgroup H, under what circumstances can we find a homomorphism φ: G G ', such that H is the kernel of φ? Clearly a necessary condition is that H is normal in G.

More information

Solutions to TOPICS IN ALGEBRA I.N. HERSTEIN. Part II: Group Theory

Solutions to TOPICS IN ALGEBRA I.N. HERSTEIN. Part II: Group Theory Solutions to TOPICS IN ALGEBRA I.N. HERSTEIN Part II: Group Theory No rights reserved. Any part of this work can be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means. Version: 1.1 Release: Jan 2013

More information

Equality and dependent type theory. Oberwolfach, March 2 (with some later corrections)

Equality and dependent type theory. Oberwolfach, March 2 (with some later corrections) Oberwolfach, March 2 (with some later corrections) The Axiom of Univalence, a type-theoretic view point In type theory, we reduce proof-checking to type-checking Hence we want type-checking to be decidable

More information

Handout #1: Mathematical Reasoning

Handout #1: Mathematical Reasoning Math 101 Rumbos Spring 2010 1 Handout #1: Mathematical Reasoning 1 Propositional Logic A proposition is a mathematical statement that it is either true or false; that is, a statement whose certainty or

More information

ABSTRACT ALGEBRA: A STUDY GUIDE FOR BEGINNERS

ABSTRACT ALGEBRA: A STUDY GUIDE FOR BEGINNERS ABSTRACT ALGEBRA: A STUDY GUIDE FOR BEGINNERS John A. Beachy Northern Illinois University 2014 ii J.A.Beachy This is a supplement to Abstract Algebra, Third Edition by John A. Beachy and William D. Blair

More information

GENTLY KILLING S SPACES TODD EISWORTH, PETER NYIKOS, AND SAHARON SHELAH

GENTLY KILLING S SPACES TODD EISWORTH, PETER NYIKOS, AND SAHARON SHELAH GENTLY KILLING S SPACES TODD EISWORTH, PETER NYIKOS, AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We produce a model of ZFC in which there are no locally compact first countable S spaces, and in which 2 ℵ 0 < 2 ℵ 1. A

More information

A Topology Primer. Preface. Lecture Notes 2001/2002. Klaus Wirthmüller. http://www.mathematik.uni-kl.de/ wirthm/de/top.html

A Topology Primer. Preface. Lecture Notes 2001/2002. Klaus Wirthmüller. http://www.mathematik.uni-kl.de/ wirthm/de/top.html A Topology Primer Lecture Notes 2001/2002 Klaus Wirthmüller http://www.mathematik.uni-kl.de/ wirthm/de/top.html Preface These lecture notes were written to accompany my introductory courses of topology

More information

A domain of spacetime intervals in general relativity

A domain of spacetime intervals in general relativity A domain of spacetime intervals in general relativity Keye Martin Department of Mathematics Tulane University New Orleans, LA 70118 United States of America martin@math.tulane.edu Prakash Panangaden School

More information

SMALL SKEW FIELDS CÉDRIC MILLIET

SMALL SKEW FIELDS CÉDRIC MILLIET SMALL SKEW FIELDS CÉDRIC MILLIET Abstract A division ring of positive characteristic with countably many pure types is a field Wedderburn showed in 1905 that finite fields are commutative As for infinite

More information

Finite Projective demorgan Algebras. honoring Jorge Martínez

Finite Projective demorgan Algebras. honoring Jorge Martínez Finite Projective demorgan Algebras Simone Bova Vanderbilt University (Nashville TN, USA) joint work with Leonardo Cabrer March 11-13, 2011 Vanderbilt University (Nashville TN, USA) honoring Jorge Martínez

More information

MATH10212 Linear Algebra. Systems of Linear Equations. Definition. An n-dimensional vector is a row or a column of n numbers (or letters): a 1.

MATH10212 Linear Algebra. Systems of Linear Equations. Definition. An n-dimensional vector is a row or a column of n numbers (or letters): a 1. MATH10212 Linear Algebra Textbook: D. Poole, Linear Algebra: A Modern Introduction. Thompson, 2006. ISBN 0-534-40596-7. Systems of Linear Equations Definition. An n-dimensional vector is a row or a column

More information

Lecture 16 : Relations and Functions DRAFT

Lecture 16 : Relations and Functions DRAFT CS/Math 240: Introduction to Discrete Mathematics 3/29/2011 Lecture 16 : Relations and Functions Instructor: Dieter van Melkebeek Scribe: Dalibor Zelený DRAFT In Lecture 3, we described a correspondence

More information

TOPIC 4: DERIVATIVES

TOPIC 4: DERIVATIVES TOPIC 4: DERIVATIVES 1. The derivative of a function. Differentiation rules 1.1. The slope of a curve. The slope of a curve at a point P is a measure of the steepness of the curve. If Q is a point on the

More information

Introduction to Modern Algebra

Introduction to Modern Algebra Introduction to Modern Algebra David Joyce Clark University Version 0.0.6, 3 Oct 2008 1 1 Copyright (C) 2008. ii I dedicate this book to my friend and colleague Arthur Chou. Arthur encouraged me to write

More information

Point Set Topology. A. Topological Spaces and Continuous Maps

Point Set Topology. A. Topological Spaces and Continuous Maps Point Set Topology A. Topological Spaces and Continuous Maps Definition 1.1 A topology on a set X is a collection T of subsets of X satisfying the following axioms: T 1.,X T. T2. {O α α I} T = α IO α T.

More information

How To Prove The Dirichlet Unit Theorem

How To Prove The Dirichlet Unit Theorem Chapter 6 The Dirichlet Unit Theorem As usual, we will be working in the ring B of algebraic integers of a number field L. Two factorizations of an element of B are regarded as essentially the same if

More information

Lecture 13 - Basic Number Theory.

Lecture 13 - Basic Number Theory. Lecture 13 - Basic Number Theory. Boaz Barak March 22, 2010 Divisibility and primes Unless mentioned otherwise throughout this lecture all numbers are non-negative integers. We say that A divides B, denoted

More information

MODELS OF SET THEORY

MODELS OF SET THEORY MODELS OF SET THEORY STEFAN GESCHKE Contents 1. First order logic and the axioms of set theory 2 1.1. Syntax 2 1.2. Semantics 2 1.3. Completeness, compactness and consistency 3 1.4. Foundations of mathematics

More information