Section 2.6 Cantor s Theorem and the ZFC Axioms

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Section 2.6 Cantor s Theorem and the ZFC Axioms"

Transcription

1 1 Section 2.6 and the ZFC Axioms Purpose of Section: To state and prove Cantor theorem, which guarantees the existence of infinities larger than the cardinality of the continuum. We also state and discuss and Zermelo-Frankel axioms and the Axiom of Choice. Introduction Cantor must have felt he was on a great adventure. He had found sets of infinite size, some countable with cardinality ℵ and some uncountable with cardinality c. He then wondered if there were larger sets. That is a larger infinities than the continuum. Cantor s Discovery of Larger Sets Often little ideas lead to big ideas. We have seen that for finite sets the power set of a set is always larger than the set itself. For example, the set A = a, b, c has three elements, whereas the power set has ( ) = φ,,,,{, },{, },{, },{,, } P A a b c a b a c b c a b c = elements. In other words, for finite sets A we have A P ( A) <. This prompted Cantor to ask if the same principle was at work for infinite sets. This question was answered in the affirmative by the following theorem. Theorem 1 () 1 () The power set ( ) strictly larger cardinality than the set A. P A of any set A has a Proof: As for many of Cantor s theorems, the proof proceeds by contradiction. The assumption that there exists a one-to-one correspondence between A and P ( A ) leads to a contradiction. We first prove the result when A is countable, which allows one to get a good visual grasp of the proof. We then prove the result uncountable sets. If A = N = A is countable, then without any loss of generality we let 1,2,3,..., our favorite infinite countable set, and assume there exists a one-to-one correspondence N P( N ). To get a good feel for the proof, we list a few elements of P ( N ) : ( N ) P =, 3, 6, 3,5, 7, 5,9,13, 9,11,15,...,...

2 2 and attempt to pair off elements of N with elements of P ( N ) as shown in Table 1: N c( N ) 1 { 3,5 } 2 { 1,2,7 } 3 { 9,13,2 } 4 { 1,5,6 } 5 { 2,5,11, 23 } Trial Pairing of the Natural Numbers and Its Power Set Table 1 Note that the numbers 1,3,4 are not members of the subset which they are paired with, while 2 and 5 do belong to the sets in which they are paired. We call the numbers 1,3,4 uncaptured numbers, and the numbers 2 and 5 captured numbers. We now create a rogue subset of the natural numbers (a member of P ( N ) ) that is not matched with any natural number, thus contradicting the fact there is a one-to-one correspondence between N and P N. This rogue set is the set of all unmatched numbers. its power set ( ) That is { : does not belong to the set it is matched to} U = n N n In our correspondences in Table 1, we have U = { 1,3,4,... }. But U is a subset of natural numbers so it must be paired with some natural number, say, let s say n U as we have illustrated in Table 2. N c( N ) 1 { 3,5 } 2 { 1,2,7 } 3 { 9,13,2 } U = 1,3,4,..., n,... n n U or n U? Table 2

3 3 =? If you say n U We now ask the question? Is n U { uncaptured numbers} that means n is an uncaptured number, but n U { 1,3, 4,..., n,... } = that means n is captured or n U, which contradicts n U. On the other hand if you say n U n U = 1,3, 4,... which that means n is an captured number, but means n is uncaptured or n U, which contradicts n U. In either case a P N P N. But we can t contradiction. Hence, we conclude that N ( N ). ( ) have P ( N) < N since the power set P ( N ) contains the singletons m of members m N, and these singletons form a copy inside P ( N ) of elements of N, and so the only remaining possibility is N < P ( N ), which proves Cantor s theorem for countable sets. Uncountable Sets: The proof for uncountable sets is the basically same as for countable sets; we just don t have the nice pictures to help with our understanding. Let f be any function from a set A to its power set P ( A ). We show that f is not onto the power set by exhibiting a subset of A not in the range of f. The subset we find is our rogue set discussed earlier: { : ( )} ( ) U = x A x f x P A. To show U is not in the range of f, suppose U is in the range of f. This means that for some y A, we have f ( y) U. Now ask whether y U or y U. If y U then y f ( y), but that implies, by definition of U, that y U. On the other hand if y U, then y f ( y) and therefore y U. In both cases whether y U or y U we arrive at a contradiction. Hence, we cannot assume that f maps A onto its power set. Hence, Cantor s theorem is proven for an arbitrary infinite sets 1. Margin Note: Cantor presented the proof of what we now call Cantor s Theorem in 1891 Űber eine elemenare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre, which was the first appearance of Cantor s Diagonal argument, used in the proof that the real numbers are uncountable. Summary: Since the power set of a set, finite or infinite, always has more members than the set itself, it is always possible to find a set with larger cardinality by simply taking the power set of a given set. Thus, one can obtain a sequence of sets having larger and larger infinities ad infinitum 1 We set is interpreted using the Zermelo-Frankel axioms of set theory. We have seen that logical paradoxes arise when sets are chosen without regard to any conditions.

4 4. ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ) ( ( )) ℵ = N < P N < P P N < P P P N < all uncountable except for smallest infinity ℵ. Cantor called these infinite numbers transfinite numbers, which means numbers larger than the finite numbers. Since Cantor s theorem implies that for every set there is a greater set, from which it follows there is not set of all sets. That is, there is no set of everything 2. Now that we know the power set of the natural numbers is larger than the natural numbers itself, just how big is it? The following theorem answers that question. Theorem 2 ( c P( ) = N ) The cardinality of the power set of natural numbers is equal to the cardinality of the real numbers. That is c P( ) = N. Proof Since the real numbers and the open interval (,1 ) both have the same cardinality ( c ), we find a one-to-one correspondence P ( N ) (,1). We first make the observation that any real number x (,1) can be expressed in binary decimal form x =. b b b where each b j is or 1. For example x =.111 = = We now associate to each real number x =. b1b 2 the subset of natural numbers consisting of the indices j for which b j = 1. For example, we associate. x =.111 1,3, 4,... x = ,3,5,6,... x = ,2,3,5,... which gives a one-to-one correspondence (,1) P ( ) N. We denote 2 ℵ to stand for the cardinality of the power set of the natural numbers, which from Example 1 we have seen is the cardinality of the continuum, i.e. ℵ c = 2. 2 The great German mathematician David Hilbert said in 191 that "No one shall drive us from the paradise which Cantor created. Later in 1926 Hilbert is quoted as saying "It appears to me to be the most admirable flower of the mathematical intellect and one of the highest achievements of purely rational human activity."

5 5 If we now call ℵ 1 the next larger infinite number after ℵ, an interesting question arises. We know ℵ is the smallest infinity and that the numbers have a larger cardinality c, but are we sure there isn t an infinite number between the two. In other words, is there some mystery set (or sets) M that have cardinality larger than ℵ but less than c. In other words ℵ < M < c. Stated another way, is c = ℵ 1? Cantor believed the assertion was true but was never able to prove or disprove it. Cantor called the hypothesis c = ℵ 1 the continuum hypothesis and went to his death not resolving the question. A proof of the continuum hypothesis would confirm that the continuum c is the smallest uncountable set and would bridge the gap between the countable and uncountable. After Cantor s death, due to the paradoxes of Bertrand Russell and others, various logicians, such as Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, placed the study of sets on a firm foundation with the introduction of a set of axioms. In 1938 under the framework of these axioms, the Austrian logician Kurt Godel ( ) proved that the continuum hypothesis can safely be assumed true since he proved it can t be proven false 3. This means that it can be added as an axiom to the existing axioms of set theory without introducing any inconsistencies that were not already present. Although this discovery was significant, it was not the last word since he didn t prove the hypothesis was true, nor did he prove it was independent of the axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF). This later question was resolved in 1963 by the American logician Paul J. Cohen who proved that the continuum hypothesis is independent of the axioms of set theory, the net result being that Cantor s continuum hypothesis c = ℵ 1 is undecidable, meaning that anyone can accept it as true or accept it as false. If taken as a true axiom (along with the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms), the resulting theory is called Cantorian set theory, while if assumed false, the theory is called non-cantorian set theory). In either case, one has a valid set of axioms, albeit much different. Very strange indeed 4! The generalized continuum hypothesis, also proposed by Cantor, has piqued the interest of set theorists and logicians for 1 years. It states that for any infinite set A there is no infinite set whose cardinality is between the cardinality of A and the cardinality of its power set P ( A ). Symbolically, it states ℵα ℵ + 1 = 2, α = 1,2,... α Margin Note: Cantor s theory does test one s intuition, knowing his theory is able to prove that a line segment a thousand light years in length contains the 3 In other words consistent with the Zermelo Fraenkel axioms. 4 Most logicians accept Cantorian set theory..

6 6 same number of points, not one more or one less, than a line the width of an electron. Hmmmmmm Since there are a finite number of letters in the alphabet, one can show the number of possible names for things is denumerable. But there are sets that are uncountable, which means there are sets which cannot be named. Example 2 (Cardinality of Sequences) Solution Show that the set of all sequences of s and 1 s has cardinality c. Consider two the typical sequences of s and 1 s Sequence 1: ( ) Sequence 2: ( ) where the dots at the end of the sequences mean all remaining members of the sequences are zero. In other words Sequence 1 has 1 s in the 1 st, 4 th, and 6 th position and zeros elsewhere. Sequence 2 has 1 s in the 3 rd, 5 th, 6 th, and 9 th positions and zeros elsewhere. Taking note of the positions of the 1 s, we can match any sequence of s and 1 s subsets of the natural numbers. 1,4,6 and we can For example, Sequence 1 can be matched with the set match Sequence 2 with { 3,5,6,9 }. Hence, the family of sequences of s and 1 s can be matched in a one-to-one manner with the power set of N, i.e. family of all subsets of natural numbers. See Figure 1. We will see in Section 2.6 that the family of subsets of N has cardinality of the continuum c. Sequence of s and 1 s Subset of N 1,4,7 ( ) ( ) { 1,2,3,8 } ( 1... ) { 3 } (... ) One-to-One Correspondence Figure 1 Everyday Sets Larger than the Continuum The question now occurs, are there sets familiar to the ordinary mathematician whose cardinality larger than

7 7 the cardinality of the continuum? One example is given by Theorem 3, which we state and hint at its proof. Theorem 3: The set of all real-valued functions defined on ( ) cardinality larger than c. The cardinality of this set is ℵ 2 Proof,1 has Again, the proof is by contradiction, similar to the proof of Cantor s theorem. We assume we can match every real number in (,1) with a realvalued function on (,1 ). We then construct a rogue function not on the list, which contradicts the our assumption that such a correspondence exists. Need for Axioms in Set Theory The reader should not entertain the belief that Cantor was the first mathematician to think about sets and their operations, such as union, intersection and compliment. The concept of a set has been known for centuries. What Cantor did was to introduce the formal study of sets and in particular a deep analysis of infinite sets and their many unexpected properties. Although Cantor produced many deep ideas, his interpretation of a set was intuitive. That is, to him a set was simply a collection of objects. It was Bertrand Russell who upset that view of sets with his 192 discovery, called Russell s Paradox, which showed that the naïve view of a set as any collection of objects leads to contradictions. Thus, it became clear in order to have a consistent theory of sets (no contradictions), one must formalize the study of sets with rules of the game. That is, axioms. So for the first time in the history of humankind, the most basic of all mathematical disciplines was formulated into a set of guidelines for operation. Russell s Paradox Russell s paradox is the most famous of all set-theoretic paradoxes which arises in naïve set theory and motivates the need for an axiomatic foundation for set theory. The paradox was constructed by English logician Bertrand Russell ( ), who proposed a family of set R consisting of all sets who do not contain themselves. He then asked whether the family R was itself a member of R. If R R, i.e. R contains R, then we have a contradiction since R is made up of sets that do not contain themselves. On the other hand if R R, this is also a contradiction since R contains all sets that do not contain themselves which means R R. Hence, we are left with the contradictory statement R R R R Hence, we must restrict the meaning of a set from the naïve point of view which says a set is an arbitrary collection of elements.

8 8 Zermelo-Fraenkel Axioms The most commonly accepted axioms of set theory are the Zermelo- Fraenkel 5 axioms (ZFC) axioms, developed by German logicians Ernst Zermelo ( ) and Abraham Fraenkel ( ). Zermelo 6 conceived of providing a consistent set of axioms, like those of plane geometry, which restricts the wide latitude of Cantor s interpretation of a set, thus avoiding the bad things, like Russell s paradox, but allows enough objects to be taken as sets for ordinary use in mathematics. The C in ZFC refers to the Axiom of Choice, the most controversial and debated of the ten ZFC axioms. Although there is no agreed upon names for each of the 1 axioms, and they are often written in varying notation, we have settled on the following list. Zermelo-Fraenkel Axioms 7 1. Existence of a Set (sets exist) There exists a set (albeit one with no elements). That is, there is a set A such that ( x)( x A) Comment: This set is called the empty set and denoted by. This axiom says that the whole theory defined by these 1 axioms is not vacuous by stating at least one set exists. 2. Axiom of Equality (equality defined) Two sets are equal if and only if they have the same members. That is for all sets A, B ( A = B) ( x)( x A x B) Comment: The Axiom of Equality (often called the Axiom of Extension) defines what it means for two sets to be equal. The first two axioms say that the empty set (guaranteed by Axiom 1) is unique. 5 There are other axioms of set theory than the ZFC axioms, such as the Von Neumann-Bernays-Godel axioms (which are logically equivalent to ZFC) and the Morse-Kelly axioms, which are stronger than ZF. 6 Zermelo published his original axioms in 198 and were modified in 1922 by Fraenkel and Skolem, and thus today are called the Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) axioms. 7 Zermelo s original axioms were stated in the language of second-order logic: i.e. sets were quantified (like ( A),( A) ) in addition to variables. There are versions of the ZFC axioms that use only first-order logic, but for convenience we have quantified sets in a few instances.

9 9 3. Axiom of Sets of Size One (singletons exist) For any a and b there is a a, b, that contains exactly a and b. That is set, denoted by ( a)( b)( A)( z) z { a, b} ( z = x) ( z = y) Comment: If we pick a = b then the axiom implies there exists sets with one a. Note that the existential quantifier A quantifies a set, which is element not allowed in first-order predicate logic. 4. Axiom of Union of Sets (unions of sets exist) We have unions of sets. For any collection of sets F = { A α }, there exists a set Y A α Λ = α, called the union of all sets in F. That is ( F )( A)( x) ( x A) ( C F )( x C ) Comment: From Axioms 3 and 4, we can construct finite sets. (We are making progress.) α Λ 5. Power Set Axiom (power sets exist) set B (think power set) such that That is for any set A there exists a X A X B 6. Axiom of Infinity (infinite sets exists) There exists a set A (think infinite) such that ( A) ( x)( x A) ( x { x} ) A Comment: This axiom creates numbers A = {,1, 2,3,... } correspondence: =, 1 = { }, 2 = { 1}, 3 { 2 } conclude that the set of natural numbers exist. according to the =, and so on. From this we 7. Correct Sets Axiom (axiom that avoids Russell s Paradox) Correct Sets Axiom (axiom that avoids Russell s Paradox) If ( ) predicate and A any set, then { x A: P( x) } p x is a defines a set, i.e. the set of elements for which the predicate P ( x ) is true. The key point is that the set { x A: P( x) } is a subset of a previously defined set A, which rules out sets of the form { x : x x} which is the Russell

10 1 paradoxical set. Axiom 7 is what is called an axiom schema, which means it is really an infinite number of axioms, one for each predicate P ( x ). 8. Image of Sets are Sets The image of a set under a function is again a set. That is, if A, B are sets and f : A B is a function with domain A and codomain B, then the image f ( A) y B : y f ( x) be defined in terms of sets as the set of ordered pairs = = is a set. (A function can {( a, b) A B : f ( a) = b} 9. Axiom of Regularity (no set can be an element of itself) Every non-empty set has an element that is disjoint from the set. That is for any set ( A ) ( x) ( x A) ( x A = ) Comment: As an example if A { a, b, c} " a " where we observe a { a, b, c} =. Note { a} { a, b, c} { a} a { a, b, c} contain themselves, like A = { 1, 2,3, A} = then we can pick our element to be = but =. What this axiom accomplishes is to keep out sets that 1. Axiom of Choice Given any collection of non-overlapping, nonempty sets, it is possible to choose one element from each set. Comments: This is an existence axiom that claims the existence of a set formed from picking one element from a collection of non-empty sets. The objection to this axiom lies in the fact that the axiom provides no rule for how the items are selected from the sets, simply that it can be done. Comments on the t Axiom of Choice A group of mathematicians are attending a buffet dinner and while they pass through the dessert line containing plates full of different kinds of cookies, one mathematician says she will appeal to the Axiom of Choice and selects one cookie from each plate. That s it, that s the Axiom of Choice. The Axiom of Choice says given a family of nonempty sets (plates of cookies) it is possible to select one member from each set. So what s the big fuss over AC? It seems so trivial. But what happens if there are an infinite number of plates, maybe uncountable? Of course if each plate has a biggest cookie, there is an obvious way to pick one cookie from each plate. Pick the biggest cookie. In

11 11 that case one doesn t have to apply the Axiom of Choice. But what if the cookies on each plate look exactly alike, then how do you go about selecting a cookie from each plate? What is your rule of selection? Can you write it on a piece of paper? Of course not. However, there is a rule and we know this since the Axiom of Choice says so. The Axiom of Choice is a pure existence axiom and for that reason it is a bone of contention for many mathematicians who prefer a constructive method for selecting the desired set. There are good consequences and bad consequences proven when adopting the Axiom of Choice (AC). A good result is the proof of Tychonoff s theorem in topology, which states that the product of an arbitrary family of compact topological spaces is compact. On the negative side, a few bad results can be proven if one adopts AC as an axiom (along with the other axioms of ZF) and one is the existence of a non-measurable set in measure theory. And last but not least is the rather disconcerting paradox known as the Banach ach Tarski Paradox, which states roughly that any sphere can be decomposed into a finite number of disjoint pieces and then reassembled as two spheres identical in size to the original. Of course, don t try that at home, since the procedure appeals to AC, which means it is a pure existence result with no constructive way to show how its done. That s the nature of results that apply to AC, one arrives somewhere without knowing how one got there. Recently, logicians have tried to find a compromise for AC and seek for new axioms 8 which produces good theorems but does not lead to unwanted consequences 9. Bertrand Russell s Shoe Model for AC Bertrand Russell once gave an intuitive reason why sometimes the Axiom of Choice is required and sometimes when it is not. Suppose you are supplied with an infinite number of pairs of shoes and asked to find a selection rule for picking one shoe from each pair. In this case no Axiom of Choice is required, since you can simply the left shoe (or right) from each pair. On the other, suppose you are supplied with an infinite pair of socks and asked the same question. The socks look alike so you are unable to provide a rule of selection for choosing a sock from each pair. But the Axiom of Choice comes to the rescue, which says there is such a rule, although not explicitly stated, which specifies how to select the socks. It is the non constructive aspect of the axiom that causes angst to some mathematicians and logicians. To some pure intuitionists, the word exists belongs more to religion and not mathematics. 8 See Hamilton, A.G Numbers, Sets and Axioms, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. 9 As the American geometer Oswald Veblen once said, The test of any axiom system lies in the theorems it produces.

12 12 Axiom of Choice Well-Ordering Principle When Zermelo introduced the Axiom of Choice, most mathematicians accepted it and never gave it a second thought 1. However, in 195 Zermelo proved a theorem that gave everyone second thoughts. He proved that the Axiom of Choice was equivalent to what came to be known as the Well- Ordered Principle. We are getting ahead of ourselves since we don t introduce order relations until Chapter 3, but roughly a set is well-ordered if there is an ordering of elements of the set in such a way that every non-empty set has N = 1,2,3,... are well- a smallest element. For example the natural numbers ordered by the usual 1 < 2 < 3 < The Well-Ordered Principle says that any non-empty set can be well-ordered by some order relation. As an example the principle says a well-ordering exists for the real numbers, although no one has ever exhibited one, which leads one to suspect the axiom as false. Although intuitively the axiom seems hard to believe, Zermelo proved it is equivalent to the Axiom of Choice, which seems obvious. It is a rather strange situation and has caused logicians a great deal of thought. 1 However, many of the foremost mathematicians of the day did object to the axiom, including measure theory analysts Henri Lebesgue and Emile Borel.

13 13 Problems 1. Prove that if we add a member to a denumerable set, we still have a denumerable set. 2. Show that the set of all sequences of s and 1 s has cardinality c. Hint: Relate each sequence of s and 1 s to a subset of natural numbers and then use Cantor s theorem. 3. Show that the set of all one-to-one correspondences between N and N is c.

So let us begin our quest to find the holy grail of real analysis.

So let us begin our quest to find the holy grail of real analysis. 1 Section 5.2 The Complete Ordered Field: Purpose of Section We present an axiomatic description of the real numbers as a complete ordered field. The axioms which describe the arithmetic of the real numbers

More information

This chapter is all about cardinality of sets. At first this looks like a

This chapter is all about cardinality of sets. At first this looks like a CHAPTER Cardinality of Sets This chapter is all about cardinality of sets At first this looks like a very simple concept To find the cardinality of a set, just count its elements If A = { a, b, c, d },

More information

This asserts two sets are equal iff they have the same elements, that is, a set is determined by its elements.

This asserts two sets are equal iff they have the same elements, that is, a set is determined by its elements. 3. Axioms of Set theory Before presenting the axioms of set theory, we first make a few basic comments about the relevant first order logic. We will give a somewhat more detailed discussion later, but

More information

3. Mathematical Induction

3. Mathematical Induction 3. MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION 83 3. Mathematical Induction 3.1. First Principle of Mathematical Induction. Let P (n) be a predicate with domain of discourse (over) the natural numbers N = {0, 1,,...}. If (1)

More information

Set Theory Basic Concepts and Definitions

Set Theory Basic Concepts and Definitions Set Theory Basic Concepts and Definitions The Importance of Set Theory One striking feature of humans is their inherent need and ability to group objects according to specific criteria. Our prehistoric

More information

Georg Cantor (1845-1918):

Georg Cantor (1845-1918): Georg Cantor (845-98): The man who tamed infinity lecture by Eric Schechter Associate Professor of Mathematics Vanderbilt University http://www.math.vanderbilt.edu/ schectex/ In papers of 873 and 874,

More information

CS 3719 (Theory of Computation and Algorithms) Lecture 4

CS 3719 (Theory of Computation and Algorithms) Lecture 4 CS 3719 (Theory of Computation and Algorithms) Lecture 4 Antonina Kolokolova January 18, 2012 1 Undecidable languages 1.1 Church-Turing thesis Let s recap how it all started. In 1990, Hilbert stated a

More information

Georg Cantor and Set Theory

Georg Cantor and Set Theory Georg Cantor and Set Theory. Life Father, Georg Waldemar Cantor, born in Denmark, successful merchant, and stock broker in St Petersburg. Mother, Maria Anna Böhm, was Russian. In 856, because of father

More information

CHAPTER 3. Methods of Proofs. 1. Logical Arguments and Formal Proofs

CHAPTER 3. Methods of Proofs. 1. Logical Arguments and Formal Proofs CHAPTER 3 Methods of Proofs 1. Logical Arguments and Formal Proofs 1.1. Basic Terminology. An axiom is a statement that is given to be true. A rule of inference is a logical rule that is used to deduce

More information

INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY

INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY INCIDENCE-BETWEENNESS GEOMETRY MATH 410, CSUSM. SPRING 2008. PROFESSOR AITKEN This document covers the geometry that can be developed with just the axioms related to incidence and betweenness. The full

More information

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products Chapter 3 Cartesian Products and Relations The material in this chapter is the first real encounter with abstraction. Relations are very general thing they are a special type of subset. After introducing

More information

Dedekind s forgotten axiom and why we should teach it (and why we shouldn t teach mathematical induction in our calculus classes)

Dedekind s forgotten axiom and why we should teach it (and why we shouldn t teach mathematical induction in our calculus classes) Dedekind s forgotten axiom and why we should teach it (and why we shouldn t teach mathematical induction in our calculus classes) by Jim Propp (UMass Lowell) March 14, 2010 1 / 29 Completeness Three common

More information

How many numbers there are?

How many numbers there are? How many numbers there are? RADEK HONZIK Radek Honzik: Charles University, Department of Logic, Celetná 20, Praha 1, 116 42, Czech Republic radek.honzik@ff.cuni.cz Contents 1 What are numbers 2 1.1 Natural

More information

Mathematical Induction

Mathematical Induction Mathematical Induction (Handout March 8, 01) The Principle of Mathematical Induction provides a means to prove infinitely many statements all at once The principle is logical rather than strictly mathematical,

More information

Set theory as a foundation for mathematics

Set theory as a foundation for mathematics V I I I : Set theory as a foundation for mathematics This material is basically supplementary, and it was not covered in the course. In the first section we discuss the basic axioms of set theory and the

More information

1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set.

1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set. 1. Prove that the empty set is a subset of every set. Basic Topology Written by Men-Gen Tsai email: b89902089@ntu.edu.tw Proof: For any element x of the empty set, x is also an element of every set since

More information

CHAPTER 7 GENERAL PROOF SYSTEMS

CHAPTER 7 GENERAL PROOF SYSTEMS CHAPTER 7 GENERAL PROOF SYSTEMS 1 Introduction Proof systems are built to prove statements. They can be thought as an inference machine with special statements, called provable statements, or sometimes

More information

The Foundations of Mathematics

The Foundations of Mathematics The Foundations of Mathematics c 2005,2006,2007 Kenneth Kunen Kenneth Kunen October 29, 2007 Contents 0 Introduction 3 0.1 Prerequisites.................................. 3 0.2 Logical Notation...............................

More information

6.3 Conditional Probability and Independence

6.3 Conditional Probability and Independence 222 CHAPTER 6. PROBABILITY 6.3 Conditional Probability and Independence Conditional Probability Two cubical dice each have a triangle painted on one side, a circle painted on two sides and a square painted

More information

God created the integers and the rest is the work of man. (Leopold Kronecker, in an after-dinner speech at a conference, Berlin, 1886)

God created the integers and the rest is the work of man. (Leopold Kronecker, in an after-dinner speech at a conference, Berlin, 1886) Chapter 2 Numbers God created the integers and the rest is the work of man. (Leopold Kronecker, in an after-dinner speech at a conference, Berlin, 1886) God created the integers and the rest is the work

More information

arxiv:0804.4490v1 [math.gm] 28 Apr 2008

arxiv:0804.4490v1 [math.gm] 28 Apr 2008 Infinite sequences in the framework of classical logic arxiv:0804.4490v1 [math.gm] 28 Apr 2008 V.V. Ivanov N.N. Semenov Institute of Chemical Physics, Russian Academy of Sciences, Kosygin str.4, Moscow,

More information

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 3. Spaces with special properties

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 3. Spaces with special properties SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR MATHEMATICS 205A Part 3 Fall 2008 III. Spaces with special properties III.1 : Compact spaces I Problems from Munkres, 26, pp. 170 172 3. Show that a finite union of compact subspaces

More information

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 2

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 2 CS 70 Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 2 Proofs Intuitively, the concept of proof should already be familiar We all like to assert things, and few of us

More information

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces

Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces Math 4310 Handout - Quotient Vector Spaces Dan Collins The textbook defines a subspace of a vector space in Chapter 4, but it avoids ever discussing the notion of a quotient space. This is understandable

More information

WRITING PROOFS. Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology

WRITING PROOFS. Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology WRITING PROOFS Christopher Heil Georgia Institute of Technology A theorem is just a statement of fact A proof of the theorem is a logical explanation of why the theorem is true Many theorems have this

More information

Mechanics 1: Vectors

Mechanics 1: Vectors Mechanics 1: Vectors roadly speaking, mechanical systems will be described by a combination of scalar and vector quantities. scalar is just a (real) number. For example, mass or weight is characterized

More information

An Innocent Investigation

An Innocent Investigation An Innocent Investigation D. Joyce, Clark University January 2006 The beginning. Have you ever wondered why every number is either even or odd? I don t mean to ask if you ever wondered whether every number

More information

INTRODUCTORY SET THEORY

INTRODUCTORY SET THEORY M.Sc. program in mathematics INTRODUCTORY SET THEORY Katalin Károlyi Department of Applied Analysis, Eötvös Loránd University H-1088 Budapest, Múzeum krt. 6-8. CONTENTS 1. SETS Set, equal sets, subset,

More information

1 if 1 x 0 1 if 0 x 1

1 if 1 x 0 1 if 0 x 1 Chapter 3 Continuity In this chapter we begin by defining the fundamental notion of continuity for real valued functions of a single real variable. When trying to decide whether a given function is or

More information

Handout #1: Mathematical Reasoning

Handout #1: Mathematical Reasoning Math 101 Rumbos Spring 2010 1 Handout #1: Mathematical Reasoning 1 Propositional Logic A proposition is a mathematical statement that it is either true or false; that is, a statement whose certainty or

More information

WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT?

WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT? WHAT ARE MATHEMATICAL PROOFS AND WHY THEY ARE IMPORTANT? introduction Many students seem to have trouble with the notion of a mathematical proof. People that come to a course like Math 216, who certainly

More information

SOLUTIONS TO ASSIGNMENT 1 MATH 576

SOLUTIONS TO ASSIGNMENT 1 MATH 576 SOLUTIONS TO ASSIGNMENT 1 MATH 576 SOLUTIONS BY OLIVIER MARTIN 13 #5. Let T be the topology generated by A on X. We want to show T = J B J where B is the set of all topologies J on X with A J. This amounts

More information

8 Divisibility and prime numbers

8 Divisibility and prime numbers 8 Divisibility and prime numbers 8.1 Divisibility In this short section we extend the concept of a multiple from the natural numbers to the integers. We also summarize several other terms that express

More information

Mathematical Induction

Mathematical Induction Mathematical Induction In logic, we often want to prove that every member of an infinite set has some feature. E.g., we would like to show: N 1 : is a number 1 : has the feature Φ ( x)(n 1 x! 1 x) How

More information

Lecture 1. Basic Concepts of Set Theory, Functions and Relations

Lecture 1. Basic Concepts of Set Theory, Functions and Relations September 7, 2005 p. 1 Lecture 1. Basic Concepts of Set Theory, Functions and Relations 0. Preliminaries...1 1. Basic Concepts of Set Theory...1 1.1. Sets and elements...1 1.2. Specification of sets...2

More information

MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 6.436J/15.085J Fall 2008 Lecture 5 9/17/2008 RANDOM VARIABLES

MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 6.436J/15.085J Fall 2008 Lecture 5 9/17/2008 RANDOM VARIABLES MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY 6.436J/15.085J Fall 2008 Lecture 5 9/17/2008 RANDOM VARIABLES Contents 1. Random variables and measurable functions 2. Cumulative distribution functions 3. Discrete

More information

CONTENTS 1. Peter Kahn. Spring 2007

CONTENTS 1. Peter Kahn. Spring 2007 CONTENTS 1 MATH 304: CONSTRUCTING THE REAL NUMBERS Peter Kahn Spring 2007 Contents 2 The Integers 1 2.1 The basic construction.......................... 1 2.2 Adding integers..............................

More information

Lecture 16 : Relations and Functions DRAFT

Lecture 16 : Relations and Functions DRAFT CS/Math 240: Introduction to Discrete Mathematics 3/29/2011 Lecture 16 : Relations and Functions Instructor: Dieter van Melkebeek Scribe: Dalibor Zelený DRAFT In Lecture 3, we described a correspondence

More information

Basic Concepts of Point Set Topology Notes for OU course Math 4853 Spring 2011

Basic Concepts of Point Set Topology Notes for OU course Math 4853 Spring 2011 Basic Concepts of Point Set Topology Notes for OU course Math 4853 Spring 2011 A. Miller 1. Introduction. The definitions of metric space and topological space were developed in the early 1900 s, largely

More information

MODELS OF SET THEORY

MODELS OF SET THEORY MODELS OF SET THEORY STEFAN GESCHKE Contents 1. First order logic and the axioms of set theory 2 1.1. Syntax 2 1.2. Semantics 2 1.3. Completeness, compactness and consistency 3 1.4. Foundations of mathematics

More information

Theory of Automated Reasoning An Introduction. Antti-Juhani Kaijanaho

Theory of Automated Reasoning An Introduction. Antti-Juhani Kaijanaho Theory of Automated Reasoning An Introduction Antti-Juhani Kaijanaho Intended as compulsory reading for the Spring 2004 course on Automated Reasononing at Department of Mathematical Information Technology,

More information

The Banach-Tarski Paradox

The Banach-Tarski Paradox University of Oslo MAT2 Project The Banach-Tarski Paradox Author: Fredrik Meyer Supervisor: Nadia S. Larsen Abstract In its weak form, the Banach-Tarski paradox states that for any ball in R, it is possible

More information

AN INTRODUCTION TO SET THEORY. Professor William A. R. Weiss

AN INTRODUCTION TO SET THEORY. Professor William A. R. Weiss AN INTRODUCTION TO SET THEORY Professor William A. R. Weiss October 2, 2008 2 Contents 0 Introduction 7 1 LOST 11 2 FOUND 19 3 The Axioms of Set Theory 23 4 The Natural Numbers 31 5 The Ordinal Numbers

More information

LEARNING OBJECTIVES FOR THIS CHAPTER

LEARNING OBJECTIVES FOR THIS CHAPTER CHAPTER 2 American mathematician Paul Halmos (1916 2006), who in 1942 published the first modern linear algebra book. The title of Halmos s book was the same as the title of this chapter. Finite-Dimensional

More information

Mathematical Induction. Mary Barnes Sue Gordon

Mathematical Induction. Mary Barnes Sue Gordon Mathematics Learning Centre Mathematical Induction Mary Barnes Sue Gordon c 1987 University of Sydney Contents 1 Mathematical Induction 1 1.1 Why do we need proof by induction?.... 1 1. What is proof by

More information

Metric Spaces Joseph Muscat 2003 (Last revised May 2009)

Metric Spaces Joseph Muscat 2003 (Last revised May 2009) 1 Distance J Muscat 1 Metric Spaces Joseph Muscat 2003 (Last revised May 2009) (A revised and expanded version of these notes are now published by Springer.) 1 Distance A metric space can be thought of

More information

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send email to: permissions@pupress.princeton.edu

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send email to: permissions@pupress.princeton.edu COPYRIGHT NOTICE: Ariel Rubinstein: Lecture Notes in Microeconomic Theory is published by Princeton University Press and copyrighted, c 2006, by Princeton University Press. All rights reserved. No part

More information

Lecture 17 : Equivalence and Order Relations DRAFT

Lecture 17 : Equivalence and Order Relations DRAFT CS/Math 240: Introduction to Discrete Mathematics 3/31/2011 Lecture 17 : Equivalence and Order Relations Instructor: Dieter van Melkebeek Scribe: Dalibor Zelený DRAFT Last lecture we introduced the notion

More information

An example of a computable

An example of a computable An example of a computable absolutely normal number Verónica Becher Santiago Figueira Abstract The first example of an absolutely normal number was given by Sierpinski in 96, twenty years before the concept

More information

Basic Concepts of Set Theory, Functions and Relations

Basic Concepts of Set Theory, Functions and Relations March 1, 2006 p. 1 Basic Concepts of Set Theory, Functions and Relations 1. Basic Concepts of Set Theory...1 1.1. Sets and elements...1 1.2. Specification of sets...2 1.3. Identity and cardinality...3

More information

Cartesian Products and Relations

Cartesian Products and Relations Cartesian Products and Relations Definition (Cartesian product) If A and B are sets, the Cartesian product of A and B is the set A B = {(a, b) :(a A) and (b B)}. The following points are worth special

More information

MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION. Mathematical Induction. This is a powerful method to prove properties of positive integers.

MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION. Mathematical Induction. This is a powerful method to prove properties of positive integers. MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION MIGUEL A LERMA (Last updated: February 8, 003) Mathematical Induction This is a powerful method to prove properties of positive integers Principle of Mathematical Induction Let P

More information

MA651 Topology. Lecture 6. Separation Axioms.

MA651 Topology. Lecture 6. Separation Axioms. MA651 Topology. Lecture 6. Separation Axioms. This text is based on the following books: Fundamental concepts of topology by Peter O Neil Elements of Mathematics: General Topology by Nicolas Bourbaki Counterexamples

More information

Sudoku puzzles and how to solve them

Sudoku puzzles and how to solve them Sudoku puzzles and how to solve them Andries E. Brouwer 2006-05-31 1 Sudoku Figure 1: Two puzzles the second one is difficult A Sudoku puzzle (of classical type ) consists of a 9-by-9 matrix partitioned

More information

Formal Languages and Automata Theory - Regular Expressions and Finite Automata -

Formal Languages and Automata Theory - Regular Expressions and Finite Automata - Formal Languages and Automata Theory - Regular Expressions and Finite Automata - Samarjit Chakraborty Computer Engineering and Networks Laboratory Swiss Federal Institute of Technology (ETH) Zürich March

More information

Cosmological Arguments for the Existence of God S. Clarke

Cosmological Arguments for the Existence of God S. Clarke Cosmological Arguments for the Existence of God S. Clarke [Modified Fall 2009] 1. Large class of arguments. Sometimes they get very complex, as in Clarke s argument, but the basic idea is simple. Lets

More information

x < y iff x < y, or x and y are incomparable and x χ(x,y) < y χ(x,y).

x < y iff x < y, or x and y are incomparable and x χ(x,y) < y χ(x,y). 12. Large cardinals The study, or use, of large cardinals is one of the most active areas of research in set theory currently. There are many provably different kinds of large cardinals whose descriptions

More information

Introduction to Topology

Introduction to Topology Introduction to Topology Tomoo Matsumura November 30, 2010 Contents 1 Topological spaces 3 1.1 Basis of a Topology......................................... 3 1.2 Comparing Topologies.......................................

More information

How To Understand The Theory Of Computer Science

How To Understand The Theory Of Computer Science Theory of Computation Lecture Notes Abhijat Vichare August 2005 Contents 1 Introduction 2 What is Computation? 3 The λ Calculus 3.1 Conversions: 3.2 The calculus in use 3.3 Few Important Theorems 3.4 Worked

More information

Mathematics for Computer Science/Software Engineering. Notes for the course MSM1F3 Dr. R. A. Wilson

Mathematics for Computer Science/Software Engineering. Notes for the course MSM1F3 Dr. R. A. Wilson Mathematics for Computer Science/Software Engineering Notes for the course MSM1F3 Dr. R. A. Wilson October 1996 Chapter 1 Logic Lecture no. 1. We introduce the concept of a proposition, which is a statement

More information

Math/Stats 425 Introduction to Probability. 1. Uncertainty and the axioms of probability

Math/Stats 425 Introduction to Probability. 1. Uncertainty and the axioms of probability Math/Stats 425 Introduction to Probability 1. Uncertainty and the axioms of probability Processes in the real world are random if outcomes cannot be predicted with certainty. Example: coin tossing, stock

More information

Pigeonhole Principle Solutions

Pigeonhole Principle Solutions Pigeonhole Principle Solutions 1. Show that if we take n + 1 numbers from the set {1, 2,..., 2n}, then some pair of numbers will have no factors in common. Solution: Note that consecutive numbers (such

More information

Automata and Formal Languages

Automata and Formal Languages Automata and Formal Languages Winter 2009-2010 Yacov Hel-Or 1 What this course is all about This course is about mathematical models of computation We ll study different machine models (finite automata,

More information

No: 10 04. Bilkent University. Monotonic Extension. Farhad Husseinov. Discussion Papers. Department of Economics

No: 10 04. Bilkent University. Monotonic Extension. Farhad Husseinov. Discussion Papers. Department of Economics No: 10 04 Bilkent University Monotonic Extension Farhad Husseinov Discussion Papers Department of Economics The Discussion Papers of the Department of Economics are intended to make the initial results

More information

TOPOLOGY: THE JOURNEY INTO SEPARATION AXIOMS

TOPOLOGY: THE JOURNEY INTO SEPARATION AXIOMS TOPOLOGY: THE JOURNEY INTO SEPARATION AXIOMS VIPUL NAIK Abstract. In this journey, we are going to explore the so called separation axioms in greater detail. We shall try to understand how these axioms

More information

Cardinality. The set of all finite strings over the alphabet of lowercase letters is countable. The set of real numbers R is an uncountable set.

Cardinality. The set of all finite strings over the alphabet of lowercase letters is countable. The set of real numbers R is an uncountable set. Section 2.5 Cardinality (another) Definition: The cardinality of a set A is equal to the cardinality of a set B, denoted A = B, if and only if there is a bijection from A to B. If there is an injection

More information

Invalidity in Predicate Logic

Invalidity in Predicate Logic Invalidity in Predicate Logic So far we ve got a method for establishing that a predicate logic argument is valid: do a derivation. But we ve got no method for establishing invalidity. In propositional

More information

Mathematical Induction. Lecture 10-11

Mathematical Induction. Lecture 10-11 Mathematical Induction Lecture 10-11 Menu Mathematical Induction Strong Induction Recursive Definitions Structural Induction Climbing an Infinite Ladder Suppose we have an infinite ladder: 1. We can reach

More information

Reading 13 : Finite State Automata and Regular Expressions

Reading 13 : Finite State Automata and Regular Expressions CS/Math 24: Introduction to Discrete Mathematics Fall 25 Reading 3 : Finite State Automata and Regular Expressions Instructors: Beck Hasti, Gautam Prakriya In this reading we study a mathematical model

More information

E3: PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS lecture notes

E3: PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS lecture notes E3: PROBABILITY AND STATISTICS lecture notes 2 Contents 1 PROBABILITY THEORY 7 1.1 Experiments and random events............................ 7 1.2 Certain event. Impossible event............................

More information

The Philosophical Implications (if any) of the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem by Peter Hollo

The Philosophical Implications (if any) of the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem by Peter Hollo The Philosophical Implications (if any) of the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem by A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF Advanced Science/Arts UNSW 1996 i UNSW Abstract

More information

The Fruits of Logicism

The Fruits of Logicism The Fruits of Logicism Timothy Bays 1. Introduction. You ll be pleased to know that I don t intend to use these remarks to comment on all of the papers presented at this conference. I won t try to show

More information

Clock Arithmetic and Modular Systems Clock Arithmetic The introduction to Chapter 4 described a mathematical system

Clock Arithmetic and Modular Systems Clock Arithmetic The introduction to Chapter 4 described a mathematical system CHAPTER Number Theory FIGURE FIGURE FIGURE Plus hours Plus hours Plus hours + = + = + = FIGURE. Clock Arithmetic and Modular Systems Clock Arithmetic The introduction to Chapter described a mathematical

More information

Continued Fractions and the Euclidean Algorithm

Continued Fractions and the Euclidean Algorithm Continued Fractions and the Euclidean Algorithm Lecture notes prepared for MATH 326, Spring 997 Department of Mathematics and Statistics University at Albany William F Hammond Table of Contents Introduction

More information

Notes on Richard Dedekind s Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?

Notes on Richard Dedekind s Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? Notes on Richard Dedekind s Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? David E. Joyce, Clark University December 2005 Contents Introduction 2 I. Sets and their elements. 2 II. Functions on a set. 5 III. One-to-one

More information

Basic Set Theory. 1. Motivation. Fido Sue. Fred Aristotle Bob. LX 502 - Semantics I September 11, 2008

Basic Set Theory. 1. Motivation. Fido Sue. Fred Aristotle Bob. LX 502 - Semantics I September 11, 2008 Basic Set Theory LX 502 - Semantics I September 11, 2008 1. Motivation When you start reading these notes, the first thing you should be asking yourselves is What is Set Theory and why is it relevant?

More information

a 11 x 1 + a 12 x 2 + + a 1n x n = b 1 a 21 x 1 + a 22 x 2 + + a 2n x n = b 2.

a 11 x 1 + a 12 x 2 + + a 1n x n = b 1 a 21 x 1 + a 22 x 2 + + a 2n x n = b 2. Chapter 1 LINEAR EQUATIONS 1.1 Introduction to linear equations A linear equation in n unknowns x 1, x,, x n is an equation of the form a 1 x 1 + a x + + a n x n = b, where a 1, a,..., a n, b are given

More information

Math 223 Abstract Algebra Lecture Notes

Math 223 Abstract Algebra Lecture Notes Math 223 Abstract Algebra Lecture Notes Steven Tschantz Spring 2001 (Apr. 23 version) Preamble These notes are intended to supplement the lectures and make up for the lack of a textbook for the course

More information

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 10

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 10 CS 70 Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2009 Satish Rao, David Tse Note 10 Introduction to Discrete Probability Probability theory has its origins in gambling analyzing card games, dice,

More information

The Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic

The Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic The Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic 1 Introduction: Why this theorem? Why this proof? One of the purposes of this course 1 is to train you in the methods mathematicians use to prove mathematical statements,

More information

The Graphical Method: An Example

The Graphical Method: An Example The Graphical Method: An Example Consider the following linear program: Maximize 4x 1 +3x 2 Subject to: 2x 1 +3x 2 6 (1) 3x 1 +2x 2 3 (2) 2x 2 5 (3) 2x 1 +x 2 4 (4) x 1, x 2 0, where, for ease of reference,

More information

Math 3000 Section 003 Intro to Abstract Math Homework 2

Math 3000 Section 003 Intro to Abstract Math Homework 2 Math 3000 Section 003 Intro to Abstract Math Homework 2 Department of Mathematical and Statistical Sciences University of Colorado Denver, Spring 2012 Solutions (February 13, 2012) Please note that these

More information

Mathematical Methods of Engineering Analysis

Mathematical Methods of Engineering Analysis Mathematical Methods of Engineering Analysis Erhan Çinlar Robert J. Vanderbei February 2, 2000 Contents Sets and Functions 1 1 Sets................................... 1 Subsets.............................

More information

Turing Machines: An Introduction

Turing Machines: An Introduction CIT 596 Theory of Computation 1 We have seen several abstract models of computing devices: Deterministic Finite Automata, Nondeterministic Finite Automata, Nondeterministic Finite Automata with ɛ-transitions,

More information

1. Give the 16 bit signed (twos complement) representation of the following decimal numbers, and convert to hexadecimal:

1. Give the 16 bit signed (twos complement) representation of the following decimal numbers, and convert to hexadecimal: Exercises 1 - number representations Questions 1. Give the 16 bit signed (twos complement) representation of the following decimal numbers, and convert to hexadecimal: (a) 3012 (b) - 435 2. For each of

More information

An Introduction to Real Analysis. John K. Hunter. Department of Mathematics, University of California at Davis

An Introduction to Real Analysis. John K. Hunter. Department of Mathematics, University of California at Davis An Introduction to Real Analysis John K. Hunter Department of Mathematics, University of California at Davis Abstract. These are some notes on introductory real analysis. They cover the properties of the

More information

C H A P T E R Regular Expressions regular expression

C H A P T E R Regular Expressions regular expression 7 CHAPTER Regular Expressions Most programmers and other power-users of computer systems have used tools that match text patterns. You may have used a Web search engine with a pattern like travel cancun

More information

INDISTINGUISHABILITY OF ABSOLUTELY CONTINUOUS AND SINGULAR DISTRIBUTIONS

INDISTINGUISHABILITY OF ABSOLUTELY CONTINUOUS AND SINGULAR DISTRIBUTIONS INDISTINGUISHABILITY OF ABSOLUTELY CONTINUOUS AND SINGULAR DISTRIBUTIONS STEVEN P. LALLEY AND ANDREW NOBEL Abstract. It is shown that there are no consistent decision rules for the hypothesis testing problem

More information

Fundamentele Informatica II

Fundamentele Informatica II Fundamentele Informatica II Answer to selected exercises 1 John C Martin: Introduction to Languages and the Theory of Computation M.M. Bonsangue (and J. Kleijn) Fall 2011 Let L be a language. It is clear

More information

Arguments and Dialogues

Arguments and Dialogues ONE Arguments and Dialogues The three goals of critical argumentation are to identify, analyze, and evaluate arguments. The term argument is used in a special sense, referring to the giving of reasons

More information

ZORN S LEMMA AND SOME APPLICATIONS

ZORN S LEMMA AND SOME APPLICATIONS ZORN S LEMMA AND SOME APPLICATIONS KEITH CONRAD 1. Introduction Zorn s lemma is a result in set theory that appears in proofs of some non-constructive existence theorems throughout mathematics. We will

More information

Linear Algebra I. Ronald van Luijk, 2012

Linear Algebra I. Ronald van Luijk, 2012 Linear Algebra I Ronald van Luijk, 2012 With many parts from Linear Algebra I by Michael Stoll, 2007 Contents 1. Vector spaces 3 1.1. Examples 3 1.2. Fields 4 1.3. The field of complex numbers. 6 1.4.

More information

26 Integers: Multiplication, Division, and Order

26 Integers: Multiplication, Division, and Order 26 Integers: Multiplication, Division, and Order Integer multiplication and division are extensions of whole number multiplication and division. In multiplying and dividing integers, the one new issue

More information

Extension of measure

Extension of measure 1 Extension of measure Sayan Mukherjee Dynkin s π λ theorem We will soon need to define probability measures on infinite and possible uncountable sets, like the power set of the naturals. This is hard.

More information

The Chinese Remainder Theorem

The Chinese Remainder Theorem The Chinese Remainder Theorem Evan Chen evanchen@mit.edu February 3, 2015 The Chinese Remainder Theorem is a theorem only in that it is useful and requires proof. When you ask a capable 15-year-old why

More information

1 Definition of a Turing machine

1 Definition of a Turing machine Introduction to Algorithms Notes on Turing Machines CS 4820, Spring 2012 April 2-16, 2012 1 Definition of a Turing machine Turing machines are an abstract model of computation. They provide a precise,

More information

SECTION 10-2 Mathematical Induction

SECTION 10-2 Mathematical Induction 73 0 Sequences and Series 6. Approximate e 0. using the first five terms of the series. Compare this approximation with your calculator evaluation of e 0.. 6. Approximate e 0.5 using the first five terms

More information

SET-THEORETIC CONSTRUCTIONS OF TWO-POINT SETS

SET-THEORETIC CONSTRUCTIONS OF TWO-POINT SETS SET-THEORETIC CONSTRUCTIONS OF TWO-POINT SETS BEN CHAD AND ROBIN KNIGHT AND ROLF SUABEDISSEN Abstract. A two-point set is a subset of the plane which meets every line in exactly two points. By working

More information

Full and Complete Binary Trees

Full and Complete Binary Trees Full and Complete Binary Trees Binary Tree Theorems 1 Here are two important types of binary trees. Note that the definitions, while similar, are logically independent. Definition: a binary tree T is full

More information

Lecture 2: Universality

Lecture 2: Universality CS 710: Complexity Theory 1/21/2010 Lecture 2: Universality Instructor: Dieter van Melkebeek Scribe: Tyson Williams In this lecture, we introduce the notion of a universal machine, develop efficient universal

More information